Skip to main content

Introduction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Geometry of Choice
  • 130 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter offers a broad contextualisation of the argument developed in the book. It serves to outline the scope of the study. The chapter introduces the reader to the fundamental notions and research assumptions as well as the philosophical setting against which these main assumptions are set.

There are more things in HEAVEN and EARTH, Horatio, than are dreamt of in your PHILOSOPHY.

Hamlet (William Shakespeare )

Novelist and existentialist philosopher Albert Camus posed the question, ‘Should I kill myself, or have a cup of coffee?’ His point was that everything in life is choice. Every second of every day, we are choosing, and there are always alternatives. Existence, at least human existence, is defined by the choices people make.

Schwartz, (2004, p. 42)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The data cited herein were extracted from the British National Corpus, which is distributed by the University of Oxford on behalf of the BNC Consortium. All rights in the cited texts are reserved. The emphasis in the examples is added by the author to better illustrate the discussed cases.

  2. 2.

    In the book the following notational convention is observed (see also Sect. 1.1): small caps to signify concepts; italics to mark out the words that represent concepts; and Capitalisation to distinguish philosophical terms. For example, cube is to be understood as a word, Cube as a Platonic solid, and cube as a conceptual category that encompasses both expert and non-expert understanding.

  3. 3.

    In their tribute paper to Claude Vandeloise and his original functional approach to the study of spatial prepositions, Michel Aurnague and Gilles Col (2017, p. 8) note: ‘Indeed, from the very start of his investigations on the expression of space in French, Vandeloise (1984, 1986, 1991) developed his own framework of analysis—within the trend of cognitive linguistics—and went on using and enhancing it until the last written work gathered in this special issue (Aurnague, 2008). He defined five groups of functional universal features that, according to him, should be taken into account when examining the semantics of spatial prepositions/adpositions: anthropomorphic principles forming the human body, naïve physics, access to perception, potential encounter, and general and lateral orientations.’ Though it seems that Vandeloise minimises the role of geometry for its structuring of our perception and instead promotes functional attributes of space, there is still some common ground that can be found between Vandeloise’s approach and that adopted in this book. The shared elements relate to the recognition of human body, naïve physics, and access to perception as being central to the description of spacetime. In his peer review of the draft manuscript of this book, Professor Andrzej Pawelec also points to differences which stem from the varied research assumptions adopted by Vandeloise and the current study: ‘As for the content of the book, the current formulation of the model could be profitably confronted with alternative approaches. For instance, the mostly static and schematic representation of human location in spacetime offered by CL (in this account) could be opposed to a more pragmatic and developmental vision offered by Claude Vandeloise in his article “Length, width, and potential passing” (1988). From the latter perspective, the position and potential movement of the agent would be central in order to determine the actual shape of the model.’ As might be inferred from these observations, cubic architecture might, therefore, be viewed by Vandeloise as at most a secondary rather than a primary form of spatiotemporal experience, as geometric configurations are determined by the agentivity of a human individual rather than the other way round.

  4. 4.

    Cf. Antonowicz (2015, pp. 93–94) and his discussion of the studies by Cohen and March (1974) and March and Olsen (1976) on the metaphorisation of decision-making processes in a hybrid organisation characterised by vaguely defined goals. The metaphors reconstruct as a result of the process of comprehensively studying the contemporary university evoke notions of structured anarchy (organised anarchies), in which decision-making processes are illustrated through reference to the notion of ‘garbage can situations’, a term used by the modern theories of organisation that denotes taking decisions under continuously changing circumstances and permanent uncertainty with regard to the tools and procedures in which decisions are to be optimally taken.

  5. 5.

    During the international conference held in Łodź in 2002, Ronald W. Langacker criticised the notion of pre-conceptuality in relation to image schemas, especially those well-grounded in the mental repositories of interlocutors such as idealised cognitive models (Lakoff, 1987). Langacker suggests that the term pre-conceptual should better be replaced with the term pre-linguistic as this notion more appropriately addresses the ontology of the schemas in question. I would like to thank Professor Barbara Lewandowska-Tomaszczyk for her remarks on the issue.

References

  • Antonowicz, D. (2015). Między siłą globalnych procesów a lokalną tradycją: Polskie szkolnictwo wyższe w dobie przemian. Wydawnictwo Naukowe Uniwersytetu Mikołaja Kopernika.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aurnague, M. (2008). Claude Vandeloise: obra baten mugarriak [Claude Vandeloise: the milestones of his work]. Gogoa, 8 (1): 9–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aurnague, M., & Col, G. (2017). Claude Vandeloise on Proximity or the Missing Piece of a Final Triptych. https://www.researchgate.net/publication/320661289_Claude_Vandeloise_on_proximity_or_the_missing_piece_of_a_final_triptych.

  • Bealer, G. (2006). Universals and the Defense of Ante Rem Realism. In P. F. Strawson & A. Chakrabarti (Eds.), Universals, Concepts and Qualities. New Essays on the Meaning of Predicates (pp. 225–238). Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brożek, B., & Hohol, M. (2014). Umysł matematyczny. Copernicus Center Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, M. D., & March, J. G. (1974). Leadership and Ambiguity: The American College President, A General Report Prepared for the Carnegie Commission on Higher Education. McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Critser, G. (2003). Fat Land: How Americans Became the Fattest People in the World. Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dąbek-Derda, E. (2017). Sześcian zamknięty w kuli. Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Śląskiego.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, V., & Green, M. (2006). Cognitive Linguistics. An Introduction. Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fauconnier, G., & Turner, M. (2002). The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and The Mind’s Hidden Complexities. Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goatly, A. (2007). Washing the Brain—Metaphor and Hidden Ideology. John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jakobson, R. (1987). Language in Literature. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. (1987). The Body in The Mind: The Bodily Basis of Cognition. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. (1993). Moral Imagination: Implications of Cognitive Science for Ethics. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. (2014). Morality for Humans. Ethical Understanding from the Perspective of Cognitive Science. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. (2018). The Aesthetics of Meaning and Thought: The Bodily Roots of Philosophy, Science, Morality, and Art. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kövecses, Z. (2010, 2002). Metaphor. A Practical Introduction. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kövecses, Z. (2015). Where Metaphors Come From (Kindle Edn.). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krzeszowski, T. P. (1997). Angels and Devils in Hell. Elements of Axiology in Semantics. Wydawnictwo Energeia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuźniak, M. (2009). Foreign Words and Phrases in English. Metaphoric Astrophysical Concepts in Lexicological Study. Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Wrocławskiego.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuźniak, M. (2018). Hot Issues in Cognitive Linguistics. In A. Uberman & M. Dick-Bursztyn (Eds.), Language in the New Millennium. Applied-linguistic and Cognitive-linguistic Considerations (pp. 95–116). Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal about The Mind. The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G. (1993). The Contemporary Theory of Metaphor. In A. Ortony (Ed.), Metaphor and thought (2nd ed., pp. 202–251). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors We Live By. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the Flesh. The Embodied Mind and its Challenge to Western Thought. Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewandowska-Tomaszczyk, B. (2017). Partial Perception and Approximate Understanding. Research in Language, 15(2), 129–152. https://doi.org/10.1515/rela-2017-0009.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • March, J. G., & Olsen, J. P. (1976). Ambiguity and Choice in Organizations. Universitetsforlaget.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ogden, C. K., & Richards, I. A. (1923). The Meaning of Meaning: A Study of the Influence of Language upon Thought and of the Science of Symbolism (8th ed.). Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc..

    Google Scholar 

  • Pawelec, A. (2008). Mentalizm w badaniach nad językiem. In P. Stalmaszczyk (Ed.), Metodologie językoznawstwa. Współczesne tendencje i kontrowersje (pp. 105–119). Lexis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1912). The Problems of Philosophy. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, T. (1990). Choice as Geometry. In R. Sato & R. V. Ramachandran (Eds.), Conservation Laws and Symmetry: Applications to Economics and Finance (pp. 175–224). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sato, R., & Ramachandran, R. V. (1990). Conservation Laws and Symmetry: Applications to Economics and Finance. Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1145-6.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, B. (2004). The Paradox of Choice. HarperCollins Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talmy, L. (1988). Force Dynamics in Language and Cognition. Cognitive Science, 12, 49–100. https://doi.org/10.1016/0364-0213(88)90008-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Talmy, L. (1996). Fictive Motion in Language and ‘Ception’. In P. Bloom, M. A. Peterson, L. Nadel, & M. F. Garrett (Eds.), Language and space (pp. 211–276). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talmy, L. (2000). Toward a Cognitive Semantics. Language, Speech, and Communication. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Talmy, L. (2001). Typology and Process in Concept Structuring. Language, Speech, and Communication: Vol. 2. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, M. (1990). Aspects of the Invariance Hypothesis. Cognitive Linguistics, 1(2), 247–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vandeloise, C. (1984). Description of Space in French. PhD dissertation, University of California, San Diego. LAUTD.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vandeloise, C. (1986). L’espace en français: sémantique des prépositions spatiales. Editions du Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vandeloise, C. (1988). Length, Width, and Potential Passing. In B. Rudzka-Ostyn (Ed.), Topics in Cognitive Linguistics [Current Issues in Linguistic Theory 50] (pp. 403–428). John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vandeloise, C. (1991). Spatial Prepositions: A Case Study in French. The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woźny, J. (2018). How We Understand Mathematics: Conceptual Integration in the Language of Mathematical Description. Mathematics in Mind. Springer International Publishing. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-77688-0.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Internet Sites

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marek Kuźniak .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Kuźniak, M. (2021). Introduction. In: The Geometry of Choice. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-78655-7_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-78655-7_1

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-78654-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-78655-7

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics