Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Sustainable Development Goals Series ((SDGS))

  • 325 Accesses

Abstract

Religious wisdom traditions offer a rich foundation for affirming the intrinsic value of non-human nature. Yet the disenchantment of modernity divests the natural world of formal and final causality: the “book of nature” ceases to tell a moral or religious tale. In these pages, I offer an immanent critique of the agnostic pieties that militate against public religious reasoning: the primacy accorded instrumental causality, the technical reduction of prudence, and the “invention” of a purely anthropocentric morality. Prudence, I argue, presumes a formal maxim of deliberation, irreducible to a technical (analytical) relation of means and ends. Such deliberation introduces elements of both formal and final causality as emergent properties, such that wisdom traditions play an integral, hermeneutical role in interpreting nature.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    “In formulating such a conception,” concludes Rawls, political liberalism “applies the principle of toleration to philosophy itself” (Rawls 1996: 9–10; See Dworkin 1978: 113–43).

  2. 2.

    In later writings, Rawls departs from such an “exclusive” conception in favor of an “inclusive,” and finally “wide” view of public reason.

  3. 3.

    In Habermas’ words, “from religious truths, after the religious world views have collapsed, nothing more and nothing other than the secular principles of a universalist ethics of responsibility can be salvaged...” (Habermas 1985: 52). Habermas subsequently qualifies this subscription of religion to the pastness of the past (Habermas 2002: 67–94, Habermas 2005: 106–18, see Junker-Kenny 2006: 106–117).

  4. 4.

    Even anthropocentric ethics, if adequately elaborated, supports an ecological ethics, inasmuch as respect for an intergenerational “kingdom of ends” enjoins care for the environment. But the technical reduction of prudence raises into question Kant’s foundational account of dignity, and, a fortiori, intergenerational responsibility.

  5. 5.

    For Kant, the semantic indeterminacy of “happiness,” ordered to the “producible ends of pleasure,” precludes the generation of prudential imperatives as such; at best, we can speak of “consilia” (Kant: 418 (37); 1956: 36).

  6. 6.

    Celia Dean-Drummond writes, “to suppose so-called objective truth claims, themselves subject of human interpretation and revision, are superior to other forms of truth, including religious truth, demonstrates not so much insight as hubris” (Deane-Drummond 2007: 587).

  7. 7.

    Celia Dean-Drummond offers an eloquent defense of the place of such wisdom (and wonder) in an evolutionary perspective. Citing Jeffrey Schloss, Dean-Drummond notes that wisdom is “not mere knowledge,...but involves deep insight into the functioning, meaning and purpose of existence along with the ability to discern how to live correspondingly, that is, in accord with the way things are” (Deane-Drummond 2006: 10–11; Schloss 2000: 151–191, at 156). Prudence, conceived as practical wisdom in the phronetic tradition of Aristotle and Aquinas, provides “a means through which relationships, attitudes and motivations can be assessed” (Deane-Drummond 2004: 92).

  8. 8.

    There is, says Williams “certainly a distinction...between regarding a man’s life, actions or character from an aesthetic or technical point of view, and regarding them from a point of view which is concerned primarily with what it is for him to live that life and do those actions in that character” (Williams 1973: 236–37).

References

  • Davidson, Donald. 1985. Reply to Essays I-X. In Essays on Davidson: Actions and Events, ed. Bruce Vermazen and Merrill B. Hintikka. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deane-Drummond, Celia. 2004. The Ethics of Nature. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006. Wonder and Wisdom: Conversations in Science, Spirituality, and Theology. West Conshohocken, PA: Templeton Foundation Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Experience Wonder and Seeking Wisdom. Zygon 42 (3).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, Louis. 1999. On the Intellectual Sources of Modern Atheism. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion: 45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1978. Liberalism. In Public and Private Morality, ed. Stuart Hampshire, 113–143. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1985. Die neue Unübersichlichkeit. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. To Seek to Salvage an Unconditional Meaning without God is a Futile Undertaking: Reflections on a Remark of Max Horkheimer. In Justification and Application: Remarks on Discourse Ethics. trans. Ciaran Cronin, Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Transcendence from Within, Transcendence in this World. In Religion and Rationality: Essays on Reason, God, and Modernity, ed. Habermas. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Vorpolitische Grundlagen des demokratischen Rechtsstaats? In Zwischen Naturalismus und Religion. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas. 1968 (1651). Leviathan. ed. C. B. Macpherson. Baltimore: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, Gerard Manley. 1986. God’s Grandeur. In Gerard Manley Hopkins, ed. Catherine Philipps. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 1957 (1751). An Inquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. Charles W. Hendel. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Junker-Kenny, Maureen. 2006. The Pre-Political Foundations of the State. In The New Pontificate: A Time for Change? ed. Erik Borgman, Maureen Junker-Kenny, and Janet Martin Soskice. London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1956 (1788). Critique of Practical Reason. trans. Lewis White Beck. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1964 (1785). Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. trans. H. J. Paton. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Madan, Geoffrey. 1981. Notebooks. ed. J. A. Gere and John Sparrow. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1996. Political Liberalism. Columbia: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. A Theory of Justice. Rev. ed. 1999. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1989. Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schloss, Jeffrey. 2000. “Wisdom Traditions as Mechanism for Organismal Integration: Evolutionary Perspectives on Homeostatis ‘Laws of Life’,” in Understanding Wisdom: Sources, Science, & Society, ed. Warren S. Brown. Philadelphia, PA: Templeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Max. 1947. “Science as a Vocation,” in From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, trans. and ed. H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills. New York: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. 1973. “The Idea of Equality,” in Problems of the Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. 1985. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1967. Zettel, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1968. Philosophical Investigations, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, 3d. ed. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, Michael J. 2009. Justice: What’s the Right Thing to Do? New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to William O’Neill .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

O’Neill, W. (2022). The Ethics of Enchantment: Spirituality and Ecological Ethics. In: Sherma, R.D., Bilimoria, P. (eds) Religion and Sustainability: Interreligious Resources, Interdisciplinary Responses. Sustainable Development Goals Series. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-79301-2_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics