Skip to main content

On a Rhetorical Ground of Human Togetherness: Plurality and Mediality in Arendt and Peirce

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Hannah Arendt: Challenges of Plurality

Part of the book series: Women in the History of Philosophy and Sciences ((WHPS,volume 10))

  • 366 Accesses

Abstract

Both in Arendt’s political phenomenology and in Peirce’s pragmatist theory of inquiry, plurality is rooted in the capacity to see that which for someone else speaks for something. This is our central thesis. By ‘plurality’ we mean the specific experiential mode of sharing a common world with beings that are implicitly taken to be equals in as much as they are embodied perspectival openings on the world, i.e. in so far as they can be proto-, hetero- and co-perspectival at one and the same time. And by speaking of a certain δύναμις as the ‘root of plurality’ we mean to indicate that plurality is not a naturally given property of our experience, but rather a necessary accomplishment. A necessary accomplishment the degree of which, however, depends on the mode of actualization of one and the same dúnamis. For Arendt and Peirce, therefore, plurality is both rooted in a capacity we, as human beings, necessarily have to actualize in at least some rudimentary form, but also something that has a determinate developmental potential and is thus capable of unfolding towards an intrinsic state of realiziational perfection. The fundamental difference between both accounts of the phenomenon, however, concerns the status of the mediality and finality of plurality, ultimately the ontological status ascribed to the phenomenon of individuality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Further cited as Rhet.

  2. 2.

    Heidegger’s emphasis on what might best be called rhetorica naturalis goes, as far as I can see, against the traditional standard interpretation of the term dúnamis in the phrase “δύναμις […] τοῦ θεωρῆσαι τὸ ἐνδεχόμενον πιθανόν” at 1355 b26. Thus Grimaldi (1980, 36), glosses that “the faculty resides in the person who has mastered the rules and principles of the τέχνη.” I can here only hint at the fact that the distinction between a theoretically reflected logica docens and a performatively actualized logica utens is fundamental in Peirce’s dynamic conception of logic; cf. Pietarinen (2005).

  3. 3.

    The English term originally used for ‘Besinnung’ is “reconsideration” (Arendt, 1958, 5) which lacks the whole semantic component of ‘coming to one’s mind’, ‘coming to one’s senses’ and ‘regaining self-control’ which is part and parcel of ‘Besinnung’ which, moreover, is an act that presupposes a preceding state of indecision, confusion, altered consciousness and/or lack of principled judgment.

  4. 4.

    My reading of the three basic activities, thus, is decidedly in line with the perspectives of a Heideggerian transcendentalism which is also explicitly at work in Braun (1994) and Loidolt (2018), especially 110–118.

  5. 5.

    Other expressions: “the over-all gigantic circle of nature” (Arendt, 1958, 96) or “the over-all natural process” (Arendt, 1958,136).

  6. 6.

    Peirce’s most substantial contributions to Evolutionary Metaphysics have been published in Peirce (1998, 1,215–371).

  7. 7.

    Dossa (1988, 74); it should be noted that whenever Arendt speaks of human plurality as a quantitative “fact”, these claims are always supported with hermeneutic evidence which—far from originating in empirical observation from a third-personal stance—articulates a determinate historical self-understanding of man. In this sense the biblical account of the creation of man in Genesis (Arendt, 1958, 8), the Latin verb inter homines esse (Arendt, 1958, 7–8), or our historically grown mode to conceive of the otherness among human beings as categorically different from the otherness obtaining among things and animals (Arendt, 1958, 176), all reflect plurality as a “fact” given nowhere but in our first-personal perspective as agents.

  8. 8.

    Benhabib (2003, 50, 104 ff.).

  9. 9.

    The characteristic of the three activities of the vita activa to function as modes of existential enactment is emphasized and carefully analyzed in Loidolt (2018, 109–123), who sees these activities reflect “who we are and how” (110), and in Braun (1994, 13–37), who conceptualizes the activities as Geschehnisweisen (34 ff.), i.e. as “»ways of taking place« of human life”, as Loidolt aptly translates the term.

  10. 10.

    The first number refers to the manuscript, second refers to page number.

  11. 11.

    Alternatively Peirce also refers to a classification or division of three: “types of men” (Peirce, 1969, MS 401:1, 1893; Peirce, 1998, 2,445, 1908), “divisions of human life” (Peirce, 1969, MS 477:01, 1903), “ways of life” (Peirce, 1969, MS 604, c. 1904), or “bodies [of men]” with correlated “classes of human vocation” (Peirce, 1969, MS 992:1, c. 1904).

  12. 12.

    This becomes particularly clear in the unpublished manuscript “Of the Practical Sciences”: “Let us begin, then, our enumeration of the principal sciences. A science, in the sense in which we are here to take the word is a deliberate course of inquiry. As such, it is animated by a purpose. Now every purpose has its root in a desire, and every desire is a phase of an instinct. The instincts of every animal appear to have for their quasi-purpose the preservation of the race of which that animal is a member, and this in one or other of two ways, 1st, by preserving that individual alive, 2nd, by causing him to reproduce his kind, and rear his offspring.” (Peirce, 1969, MS 1343:17–18, emphasis added). will then also include a third class of “specicultural instincts”, which, other than the two reproductive instincts concerning food and reproduction, is not related to things or fellow-beings, but rather to ideas.

  13. 13.

    Aristotle (2001, 1095 b10–1096 a10).

  14. 14.

    Cf. Arendt (1958, 12–13) and Aristotle (2001, Nicomachean Ethics, X, 7–8).

  15. 15.

    Cf. Peirce, 1958, (1.55 (c. 1896), 1.135 (1898), 5.582 f. (1898)).

  16. 16.

    Cf. Peirce, 1969, MS 1334:4–6 = Peirce 1958 7.54 (1903) and 1.235 f. (1902).

  17. 17.

    Cf. Arendt (1958, 206–207).

  18. 18.

    On the Peircean conception of habit-taking as a manifestation of the formal category of thirdness in psychic and physical processuality. cf. Peirce 1958, 1.351, 1.409, 6.299, 6.262, 8.80.

  19. 19.

    Cf. also Section 25.

  20. 20.

    Hampshire (1989); cf. Kant (2000, § 40).

  21. 21.

    Hookway (1985, 48).

  22. 22.

    I have developed this interpretation in detail in Topa (2016, 82–93).

  23. 23.

    Kant (2000, § 40). 

  24. 24.

    Loc. cit.; See also Borren (2013), for an excellent account of the central role the common sense already plays in Arendt’s work before the Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy.

  25. 25.

    Cf. e.g. Peirce (1998, 2,58 f., 1901) and Peirce (1958, 5.402 n.3, 1906).

  26. 26.

    Thus, as Habermas (1992, 110), rightly points out, “the generalization of a consensus [for Peirce] not only implies the dissolution of contradictions, but also the extinguishing of the individuality of those who are able to contradict each other—their disappearance within a collective representation.”

References

  • Arendt, H. (1958). The human condition. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1981). Vita Activa oder vom tätigen Leben. Piper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (2001). The basic works of Aristotle, edited by Richard McKeon. Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. (2003). The reluctant modernism of Hannah Arendt. Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borren, M. (2013). ‘A sense of the world’: Hannah Arendt’s hermeneutic phenomenology of common sense. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 21(2), 225–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braun, M. (1994). Hannah Arendts transzendentaler Tätigkeitsbegriff. Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dossa, S. (1988). The public realm and the public self. Wilfred Laurier University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimaldi, W. (1980). Aristotle rhetoric I. Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1992). Peirce on communication. In Post-metaphysical thinking: Philosophical essays. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampshire, S. (1989). The social spirit of mankind. In E. Förster (Ed.), Kant’s transcendental deductions (pp. 145–156). Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2002). Grundbegriffe der Aristotelischen Philosophie. Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2008). Being and time. Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hookway, C. (1985). Peirce. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant (1998, B 111).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998). Critique of pure reason. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2000). Critique of the power of judgment. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loidolt, S. (2018). Phenomenology of plurality. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1958). The collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1969). Manuscripts of Charles S. Peirce in the Houghton Library of Harvard University, followed by manuscript number and page number, as identified in Robin (1967), and in Robin (1971). Page numbers prefixed with a zero do not refer to Peirce’s pagination, but to the numbers stamped on each page of the microfilm edition of the Harvard manuscripts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1998). The essential Peirce. Vols. 1-2. Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietarinen, A.-V. (2005). Cultivating habits of reason: Peirce and the Logica Utens versus Logica Docens Distinction. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 22(4), 357–372.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robin, R. (1967). Annotated catalogue of the papers of Charles S. Peirce. University of Massachusetts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robin, R. (1971). The Peirce papers: A supplementary catalogue. Transactions of the Charles Sanders Peirce Society, 7(1), 37–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Topa, A. (2016). ‘I have to confess I cannot read history so’. On the origins and development of Peirce’s philosophy of history. European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 8(2), 71–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Villa, D. (1996). Arendt and Heidegger: The fate of the political. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Topa, A. (2022). On a Rhetorical Ground of Human Togetherness: Plurality and Mediality in Arendt and Peirce. In: Robaszkiewicz, M., Matzner, T. (eds) Hannah Arendt: Challenges of Plurality. Women in the History of Philosophy and Sciences, vol 10. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-81712-1_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics