Skip to main content

Bargaining in Philadelphia: Constitutional Games, Rational Law-Making, and Originalism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Exploring the Province of Legislation

Part of the book series: Legisprudence Library ((LEGIS,volume 9))

  • 209 Accesses

Abstract

This article explores a possible bargaining-based account of the U.S. Constitution and its impact on intention-based originalism. I argue that the bargaining approach leads to a characterization of original intent in terms of rules in equilibria. The adoption of the U.S. (Federal) Constitution is the institutional result of coordination among a plurality of State agents with opposed interests and political views. Game theory might offer a rational reconstruction of the constitution-making process: under the game-theoretic model, the Constitution is the product of a series of intentional actions performed by individual agents behaving mainly as selfish individuals or group utility maximizers. These agents operate within a specific institutional framework. Game theory saves the intuition that law-making at the constitutional method can be effectively understood as a rational process. What is more, it might justify an originalist method for constitutional interpretation: we shall interpret constitutional provisions in light of their underlying equilibria.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Möllers (2013), pp. 1 ff.

  2. 2.

    See generally Schapiro (2011).

  3. 3.

    See generally Atienza and Ruiz Manero (1996); Moreso 2009.

  4. 4.

    See generally Dworkin (1986).

  5. 5.

    See generally Rawls (1971).

  6. 6.

    Buchanan (1978), pp. 5 ff.

  7. 7.

    Heckathorn and Maser (1987), p. 143.

  8. 8.

    Hayek (1973).

  9. 9.

    Troper (2006), p. 78.

  10. 10.

    Elster (1995), p. 365.

  11. 11.

    Heckathorn and Maser (1987), pp. 142 ff.

  12. 12.

    Heckathorn and Maser (1987), p. 143.

  13. 13.

    Elster (2018), p. 216.

  14. 14.

    Elster (1995), p. 371.

  15. 15.

    Elster (2018), pp. 222 ff.

  16. 16.

    Elster (1995), p. 372, footnote 19.

  17. 17.

    Heckathorn and Maser (1987), p. 146.

  18. 18.

    Elster (1995), p. 374.

  19. 19.

    Elster (1979), Chapter II.

  20. 20.

    Elster (1995), p. 376; Elster (2018), pp. 207 ff.; Hume (1987).

  21. 21.

    Elster (1995), p. 377.

  22. 22.

    Elster (2018), p. 207.

  23. 23.

    Farrand (1911).

  24. 24.

    Roche (1961), pp. 799 ff.; McDonald (1979), Chapter 5.

  25. 25.

    Heckathorn and Maser (1987), p. 152. The proposals ranged from annual election to 20 years of mandate.

  26. 26.

    Farrand (1911), Vol. 1, pp. 196–202; Elster (1995), p. 375.

  27. 27.

    Farrand (1911), Vol. 1, p. 500. Gunning Bedford of Delaware declares: ‘I do not, gentlemen, trust you. If you possess the power, the abuse of it could not be checked; and what then would prevent you from exercising it to our destruction?’.

  28. 28.

    Elster (1995), p. 374.

  29. 29.

    Jillson and Eubanks (1984), p. 445 ff.; Farrand (1911), Vol. 1, p. 196.

  30. 30.

    Buchanan and Tullock (1962).

  31. 31.

    Beard (1986); McGuire (1988), pp. 483 ff.

  32. 32.

    Elster (1995), p. 388.

  33. 33.

    Elster (1995), pp. 384, 390.

  34. 34.

    Beard (1986), pp. 16–18.

  35. 35.

    Elkins and McKittrick (1961), pp. 181 ff.; Rutland (1966).

  36. 36.

    Lee (1960); Schuyler (1961), pp. 73–80.

  37. 37.

    McGuire (1988), pp. 504 ff. Under this model, a vote is conceived as a double function: a function of the economic interests and ideologies of the delegate (Vi = f (DE, DI)), and a function of the economic interests and ideologies of his constituents (Vi = f (CE, CI), where Vi is a dummy variable representing a delegate’s vote on issue I, limited to yes = 1 OR no = 0; DE is the set of variables measuring personal economic interests, DI is the set of variables measuring personal ideology, CE is the set of variables proxying his constituents’ economic interests, and CI the set of variables proxying the constituents’ ideology). The delegates to the Philadelphia convention acted as utility maximizers concerned with their future and personal ambition, as the statistical correlation between the probable votes expressed on specific vital issues (national veto, interstate commerce, and slavery, to name only a few) and the marginal effect of units changes in a particular independent variable suggests. The possibility of testing voting preferences is limited, both for conceptual and contingent reasons: as a conceptual reason, strategic bargaining and logrolling tend to obscure the actual vote patterns; the Philadelphia Convention operated under a secrecy principle, and the voting procedure was recorded only in part.

  38. 38.

    Jillson (1981), pp. 598–612; Jillson and Eubanks (1984), pp. 435–458; Riker (1984), pp. 1–16.

  39. 39.

    Farrand (1911) Vol. 1, 86 ff.; Jillson and Eubanks (1984), p. 439.

  40. 40.

    Finkelman (2014).

  41. 41.

    Farrand (1911), Vol. 1, 164 ff.

  42. 42.

    Elster (1993).

  43. 43.

    McGuire (1988), p. 491.

  44. 44.

    Wood (1980), p. 8; Beard (1912), pp. 80f.

  45. 45.

    Buchanan and Tullock (1962) 79 ff.

  46. 46.

    See also Riker (1986).

  47. 47.

    Nash (1950a, b, 1951).

  48. 48.

    Elster (1995), p. 393.

  49. 49.

    Frohlich and Oppenheimer (1984), pp. 3 ff.

  50. 50.

    Roche (1961), pp. 804.

  51. 51.

    Jillson and Eubanks (1984), pp. 435 ff.

  52. 52.

    Jillson and Eubanks (1984), pp. 438 ff. The higher-level of constitutional-making comprises ‘general questions concerning the scope, scale, and form appropriate to government. Will the regime be an aristocratic, democratic, or mixed republic? Will the government have a legislative or an executive focus? Will its legislature be bicameral or unicameral?’. According to Jillson and Eubanks, these questions are ‘less likely to be decided with reference to economic status, social role, or material characteristics of the constitution maker than with reference to his philosophical assumption concerning the interplay among human nature, political institutions, and the good society’.

  53. 53.

    Neumann and Morgenstern (1953). A utility function U: P → ℜ is a von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function if there are numbers (u1, …, un) for each of the N outcomes (x1, …, xn) such that for every p ∈ P, U (p) = Pn i = 1 piui. The expected utility function is a way of incorporating in the model a theory of behavior towards risk variance. Under the condition of risk variance, the optimal choice maximizes expected utility, which is given by combining the pertinent utilities and their associated probabilities. The decision maker’s preferences are pinned down over uncertain outcomes.

  54. 54.

    Shapley (1953), pp. 1095 ff.; Mertens and Neyman (1981), p. 53 ff.; Baron and Ferejohn (1989), p. 1181 ff.

  55. 55.

    Bicchieri (1997), p. 2.

  56. 56.

    Binmore (2007), p. 37.

  57. 57.

    Mashaw (1989), pp. 123 ff.

  58. 58.

    Bacharach (2006), p. 163: ‘in coming to frame a situation as a problem ‘for us’, an individual also gains some sense of how likely it is that another individual would frame it in the same way’.

  59. 59.

    Nash (1950a, b, 1951).

  60. 60.

    Binmore (2007), p. 14.

  61. 61.

    Binmore (2007), p. 57.

  62. 62.

    Börgers (1992), p. 163 ff.

  63. 63.

    Aumann (1995), p. 6 ff.; Neumann and Morgenstern (1953).

  64. 64.

    Schelling (1960).

  65. 65.

    Lewis (1969).

  66. 66.

    Binmore (2007), p. 45.

  67. 67.

    McGuire (1988), p. 506.

  68. 68.

    Miller and Knapp (1977), pp. 367 ff.

  69. 69.

    Karp (2016).

  70. 70.

    Jillson and Eubanks (1984), p. 440.

  71. 71.

    Jillson and Eubanks (1984), p. 452; Farrand (1911), Vol. 2, pp. 451–461.

  72. 72.

    Rosenthal (1981), pp. 92 ff.

  73. 73.

    Brest (1980).

  74. 74.

    60 U.S. 393 (1857).

  75. 75.

    199 U.S. 437 (1905).

  76. 76.

    Scalia (1997), p. 22.

  77. 77.

    Brest (1980), pp. 214 ff.; Bennett (1984), p. 456.

  78. 78.

    Lawson and Siedman (2008), p. 73; Barnett (1999), p. 621.

  79. 79.

    Bickel (1986).

  80. 80.

    Bobbitt (1982), p. 26.

  81. 81.

    Elster (2018), pp. 235 ff.

References

  • Atienza M, Ruiz Manero J (1996) Las Piezas del Derecho. Ariel, Barcelona

    Google Scholar 

  • Aumann RJ (1995) Backward induction and common knowledge of rationality. GEB 8(1):6–19

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacharach M (2006) Beyond individual choice. Teams and frames in game theory. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barnett RA (1999) An originalism for nonoriginalists. Loyola Law Rev 45:661–654

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron DP, Ferejohn JA (1989) A model for multilateral bargaining. Am Polit Sci Rev 83(4):1181–1206

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beard CA (1912) The Supreme Court and the constitution. McMillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Beard CA (1986) An economic interpretation of the constitution of the United States (1913). Free Press, University of Michigan

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett RW (1984) Objectivity in constitutional law. U Pa Law Rev 132:445–496

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bicchieri C (1997) Rationality and coordination. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickel A (1986) The least dangerous branch. The Supreme Court at the bar of politics, 2nd edn. Yale University Press, New Heaven

    Google Scholar 

  • Binmore K (2007) Game theory. A very short introduction. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bobbitt P (1982) Constitutional fate. Theory of the constitution. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Börgers T (1992) Iterated elimination of dominated strategies in a Bertrand-Edgeworth model. Rev Econ Stud 59(1):163–176

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brest P (1980) The misconceived quest for the original understanding. Bost Univ Law Rev 60:204–238

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan JM (1978) The limits of liberty. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan JM, Tullock G (1962) The calculus of consent: logical foundations of constitutional democracy. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1986) Law’s empire. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Elkins S, McKittrick E (1961) The founding fathers: young men of the revolution. Polit Sci Q 76:181–216

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster J (1979) Ulysses and the Sirens. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster J (1993) Bargaining over the presidency. East Eur Const Rev 2(4)/3(1):95–98

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster J (1995) Forces and mechanisms in the constitution-making process. Duke Law J 45:364–396

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster J (2018) The political psychology of constitution making. In: Elster J, Gargarella R, Vatsal N, Bjorn ER (eds) Constituent assemblies. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 207–247

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Farrand M (1911) The records of the Philadelphia convention of 1787. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Finkelman P (2014) Slavery and the founders, 3rd edn. Routledge, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frohlich N, Oppenheimer J (1984) Beyond economic man. J Confl Resolut 28:3–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek FA (1973) Law, legislation, and liberty. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Heckathorn DD, Maser SM (1987) Bargaining and constitutional contracts. AJPS 31(1):142–168

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1987) Essays: moral, political, literary (1777). Liberty Fund, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Jillson C (1981) Constitution-making: alignment and realignment in the federal convention of 1787. Am Polit Sci Rev 75:598–612

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jillson CC, Eubanks CL (1984) The political structure of constitution-making: the federal convention of 1787. AJPS 28(3):435–458

    Google Scholar 

  • Karp M (2016) This Vast Southern Empire. Slaveholders at the Helm of American Foreign Policy. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lawson G, Siedman G (2008) Originalism as a legal enterprise. Const Commun 23:47–80

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee B (1960) Turner and Beard: American historical writing reconsidered. Free Press, Glencoe

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis DK (1969) Convention. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mashaw JL (1989) The economics of politics and the understanding of public law. Chicago-Kent Law Rev 65:123–160

    Google Scholar 

  • McDonald F (1979) E Pluribus Unum. Liberty Press, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • McGuire RA (1988) Constitution making: a rational model of the federal convention of 1787. AJPS 32(2):483–522

    Google Scholar 

  • Mertens JF, Neyman A (1981) Stochastic games. Int J Game Theory 10(2):53–66

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller AS, Knapp GM (1977) The congressional veto: preserving the constitutional framework. Ind Law J 52(2):367–395

    Google Scholar 

  • Möllers C (2013) The three branches: a comparative model of separation of powers. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moreso JJ (2009) La Constitución: Modelo para Armar. Marcial Pons, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Nash J (1950a) Two persons cooperative games. U.S. Air Force Project Rand. P-172. Santa Monica

    Google Scholar 

  • Nash J (1950b) The bargaining problem. Econometrica 18(2):155–162

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nash J (1951) Non-cooperative games. Ann Math 54(2):286–295

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neumann JV, Morgenstern O (1953) Theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1971) A theory of justice. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Riker WH (1984) The heresthetics of constitution making: the presidency in 1787, with comments on determinism and rational choice. Am Polit Sci Rev 78:1–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riker WH (1986) The art of political manipulation. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Roche J (1961) The founding fathers: a reform caucus in action. Am Polit Sci Rev 65:799–816

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal RW (1981) Games of perfect information, predatory pricing, and the chain store. J Econ Theory 25(1):92–100

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rutland RA (1966) The ordeal of the constitution: the antifederalist and the ratification struggle of 1787–1788. University of Oklahoma Press, Norman

    Google Scholar 

  • Scalia A (1997) A matter of interpretation. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Schapiro S (2011) Legality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling T (1960) The strategy of conflict. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuyler RL (1961) Forrest MacDonald’s critique of the beard thesis. South Hist 27:73–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapley LS (1953) Stochastic games. PNAS 39(10):1095–1100

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Troper M (2006) Terminer la Révolution: La Constitution de 1795. Fayard, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood G (1980) Democracy and the constitution. In: Goldwin RA, Schambra WA (eds) How democratic is the constitution? American Enterprise Institute, Washington DC

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The Author remains grateful to the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation for sponsoring this research, which is part of a larger project hosted by the University of Heidelberg, Institut für Staatsrecht, Verfassungslehre und Rechtsphilosophie. The Author wishes to express his gratitude to his host, Professor Martin Borowski, for his precious support. Special thanks go to Mauro Barberis, Paolo Comanducci, Pierluigi Chiassoni, Francesco Ferraro, Daniel Oliver Lalana, and Jan R. Sieckmann for their valuable suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alessio Sardo .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Sardo, A. (2022). Bargaining in Philadelphia: Constitutional Games, Rational Law-Making, and Originalism. In: Ferraro, F., Zorzetto, S. (eds) Exploring the Province of Legislation. Legisprudence Library, vol 9. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-87262-5_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-87262-5_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-87261-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-87262-5

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics