Skip to main content

Chapter 5: The Abandonment of Business Codes of Ethics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Business Ethics: Kant, Virtue, and the Nexus of Duty

Abstract

Avoidance of well established ethical business-codes currently continues as a prime societal problem. Examples of proper business codes of ethics, ones that are consistent with Kant’s (1996) categorical imperative, are reviewed, but these codes have a tendency to be ignored for reasons inherent to competitive firms. These inherent reasons are examined in the context of Arendt’s (Thinking and Moral Considerations, 1971; Responsibility and Judgment, 2003) theory of why ethical codes are abandoned. Svendsen’s Philosophy of Evil (2001) is shown to provide insights relevant for preserving these codes. In addition, the evidence from recent experimental psychology is shown to reinforce these devolution theories posed by Arendt and Svendsen.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Forward contracts are merely signed commitments for future delivery or purchase. Futures contracts are forward contracts traded on organized exchanges. For Enron, these contracts involved energy, electric power and natural gas.

References

  • Alicke, M.D. 1985. Global Self Evaluation as Determined by the Desirability and Controllability of Trait Adjectives. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 49 (6): 1621–1630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Annas, Julia. 1993. The Morality of Happiness. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquino, K., and A. Reed. 2002. The self Importance of Moral Identity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 83 (6): 1423–1440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aquino, K., A. Reed, S. Thau, and D. Freeman. 2007. A Grotesque and Dark Beauty: How Moral Identity and Mechanisms of Moral Disengagement Influence Cognitive and Emotional Reactions to War. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 43: 385–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1951. The Origins of Totalitarianism. Orlando, Florida: Harcourt, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1963. Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil. Viking Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1971. Thinking and Moral Considerations. Harcourt, Brace and Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1978. The Life of the Mind. Orlando, FL: Harcourt, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Thinking and Moral Considerations. In Responsibility and Judgment, ed. Jerome Kohn. New York, NY: Schocken Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bandura, A. 1990. Selective Activation and Disengagement of Moral Control. Journal of Social Issues 46: 27–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Moral Disengagement in the Preparation of Inhumanities. Personal and Social Psychology Review 3: 193–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bandura, A., B. Underwood, and M.E. Fromson. 1975. Disinhibition of Aggression Through Diffusion of Responsibility and Dehumanization of Victims. Journal of Research in Personality 9: 253–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bandura, A., C. Barbaranelli, G. Capara, and C. Pastorelli. 1996. Mechanisms of Moral Disengagement in the Exercise of Moral Agency. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 71: 364–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bandura, A., C. Barbaranelli, G. Capara, C. Pastorelli, and C. Regalia. 2001. Sociocognitive Self-Regulatory Mechanisms Governing Transgressive Behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 80: 125–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister, R.F., and T.F. Heatherton. 1996. Self Regulation Failure: An Overview. Psychological Inquiry 7: 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister, R.F., L. Newman, S. 1994. Self-Regulation of Cognitive Inference and Decision Processes. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 20: 3–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonhoeffer, Dietrich. 1997. Letters and Papers from Prison. Trans. Reginald Fuller, Frank Clark, et al. New York, NY: Simon & Shuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Detert, J.R., L.K. Trevino, and V.L. Sweitzer. 2008. Moral Disengagement in Ethical Decision Making: A Study of Antecedents and Outcomes. Journal of Applied Psychology 93 (2): 374–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliot, A.J., and P.G. Devine. 1994. On the Motivational Nature of Cognitive Dissonance: Dissonance as Psychological Discomfort. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 67: 382–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epley, N., and E.M. Caruso. 2004. Egocentric Ethics. Social Justice Research 17: 171–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epley, N., and D. Dunning. 2000. Feeling “Holier than Thou”: Are Self Serving Assessments Produced by Errors in Self- or Social-Prediction. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 71: 364–374.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gino, F., S. Ayal, and D. Ariely. 2009a. Contagion and Differentiation in Unethical Behavior: The Effect of One Bad Apple on the Barrel. Psychological Science 20 (3): 393–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gino, F., Ayal S., and Pierce, L. 2009b. The Abundance Effect: Unethical Behavior in the Presence of Wealth. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 109 (2): 142–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gourevitch, Phillip. 1998. We Wish to Inform You that Tomorrow We Will Be Killed With Our Families: Stories from Rwanda. New York, NY: Farrar, Strauss and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henkel, L.A., and M. Mather. 2007. Memory Attributions for Choices: How Beliefs Shape Our Memories. Journal of Memory and Language 57: 163–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1785. Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals. In Basic Writings of Kant, ed. Allen W. Wood. New York: The Modern Library Classics, The Modern Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazar, N., O. Amir, and D. Ariely. 2008. The Dishonesty of Honest People: A Theory of Self-Concept Maintenance. Journal of Marketing Research 45 (6).

    Google Scholar 

  • McAlister, A.L., A. Bandura, and S. Owen. 2006. Mechanisms of Moral Disengagement in Support of Military Force: The Impact of Sept. 11. Journal of Clinical and Social Psychology 25: 141–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Messick, D.M., and M.H. Bazerman. 1996. Ethical Leadership and the Psychology of Decision Making. Sloan Management Review: 9–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Messick, D.M., S. Bloom, J.P. Boldizar, and C.D. Samuelson. 1985. Why We are Fairer than Others. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 21: 480–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D.T., and R.K. Ratner. 1998. The Disparity between the Actual and Assumed Power of Self Interest. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 74 (1): 53–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratner, R.K., and D.T. Miller. 2001. The Norm of Self Interest and its Effects on Social Action. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 81 (1): 5–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shu, L. et al. 2012. Signing at the Beginning Makes Ethics Salient. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 109 (38): 15197.

    Google Scholar 

  • Svendsen, Lars. 2001. A Philosophy of Evil. London: Dalkey Archive Press. First English Translation, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vollum, S., J. Buffington-Vollum, and D.R. Longmire. 2004. Moral Disengagement and Attitudes about Violence toward Nonhuman Animals. Society and Animals 12: 2009–2235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Supplementary Readings

  • Annas (1993) presents the most comprehensive review of virtue ethics. It is a lengthy book that is nonetheless accessible to the reader.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Appendix: Enron as an Example

Appendix: Enron as an Example

Enron presented one of the major accounting scandals of the early years of this century. Enron began as an energy company in 1985, but it largely grew to become an energy trading company, trading in futures and forward contracts.Footnote 1 By 2001, Enron was the world’s largest energy trading companies through holding 25 percent of all energy contracts. It claimed $40 billion in revenue in 1998, $60 billion in 2000, and $101 billion in 2000. Its stated goal was to grow revenue by 15 percent per year.

Enron’s ethical conflicts concerned five significant issues:

  1. 1.

    Its use of mark-to-market accounting practices, although perhaps conforming with FASB rules, were deceptive as to its real cash revenues.

  2. 2.

    It used numerous (about 3000 transactions) off-the-book special purpose entities (SPEs) such as limited partnerships and limited liability companies, that it ostensibly only partly owned, but in fact fully controlled, to remove liabilities off its balance sheet, although it still owed these obligations. There were almost 900 of these SPEs.

  3. 3.

    The SPEs were owned and controlled by officers of Enron, who personally benefitted from these subsidiaries although this involved conflicts of interest that violated Enron’s stated ethics code.

  4. 4.

    Enron sought to coerce its auditing company (Arthur Anderson and Co.) into not revealing its accounting manipulations.

  5. 5.

    When questions were raised about its accounting irregularities, and the conflicts of interests of executives with the SPEs, Enron sought to publicly humiliate its dissenters.

FASB Rule 125 allowed companies to sign contracts for future delivery of some good, and at a stated price, and to book this future income as current income (mark-to-market). If the price drops between the date of signing the contract and fulfillment date, the company can book this as a positive revenue even though it has yet to be actually received. According to mark-to-market, if the price increases, a loss should be booked. Enron merely entered positive revenues, and had its SPEs book its losing contracts. According to FASB 125, as long as the SPE owned at least 51 percent outside ownership, then Enron need not book this transaction on its own books. Most of these SPEs’ were registered as Cayman Island companies where the other owners were executives of Enron, either Chairman Kenneth Lay, or CEO Jeffrey Skillings or CFO Andrew Fastow. With limited liability in effect, these SPEs (881 in total by 2002) involved no personal losses for these executives.

This practice, since it was so large in effect, although within the letter of the FASB code, it clearly violated the spirit of accounting practice since the performance and health of Enron was hidden. This practice was deceptive to its core. This allowed Enron to book deceptive positive revenues so that performance objectives could be consistently met. Executive bonuses depended upon meeting these performance objectives of 15 percent growth per year in revenues.

Enron’s Code of Ethics addressed the issue of conflicts of interest in two sections. The first stated that, “An employee shall not conduct himself or herself in a manner which directly or indirectly would be detrimental to the best interests of the company or in a manner which would bring to the employee financial gain separately derived as a direct consequence of his or her employment with the company.” The code also continued to state, “….it follows that no full time officer or employee should: (c) Own an interest in or participate, directly or indirectly, in the profits of another entity which does business with or is a competitor of the company unless such ownership or participation has been previously disclosed in writing to the Chairman of the Board and Chief Executive Officer of Enron Corp., and such officer has determined that such interest or participation does not adversely affect the best interests of the Company.” The Board waived this policy for Andrew Fastow on three occasions.

In 1999, Arthur Anderson, Enron’s auditor, led by the Enron Account Executive David Duncan, initially questioned these SPE arrangements, calling them “form over substance transactions.” Pressure by Enron on its auditor, however, eliminated further questions about this practice.

Several analysts who questioned the accuracy of Enron’s reported accounting numbers were publicly attacked. For example, a reported for Fortune, Bethany McClean questioned Enron’s profits given its large off-balance-sheet transactions led to Ken Lay calling her editor to ask that she be removed from the story. During an analyst interview, Jeffrey Skillings called Ms. McClean an unrepeatable derogatory name. Also, when John Olson, and analyst for Merrill Lynch questioned advised his clients to avoid Enron due to their questionable earnings, he was fired. Enron was a client of Merrill Lynch. Internal employees were given the same treatment. When Sherron Watkins, was Vice President for Corporate Development questioned the off-the-books transactions, and consequential true debt load of Enron, Mr. Fastow accused her of wanting his job. She was fired. Other employees who questioned Enron executives were also fired and humiliated.

Enron’s stated policy was to eliminate underperforming employees. Of course, the executives decided the criteria for this performance. Approximately 20 percent were fired each year from 1998 through 2001. The culture of conformance was no doubt strengthened as a result.

In the end, Andrew Fastow stated in court, “Within the culture of corruption that Enron had, that valued financial reporting rather than economic value, I believed I was a hero.” Perhaps we can perceive Svendsen’s steps of devolution in the Enron story:

  1. 1.

    No doubt the off-balance-sheet transactions were minor at first, but they grew to be $25 billion out of the $38 billion in actual debt that Enron had in 2002. Violations of the spirit of accounting codes, and its own internal Code of Ethics were accepted by all including the Board, and escalated over 1999 through 2002.

  2. 2.

    Dissent was minor until the end when strong statements of regret were made. Dissenters were consistently humiliated until the end.

  3. 3.

    Leaders in this devolution saw themselves as heroic.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Robinson, R.M. (2022). Chapter 5: The Abandonment of Business Codes of Ethics. In: Business Ethics: Kant, Virtue, and the Nexus of Duty. Springer Texts in Business and Economics. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-85997-8_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics