Skip to main content
  • 101 Accesses

Abstract

The high bar that Aristotle sets for judicious deliberation creates difficulties for his political theory. If a judicious deliberator must be virtuous in order to be able understand the chief end for humans and to deliberate well (see above, Chap. 4), political deliberation faces severe challenges in most cities that do not have the requisite number of virtuous citizens. Worse still, no deliberation is possible without a common goal and most cities are divided between the rich and the poor with very different ideas of the goal of political activity. As with his other studies, other difficulties emerge from Aristotle’s survey of the reputable opinions (henceforth, RO), but these difficulties are not merely theoretical because some of the ROs surveyed represent firmly held opinions of political participants for which the judicious legislator needs to account. For example, in Politics 3, Aristotle considers the competing claims of the few or the many to rule. These represent the opinions held by the rich and the poor (Pol. 3.9, 1280a22–5) who are the key parts of most cities that the judicious legislator needs to accommodate to have any hope of attaining civil peace.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Robinson (1962, p. ix) expresses the common view that the Politics is not a united treatise: “The fact is, probably, that the Politics is a collection of long essays and brief jottings pretending to be a treatise.”

    Lord (2013, p. xxv) and Simpson (1998, p. xvii) see the Politics as unified but do not explain its unity in terms of its central pros hen analogy.

  2. 2.

    Jaeger (1948, p. 273) argues that books 2, 3, 7 & 8 of the Politics represent an earlier “utopian” approach and that books 4–6 are a later insertion of “purely empirical” material.

  3. 3.

    For good reasons for skepticism regarding the developmental approach in Jaeger and in general, see Barnes (1995, pp. 16–22).

  4. 4.

    Note that the sentences are not identical, which tells against a purely mechanical explanation such as Richard Kraut’s. Kraut (2002, pp. 188–9) argues that the last sentence of Book 3 enters from a shorter edition omitting books 4–6, so there is no need to change the order of the books. His hypothesis does not explain the verbal differences between the sentences.

  5. 5.

    Simpson (1998, p. 194) tries to overcome the problem by reading it as a complete sentence, filling in an implicit reference to the preceding sentence, “Anyone, then, who is going to do this [namely, speak about the best regime] must conduct the examination that is proper to the subject.” Besides resulting in rather anodyne advice, the reconstruction does not work grammatically because Simpson has introduced two verbs (“do” & “conduct”) to complete the two auxiliaries (“going to” & “must”) in the sentence, where the Greek has only one verb poiēsasthai. Poiēsasthai is governed by mellonta leaving anagkē without a verb to govern.

  6. 6.

    As Kraut (2002, pp. 185–6) notes, the Politics builds from the less to the more perfect.

  7. 7.

    See also Robert Bartlett (1994, pp. 387–8); Carrie-Anne Biondi (2007, p. 181); Suzanne Stern-Gillet (1995, p. 156); Thanassis Samaras (2007, p. 79); Waller Newell (1991, p. 194).

  8. 8.

    See Pierre Aubenque (1993, p. 264); Michel Narcy (1993, p. 271); Clifford Bates (2003, p. 212); Stephen Everson (1988, p. 90).

  9. 9.

    Ober (2005, p. 234) calls Aristotle’s ideal state an “aristocratic democracy.” Keyt (1991, p. 257, n. 43) claims, “‘the one constitution that is best’ is a genus whose species are absolute kingship and true aristocracy,” 257 n. 43. Keyt’s view is endorsed by Fred Miller, Jr. (1995, p. 193). Wilson (2011, p. 268) says the best regime is an aristocracy with features of a polity.

  10. 10.

    See also, Bates (2003, pp. 213–14); Kraut (2002, p. 358); Coby (1986, p.487); Lindsay (1992, p. 103).

  11. 11.

    Contrary to Saxonhouse (1996, p. 130) who argues that Aristotle leaves behind the competing claims to rule to focus on the preservation of regimes. The two questions can hardly be separated. As Aristotle says, “It is difficult for a constitution to remain if it is founded on something other than justice” (Pol. 7.14, 1332b27–9).

    The issue of just rule remains central throughout. Aristotle’s discussion of the preservation of regimes in Politics 5 prioritizes conflicting claims to just rule as being the universal cause of revolution (Pol. 5.2, 1302a23–4). He seeks to balance the conflicting claims in his discussion of the middle regime (Pol. 4.11, 1296a7–9) and returns to the question of just rule in Politics 7.14 (1332b27–38).

  12. 12.

    The analysis here focuses on the outline of the questions in Politics 4.2. By contrast Frede (2005, p. 168) draws the main questions from Politics 4.1. She lists the best states as “the best state that one could wish or pray for;” the best ‘under given conditions;’ and the best “under special circumstances.” She omits the best state generally, which Aristotle mentions both in 4.1 (1288b33–5) and 4.2 (1289b14–17) and includes the best ex hupotheseōs, which is included in 4.1 (1288b28) but not in 4.2 and only briefly at the end of 4.11 (1296b9–10).

    The list of questions in 4.2 better tracks with what follows in Politics 4 & 5, whereas the list in 4.1 is part of a more general discussion of the various senses of “the best” in the comparison between the legislator and the trainer.

  13. 13.

    Contrary to Roochnik (2008, p. 714) who argues that in Politics 7, Aristotle defends contemplation as the best life. Illustrative of Roochnik’s approach, he argues that Politics 7.2 shows that the political life is not best, and therefore the theoretical life is (p. 723). This is a false dichotomy because it ignores the possibility of a complete life that includes both political activity and contemplation.

  14. 14.

    So also, Solmsen (1964, pp. 216–17). Vander Waerdt (1985, p. 252) argues that the citizens of the CP avoid politics. By contrast, Alexander (2000, p. 209) claims they are active gentleman and not contemplative.

  15. 15.

    So also, Francisco Lisi (2014, p. 263).

  16. 16.

    Cherry (2009, p. 1418) notes the connection between leisure and political activity; cf. Kraut (2002, p. 200); cf. Frede (2019, pp. 498–500).

  17. 17.

    Resolving the debate between the “inclusive” versus “dominant” interpretations of the human good would require a careful analysis of Nicomachean Ethics 10.7–8 and is beyond the scope of the present study. For our purposes, we are not assuming that the Nicomachean Ethics and Politics present identical views of happiness, so even if the Nicomachean Ethics teaches the dominant version of happiness, that does not mean that the Politics does. For the contrasting interpretations of happiness, see Hardie (1965, p. 279); see also Frede (2019, 484–8) who points out several incongruities between the discussion of happiness in Nicomachean Ethics 10.7–8 and the rest of the Nicomachean Ethics . This is a further indication that one cannot simply import a dominant interpretation of Nicomachean Ethics 10.7 into the reading of Politics 7, as Lord and Roochnik do.

    For a recent review of the literature on happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics , see Roche (2014).

  18. 18.

    As Kraut (2002, p. 225) indicates, inferences can also be drawn from his discussions from earlier books of the Politics.

  19. 19.

    See also, Schütrumpf (2005, 110, n. 5) for a discussion of Aristotle’s refined definition of aristocracy.

  20. 20.

    Cf. Ober (1998, p. 11); Preus (2012, 35). Kraut (2002, p. 360) identifies the CP as a polity.

  21. 21.

    Pellegrin (1996, p. 349) argues that the CP is “prepolitical” because it does not determine a constitutional form. Pellegrin ignores the fact that all the elderly participate in a deliberative assembly, see above.

  22. 22.

    Aristotle never precisely defines what he means by the middle class.

    According to Woods (2014, p. 411) it is the hoplites.

    However, the best indication occurs in 6.5, 1320a32–b1, quoted and discussed below, in which he recommends moving citizens out of poverty by making them economically independent.

    This is consistent with several studies. Markle (1985, p. 268, n. 7) notes, “The basic meaning of a-poros [i.e. poor] is ‘without sufficient property to serve the polis’.” Cf. Nagle (2006).

    See also, Ober (1991, p. 119) who identifies the middle with those with sufficient means “to avoid the necessity of manual labor.”

  23. 23.

    Frank (2005, p. 164) argues that the middle polity is no more achievable than the CP because in most cities there are few in the middle class. This certainly reflects Aristotle’s view of the state of most cities (Pol. 4.11, 1296a23–4), but ignores the steps that Aristotle says a legislator should take to grow the middle class, see below.

  24. 24.

    Johnson (1988, p. 199); Creed (1989, pp. 23–4); Lane (2014, p. 206).

  25. 25.

    Miller (1995, p. 255).

  26. 26.

    Miller (1995, p. 268) argues that the arguments for the virtue of the middle class are “unsubstantiated.” It is better to look at his arguments as not meant to establish the virtue of the middle class in a general sense, but to argue that their experience in ruling and being ruled prepares them to be good citizens.

  27. 27.

    In Eudemian Ethics 7.4, Aristotle does discuss the friendship between non-equals, but denies that the pair are friends (1239a4–5). They are not both friends because the relationship is one-sided and the inferior loves the superior, but not vice versa (6–8). In any case, political friendship is a friendship of equals (Eth. Eud. 7.10, 1242b21–2).

  28. 28.

    According to Bickford (1996, p. 410), “Deliberation is a practice that can enable citizens who do not perceive themselves to have substantive common interests, and are not bound by friendship, to interact politically.” This is contrary to Aristotle’s theory of deliberation, which requires a shared end (see above, Chap. 4). Deliberation is not an alternative to political friendship as Bickford claims. Political friendship serves as the basis for political deliberation in the middle polity because the mutual recognition of ends in political friendship supplies the common ends needed for political deliberation. Alternatively, the poor and rich can be numerically balanced in the deliberative body (Pol. 4.14, 1298b25–6), but as will be seen below, such a balance is inherently unstable.

    Yack (1993, p. 238) suggests that Aristotle expects the middle class “to be much more open to recognizing the relevance of both egalitarian and inegalitarian principles of justice.” However, Aristotle never says as much. Instead, he emphasizes that they do not have so little as to desire the property of others (1295b29–30). This is an economic consideration, not relying on the ability of the middle class to consider principles of justice or to place themselves in the minds of others.

  29. 29.

    Yack (1993, p. 114) understands political friendship is a friendship of utility. So also, Mayhew (1997, pp. 79–82); Leontsini (2013, p. 26); Jenkins (1999, pp. 468–9); Miller (1995, pp.135–6).

    By contrast, Schollmeier (1994, pp. 83–4) takes it to be virtue-based friendship. So also, Kronman (1979, p. 129).

    Alternatively, Yack (1999) classifies political friendship as a combination of a friendship of utility and a friendship of virtue.

  30. 30.

    For further analysis, see Yack (1993, pp. 235–6).

    As Skultety (2009, p. 357) points out, stasis in the Politics refers to civil war, not mere factionalism.

  31. 31.

    The translation of geōrgia as independent farming is meant to reflect the status of a georgos as a “middling farmer;” see Hanson (1999).

    On the importance of middle-class farmers to Athenian democracy, see Hampus Lyttkens (2013, p. 63).

References

  • Alexander, Liz Anne. 2000. The Best Regimes of Aristotle’s Politics. History of Political Thought 21: 189–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aubenque, Pierre. 1993. Aristote et la démocratie. In Aristote politique: Études sur la Politique d’ Aristote, ed. Pierre Aubenque and Alonso Tordesillas, 255–264. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, Jonathan. 1995. Life and Work. In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle, ed. Jonathan Barnes, 1–26. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartlett, Robert. 1994. The ‘Realism’ of Classical Political Science. American Journal of Political Science 38: 381–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bates, Clifford, Jr. 2003. Aristotle’s “Best Regime:” Kingship, Democracy, and the Rule of Law. Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickford, Susan. 1996. Beyond Friendship: Aristotle on Conflict, Deliberation, and Attention. Journal of Politics 58: 398–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biondi, Carrie-Anne. 2007. Aristotle on the Mixed Constitution and Its Relevance for American Political Thought. Social Philosophy and Policy 24: 176–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cherry, Kevin. 2009. The Problem of Polity: Political Participation and Aristotle’s Best Regime. Journal of Politics 71: 1406–1421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coby, Patrick. 1986. Aristotle’s Four Conceptions of Politics. Western Political Quarterly 39: 480–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, John. 1987. Contemplation and Happiness: A Reconsideration. Synthese 72: 187–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Creed, John. 1989. Aristotle’s Middle Constitution. Polis 8: 2–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Everson, Stephen. 1988. Aristotle on the Foundations of the State. Political Studies 36: 89–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank, Jill. 2005. A Democracy of Distinction: Aristotle and the Work of Politics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frede, Dorothea. 2005. Citizenship in Aristotle’s Politics. In Aristotle’s Politics: Critical Essays, ed. Richard Kraut and Steven Skultety, 167–184. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2019. New Perspectives on an Old Controversy: The Theoretical and the Practical Life in Aristotle. Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung 73: 481–510.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hampus Lyttkens, Carl. 2013. Economic Analysis of Institutional Change in Ancient Greece: Politics, Taxation, and Rational Behaviour. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, Victor. 1999. The Other Greeks: The Family Farm and the Agrarian Roots of Western Civilization. 2nd ed. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardie, William. 1965. The Final Good in Aristotle’s Ethics. Philosophy 40 (154): 277–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaeger, Warner. 1948. Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of His Development, 2nd ed. Translated by Richard Robinson. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, Joyce. 1999. The Advantages of Civic Friendship. Journal of Philosophical Research 24: 459–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Curtis. 1988. Aristotle’s Polity: Mixed or Middle Constitution? History of Political Thought 9: 189–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990. Aristotle’s Theory of the State. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Keyt, David. 1991. Aristotle’s Theory of Distributive Justice. In A Companion to Aristotle’s Politics, ed. David Keyt and Fred Miller Jr., 238–278. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraut, Richard. 2002. Aristotle: Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kronman, Anthony. 1979. Aristotle’s Idea of Political Fraternity. American Journal of Jurisprudence 24: 114–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lane, Melissa. 2014. The Birth of Politics: Eight Greek and Roman Political Ideas and Why They Matter. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leontsini, Eleni. 2013. The Motive of Society: Aristotle on Civic Friendship, Justice and Concord. Res Publica 19: 21–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindsay, Thomas. 1992. Aristotle’s Qualified Defense of Democracy Through ‘Political Mixing’. Journal of Politics 54: 101–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lisi, Francisco. 2014. Theoretical Life, Practical Life, and Happiness in Aristotle. In Theoria: Studies on the Status and Meaning of Contemplation in Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Pierre Destrée and Marco Zongano, 241–271. Louvain-La-Neuve: Peeters.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lord, Carnes. 1982. Education and Culture in the Political Thought of Aristotle. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Aristotle’s Politics. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Markle, Minor. 1985. Jury Pay and Assembly Pay at Athens. History of Political Thought 6: 265–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayhew, Robert. 1997. Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato’s Republic. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Fred, Jr. 1995. Nature, Justice, and Rights in Aristotle’s Politics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagle, D. Brendan. 2006. The Household as the Foundation of Aristotle’s Polis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Narcy, Michel. 1993. Aristote devant les Objections de Socrate a la Démocratie. In Aristote politique: Études sur la Politique d’ Aristote, ed. Pierre Aubenque and Alonso Tordesillas, 265–288. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell, Walter. 1991. Superlative Virtue: The Problem of Monarchy in Aristotle’s Politics. In Essays on the Foundations of Aristotelian Political Science, ed. Carnes Lord and David O’Connor, 191–211. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ober, Josiah. 1991. Aristotle’s Political Sociology: Class, Status, and Order in the Politics. In Essays on the Foundations of Aristotelian Political Science, ed. Carnes Lord and David O’Connor, 112–135. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Political Dissent in Democratic Athens: Intellectual Critics of Popular Rule. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Aristotle’s Natural Democracy. In Aristotle’s Politics: Critical Essays, ed. Richard Kraut and Steven Skultetey, 223–243. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrin, Pierre. 1996. On the ‘Platonic’ Part of Aristotle’s Politics. In Aristotle’s Philosophical Development: Problems and Prospects, ed. William Wiens, 347–357. London: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preus, Anthony. 2012. Aristotle on Oligarchy: Theory and Observation. Philosophical Inquiry 35: 26–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, Richard. 1962. Aristotle’s Politics: Books III and IV. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roche, Timothy. 2014. The Private Moral Life of Aristotle’s Philosopher: A Defense of a Non-intellectualist Interpretation of Nicomachean Ethics 10.7–8. In Theoria: Studies on the Status and Meaning of Contemplation in Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Pierre Destrée and Marco Zongano, 207–239. Louvain-La-Neuve: Peeters.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roochnik, David. 2008. Aristotle’s Defense of the Theoretical Life: Comments on Politics 7. Review of Metaphysics 61: 711–735.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samaras, Thanassis. 2007. Aristotle’s Politics: The City of Book Seven and the Question of Ideology. Classical Quarterly 57: 77–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, Trevor. 1999. The Politics. In Routledge History of Philosophy v. 2: From Aristotle to Augustine, ed. David Furley, 125–146. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saxonhouse, Arlene. 1996. Athenian Democracy: Modern Myth Makers and Ancient Theorists. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, Malcolm. 2003. Saving the City: Philosopher-Kings and Other Classical Paradigms. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schollmeier, Paul. 1994. Other Selves: Aristotle on Personal and Political Friendship. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schütrumpf, Eckart. 1991. Aristotles, Politik, Buch I. Berlin: Akademie.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Aristotles, Politik, Buch IV–VI. Berlin: Akademie.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Aristotles, Politik, Buch VII/VIII. Berlin: Akademie.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, Peter. 1998. A Philosophical Commentary on the Politics of Aristotle. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skultety, Steven. 2009. Delimiting Aristotle’s Conception of Stasis in the Politics. Phronesis 54: 346–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solmsen, Friedrich. 1964. Leisure and Play in Aristotle’s Ideal State. Rheinisches Museum für Philologie 107: 193–220.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern-Gillet, Suzanne. 1995. Aristotle’s Philosophy of Friendship. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vander Waerdt, Paul. 1985. Kingship and Philosophy in Aristotle’s Best Regime. Phronesis 30: 249–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, James. 2011. Deliberation, Democracy, and the Rule of Reason in Aristotle’s Politics. American Political Science Review 105: 259–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woods, Cathal. 2014. The Limits of Citizenship in Aristotle’s Politics. History of Political Thought 35: 399–435.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yack, Bernard. 1993. Problems of a Political Animal: Community, Justice, and Conflict in Aristotelian Political Thought. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Community and Conflict. In Action and Contemplation: Studies in the Moral and Political Thought of Aristotle, ed. Robert Bartlett and Susan Collins, 273–292. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to J. Noel Hubler .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Hubler, J.N. (2021). Aristotle’s Model Polities. In: Overcoming Uncertainty in Ancient Greek Political Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-82091-6_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics