Skip to main content

Introduction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Conceptual Jurisprudence

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 137))

  • 449 Accesses

Abstract

The introduction sets the stage by explaining the goals of conceptual jurisprudence and providing a summary of the essays.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Although we have derived this illustrative label from KE Himma, as explained in footnote 14, we do not follow his approach. See Himma (2015). For more information, see van der Burg (2020).

  2. 2.

    Hart (2012).

  3. 3.

    For the classical expression of this view, see Kantorowicz (1958).

  4. 4.

    Hart (2012), pp. 13–14; Hart (1983a), pp. 33–35.

  5. 5.

    Hart (2012), chap. 1.

  6. 6.

    Ibid., p. 6.

  7. 7.

    Mainly based on certain historical connections with the school of Oxford’s ordinary language philosophy, Hart was taken “to be engaged in a familiar philosophical project of conceptual analysis”—that is, according to this interpretation, he was “doing the same kind of philosophical work that his peers in the philosophy of language, metaphysics, ethics and epistemology were doing.” Coleman (2001), p. 175. Similarly, according to Nicos Stavropoulos, “Rather than seeking rules for using the key expressions, or setting out to list the situations in which users apply the expressions, Hart’s method was usually called conceptual analysis.” Stavropolous (2001), p. 69. Others, however, have rejected such a connection. See, for example, Green (2012); Marmor (2013).

  8. 8.

    Hart (2012), pp. 239–40.

  9. 9.

    Langlinais and Leiter (2016), p. 671.

  10. 10.

    Hart (1983b).

  11. 11.

    Raz (1999), pp. 10–1.

  12. 12.

    See, e.g., Burgess and Plunkett (2013).

  13. 13.

    See, e.g., Flathman (1973).

  14. 14.

    The most influential approaches in this sense are found in Shapiro (2011), chap. 1, and Himma (2015).

  15. 15.

    As an illustration of the richness of the notion analysis, see Beaney (2014). For the different understandings of “conceptual analysis” in jurisprudence, see the first Chapter by Pierluigi Chiassioni.

  16. 16.

    Giudice (2015).

  17. 17.

    Cappelen (2018); Burgess et al. (2020).

  18. 18.

    William Twining offers a useful catalogue of the tools available to legal theory, with references to secondary literature. Twining (2009), pp. 40–1.

  19. 19.

    See, e.g., the chapters by Lucas Miotto and Andrés Molina-Ochoa.

  20. 20.

    de Santos (2002), p. 86.

  21. 21.

    Teubner (1997), p. 14.

  22. 22.

    This view is discussed in the chapters by José Juan Moreso and Sari Kisilevsky, among others.

  23. 23.

    HLA Hart, for example, suggests that this notion is the “most powerful tool for the analysis of much that has puzzled both the jurist and the political theorist.” Hart (2012), p. 98.

  24. 24.

    Schauer (2015).

  25. 25.

    There are numerous statements from legal philosophers suggesting that this is the central question of jurisprudence. For example, as noted above, one of Hart’s central questions concerns explaining how legal obligations differ from and are related to moral obligations. Hart (2012), pp. 7–8. Brian Leiter similarly diagnose legal philosophers as having “been preoccupied with specifying the differences between two systems of normative guidance that are omnipresent in all human societies: law and morality. In the last 100 years… the problem of how to distinguish these two normative systems has been the dominant problem in jurisprudence…” Leiter (2011), p. 664.

  26. 26.

    Austin (1995), Kelsen (1992), and Hart (2012) are considered primary examples of legal positivism thus understood.

  27. 27.

    Aquinas (1981), Finnis (2011), and Murphy (2003) are examples of classical natural lawyers, who generally endorse a specific conception of basic goods. In turn, Dworkin (1986) and Alexy (2002) are examples of self-styled "non-positivists," who differ from natural lawyers by not endorsing a classical conception of basic goods.

  28. 28.

    See, e.g., Waluchow (1994).

  29. 29.

    See, e.g., Raz (1994).

  30. 30.

    Hart (2012), pp. 238–276.

  31. 31.

    Ibid., p. 210.

  32. 32.

    For the classical formulation, see Raz (1999).

  33. 33.

    Plunkett and Shapiro (2017).

  34. 34.

    For a classical formulation, see Marmor (2006).

References

  • Alexy R (2002) The argument from injustice: a reply to legal positivism. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas T (1981) The Summa Theologica of St. Thomas Aquinas. Christian Classics, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin J (1995) The province of jurisprudence determined. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beaney M (2014) Analysis. In: Zalta EN (ed) Standford encyclopedia of philosophy

    Google Scholar 

  • Burgess A, Plunkett D (2013) Conceptual ethics I. Philos Compass 8:1091–1101. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12086

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burgess A, Cappelen H, Plunkett D (eds) (2020) Conceptual engineering and conceptual ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen H (2018) Fixing language: an essay on conceptual engineering. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman JL (2001) The practice of principle: in defense of a pragmatist approach to legal theory. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • de Santos BS (2002) Toward a new legal common sense: law, globalization, and emancipation, 2nd edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1986) Law’s Empire. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis J (2011) Natural law and natural rights, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Flathman RE (1973) Concepts in social & political philosophy. Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Giudice M (2015) Understanding the nature of law: a case for constructive conceptual explanation. Edward Elgar Publishing, Cheltenham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Green L (2012) Introduction. In: The concept of law, 3rd edn. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp xv–lv

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (1983a) Definition and theory in jurisprudence. In: Essays in jurisprudence and philosophy. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 21–48

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (1983b) Problems of the philosophy of law. In: Essays in jurisprudence and philosophy. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 88–119

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (2012) The concept of law, 3rd edn. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Himma KE (2015) Conceptual jurisprudence. An introduction to conceptual analysis and methodology in legal theory. Revus 26:65–92

    Google Scholar 

  • Kantorowicz H (1958) The definition of law. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (1992) Introduction to the problems of legal theory: a translation of the first edition of the ‘Reine Rechtslehre’ or Pure Theory of Law. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Langlinais A, Leiter B (2016) In: Cappelen H, Gendler TS, Hawthorne J (eds) The methodology of legal philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Leiter B (2011) The demarcation problem in jurisprudence: a new case for scepticism. Oxf J Leg Stud 31:663–677

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marmor A (2006) How law is like chess. Legal Theory 12:347–371

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marmor A (2013) Farewell to conceptual analysis (in Jurisprudence). In: Waluchow W, Sciaraffa S (eds) Philosophical foundations of the nature of law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 209–228

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy MC (2003) Natural law jurisprudence. Legal Theory 9:241–267

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plunkett D, Shapiro S (2017) Law, morality, and everything else: general jurisprudence as a branch of metanormative. Ethics 128:37–68

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (1994) Authority, law, and morality. In: Ethics in the public domain. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 210–237

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (1999) practical reason and norms, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (2015) The force of law. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro SJ (2011) Legality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stavropolous N (2001) Hart’s semantics. In: Coleman JL (ed) Hart’s postscript: essays on the postscript to the concept of law. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 59–98

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Teubner G (1997) ‘Global Bukowina’: legal pluralism in the world society. In: Teubner G (ed) Global law without a state. Dartmouth, Aldershot, pp 3–30

    Google Scholar 

  • Twining W (2009) General jurisprudence: understanding law from a global perspective. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van der Burg W (2020) Conceptual theories of law and the challenges of global legal pluralism: a legal interactionist approach. In: Berman PS (ed) The Oxford handbook on global legal pluralism. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Waluchow WJ (1994) Inclusive legal positivism. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jorge Luis Fabra-Zamora .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Fabra-Zamora, J.L., Villa Rosas, G. (2021). Introduction. In: Fabra-Zamora, J.L., Villa Rosas, G. (eds) Conceptual Jurisprudence. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 137. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-78803-2_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-78803-2_1

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-78802-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-78803-2

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics