Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Law, Governance and Technology Series ((ISDP,volume 46))

  • 1002 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter focuses on the relationship between human rights and the different forms of AI. Its goal is to start specifying the framework for AI governance, in line with the fundamental goals of the international community. Human rights are approached here from the perspective of the area of international law, which guarantees the prevalence of human-centrism in the international legal order. This role necessitates thorough monitoring and careful but still effective interventions in the evolution of AI, in the sense of imposing regulatory mechanisms, of slowing down or even of prohibiting certain AI advantages.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Cassese (1986), pp. 377–379.

  2. 2.

    Perkins (1992), pp. 379–380; Buchanan (2004), p. 119.

  3. 3.

    Provost (2004), pp. 16–17; Schwebel (1991), pp. 955–956.

  4. 4.

    Weston (2008), pp. 324–325.

  5. 5.

    Buchanan (2004), pp. 121–123.

  6. 6.

    Provost (2004), p. 25.

  7. 7.

    Teng (2012), p. 157; Anderson (2010), p. 194.

  8. 8.

    UN Charter, Preamble; Universal Declaration of Human Rights-UNDA-Preamble; International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights-ICCPR-Preamble; International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights-ICESCR-Preamble.

  9. 9.

    Apart from the UN Charter one may indicatively refer to UNDA, ICCPR, ICESR, European Convention of Human Rights-ECHR-African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights-ACHPR-American Convention on Human Rights-ACHR.

  10. 10.

    Stamatopoulou (1999), pp. 284–285.

  11. 11.

    Anderson (2010), pp. 183, 186, 194–197.

  12. 12.

    U.N. GA RES/48/134(1993), Principles Relating to the Status of National Institutions; UN Human Rights Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, World Conference on Human Rights, (June 14–25, 1993), (www.ohchr.org/EN/ABOUTUS/Pages/ViennaWC.aspx access. 30-06-2020). Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, U.N. Doc. A/CONF.157/23 (July 12, 1993).

  13. 13.

    Conklin (2012), p. 838; Crawford (2002), pp. 148–150, 158–160; Byers (1999), p. 194; ICJ statute, Article 38 (www.icj-cij.org/documents/?p1=4&p2=2&p3=0#CHAPTER_II, access. 28-1-2015).

  14. 14.

    Committee of United States Citizens in Nicaragua v. Reagan, 859 F.2d 929, 935 (D.C. Cir. 1988). Rozakis (1976), p. 1.

  15. 15.

    ICJ, Armed Activities on the Territory of the Congo, Separate Opinion Of Judge Ad Hoc Dugard, (New Application, 2002), 85.

  16. 16.

    Spagnoli (2008), pp. 325–326; Petsche (2010), p. 255; Ogilvy (2009), p. 176; Criddle and Decent (2009), p. 334; Orakhelashvili (2005), pp. 79, 85; Cassese (2012), p. 166.

    Regarding when it can be objectively identified that there is a jus cogens violation, judge Lauterpacht, in the case “Bosnia v Serbia II”, argued that: “The duty to “prevent” genocide is a duty that rests upon all parties and is a duty owed by each party to every other… First, there is the duty of the Respondent [and thus of any state party] both to prevent genocide and to refrain from conduct that inhibits the ability of the Applicant itself to prevent genocide or to resist it… Third, there is the question of access by the Applicant to the means to prevent the commission of acts of genocide. The Applicant obviously has here in mind… the embargo placed by Security Council resolution 713 (1991)… [I]t is not to be contemplated that the Security Council would ever deliberately adopt a resolution clearly and deliberately flouting a rule of jus cogens or requiring a violation of human rights. But the possibility that a Security Council resolution might inadvertently or in an unforeseen manner lead to such a situation cannot be excluded… On this basis, the inability of Bosnia-Herzegovina sufficiently strongly to fight back against the Serbs and effectively to prevent the implementation of the Serbian policy of ethnic cleansing is at least in part directly attributable to the fact that BosniaHerzegovina’s access to weapons and equipment has been severely limited by the embargo. Viewed in this light, the Security Council resolution can be seen as having in effect called on Members of the United Nations, albeit unknowingly and assuredly unwillingly, to become in some degree supporters of the genocidal activity of the Serbs and in this manner and to that extent to act contrary to a rule of jus cogens.”

    ICJ, Bosnia v. Serbia II, (2007), (separate opinion of Judge Lauterpacht) 436-41.

    Also see:

    ICJ, Questions of Interpretation and Application of the 1971 Montreal Convention arising from the Aerial Incident at Lockerbie (Libyan Arab Jamahiriya v. United States of America), (1998) Dissenting Opinion Of President Schwebel, 60.

    Reference should also be made to article 38 of the ICJ.

    For a contradictory argument: Weisburd (1995), pp. 38–39.

    The origins of jus cogens in the post-World War II era can also be traced in the Nuremberg trial while at a later phase, in the “Barcelona Traction (Belgium v. Spain)” case, the similar term of “erga omnes” obligations was introduced.

    Charter of the International Military Tribunal, in force August 8, 1945, 59 Stat. 1544, E.A.S. No. 472, 82 U.N.T.S. 279, ICJ, Barcelona Traction, 4, 32.

  17. 17.

    F. F. Martin, Human Rights and the Hierarchy of International Law Sources and Norms, at p. 353; Crawford (2006), p. 102; Domingo (2012), p. 566.

  18. 18.

    Parker and Neylon (1989), p. 414.

  19. 19.

    Article 53 of the Vienna Convention “.”

  20. 20.

    Rozakis (1976), p. 14.

  21. 21.

    Rozakis (1976), pp. 45, 89–91; Weisburd (1995), p. 19; Schwarzenberger (1965), p. 467; Shleton (2006), p. 291.

  22. 22.

    ICJ, Congo v. Rwanda Judgment, (citing Application of the Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide (Bosn. & Herz. v. Yugo.), Preliminary Objections, (1996) 64. Spijkers (2009–2010), pp. 87–88. ICJ, Case Concerning Armed Activities on the Territory of the Congo (Democratic Republic of the Congo v. Rwanda), Jurisdiction of the Court and Admissibility of the Application, (2006) 64. Fitzmaurice (1973), p. 323. ICJ, The South West Africa Cases, (Ethiopia v. S. Afr.; Liberia v. S. Afr.) (1966) (Tanaka, J., dissenting) 6, 298 (Tanaka, J., dissenting). ICJ, Barcelona Traction, Light and Power Company (Belg. v. Spain), (1970) 3, 301. Adams (2005), pp. 364–369. ICTY, Prosecutor v Furundz ija, No IT-95-17/1-T, (1998), 153–154. H. Gros Espiell, Implementation Of United Nations Resolutions Relating To The Right Of Peoples Under Colonial And Alien Domination To Self-Determination, UN,E/CN.4/Sub.2/405(vol. I) (1978), (unispal.un.org/UNISPAL.NSF/0/BE1DDCB608178D7685256DE100727E8F, access. 29-1-2015). Kamminga (1992), p. 163. ICJ, Barcelona Traction Case, (1962), (Separate opinion of judge Ammoun), 301, 304–312; I.C.J., South West Africa cases, (1966), (Dissenting opinion of Judge Tanaka), 289–290, 298.

  23. 23.

    Report of the International Law Commission on the Work of its Twenty-Eighth Session, State Responsibility, (1976) 2(2), Y.B. Int’l L. Comm’n 69, 99, U.N. Doc. A/CN.4/SER.4/1976/Add.1 (Part 2).

  24. 24.

    R. Nieto-Navia, International Peremptory Norms (Jus Cogens) And International Humanitarian Law, in the (www.iccnow.org/documents/WritingColombiaEng.pdf access. 01-07-2020); Janis (2003), pp. 62–63.

  25. 25.

    Verdross (1966), p. 58.

    Sir Hirsch Lauterpacht in 1953 argued that: “It would thus appear that the test whether the -object of the treaty is illegal and whether the treaty is void for that reason is not inconsistency with customary international law pure and simple, but inconsistency with such overriding principles of international law which may be regarded as constituting principles of international public policy (ordre international public). These principles need not necessarily have crystallized in a clearly accepted rule of law such as prohibition of piracy or of aggressive war. They may be expressive of rules of international morality so cogent that an international tribunal would consider them as forming part of those principles of law generally recognized by civilized nations which the International Court of Justice is bound to apply by virtue of Article 38 (3) of its Statute.”

    H. Lauterpacht, Document:- A/CN.4/63, Report on the Law of Treaties Special Rapporteur Topic: Law of Treaties, (1953), II, Yearbook of the International Law Commission:, 106, at p. 155.

    Fitzmaurice also, held that: “The rules of international law in this context fall broadly into two classes—those which are mandatory and imperative in .any circumstances (jus cogens) and those (jus dispositivum) which merely furnish a rule for application in the absence of any other agreed regime, or, more correctly, those the variation or modification of which under an .agreed regime is permissible, provided the position and rights of their States are not affected.”

    G. G. Fitzmaurice, Third Report on the Law of Treaties, Document A/CN//4/115, (1958) II, Yearbook of. International Law Commission, 20, on p. 40.

  26. 26.

    International Law Commission, Report of the on the Work of Its Fifty-third Session, Draft Articles on Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts, RUN GAOR, 56th Sess., Supp. No. 10, at 43, UN Doc. A/56/10 (2001), (www.un.org/il,c access. 29-1-2015); Brownlie (1979), p. 512.

  27. 27.

    Tams (2005), p. 141; Parker and Neylon (1989), pp. 413–414, Brownlie (1979), p. 513.

  28. 28.

    Trnavci (2005), pp. 251–252.

  29. 29.

    Cf. Bassiouni (2001), p. 104.

  30. 30.

    European Court of Justice, Case T-315/01, Kadi v. Council (2005), 224, 226.

  31. 31.

    European Court of Human Rights, Case Of Al-Adsani V. The United Kingdom, (2001), 61.

  32. 32.

    “By accepting that the rule on prohibition of torture is a rule of jus cogens, the majority recognise that it is hierarchically higher than any other rule of international law, be it general or particular, customary or conventional, with the exception, of course, of other jus cogens norms. For the basic characteristic of a jus cogens rule is that, as a source of law in the now vertical international legal system, it overrides any other rule which does not have the same status. In the event of a conflict between a jus cogens rule and any other rule of international law, the former prevails. The consequence of such prevalence is that the conflicting rule is null and void, or, in any event, does not produce legal effects which are in contradiction with the content of the peremptory rule. 2. The Court’s majority do not seem, on the other hand, to deny that the rules on State immunity; customary or conventional, do not belong to the category of jus cogens; and rightly so, because it is clear that the rules of State immunity, deriving from both customary and conventional international law, have never been considered by the international community as rules with a hierarchically higher status. It is common knowledge that, in many instances, States have, through their own initiative, waived their rights of immunity; that in many instances they have contracted out of them, or have renounced them. These instances clearly demonstrate that the rules on State immunity do not enjoy a higher status, since jus cogens rules, protecting as they do the “ordre public”, that is the basic values of the international community, cannot be subject to unilateral or contractual forms of derogation from their imperative contents. 3.The acceptance therefore of the jus cogens nature of the prohibition of torture entails that a State allegedly violating it cannot invoke hierarchically lower rules (in this case, those on State immunity) to avoid the consequences of the illegality of its actions.”

    European Court of Human Rights, Case Of Al-Adsani V. The United Kingdom, (2005, Joint Dissenting Opinion Of Judges Rozakis And Caflisch Joined By Judges Wildhaber, Costa, Cabral Barreto And Vajić), 1–3.

  33. 33.

    UDHR, Articles 22–28.

  34. 34.

    Jason Pielemeier, AI & Global Governance: The Advantages of Applying the International Human Rights Framework to Artificial Intelligence, United Nations University Centre for Policy Research, (2019, February 26), (https://cpr.unu.edu/publications/articles/ai-global-governance-the-advantages-of-applying-the-international-human-rights-framework-to-artificial-intelligence.html).

  35. 35.

    Alston (1984), p. 607 et seq.

  36. 36.

    Carozza (2008), p. 932.

  37. 37.

    Human dignity as a universal value interacts with each one, specific legal framework, remaining “informal, flexible and pluralistic in its relationship to local law and culture”. Carozza (2003), p. 1043.

  38. 38.

    Diane Desierto, Human Rights in the Era of Automation and Artificial Intelligence, EJILTalk, (2020, February 26), (https://www.ejiltalk.org/human-rights-in-the-era-of-automation-and-artificial-intelligence/).

  39. 39.

    Kate Saslow and Philippe Lorenz, Artificial Intelligence Needs Human Rights September 2019, (https://www.stiftung-nv.de/sites/default/files/ai_needs_human_rights.pdf), p. 18.

  40. 40.

    UN Human Rights Committee, Expert Seminar on Artificial Intelligence and the Right to Privacy, 27–28 May 2020, https://www.ohchr.org/EN/Issues/DigitalAge/Pages/SeminarArtificialIntelligence.aspx.

  41. 41.

    The UN working group on business and human rights, the UN guiding principles on business and human rights an introduction, (https://www.ohchr.org/Documents/Issues/Business/Intro_Guiding_PrinciplesBusinessHR.pdf).

  42. 42.

    UN Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (CESCR), E/C.12/GC/24, General comment No. 24 (2017) on State obligations under the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights in the context of business activities, (2017, August 10), at paras. 1–12, 35, https://www.refworld.org/docid/5beaecba4.html.

  43. 43.

    Council of Europe Commissioner for Human Rights, Unboxing Artificial Intelligence: 10 steps to protect Human Rights, pp. 7–8.

  44. 44.

    EDRi, UN Special Rapporteur analyses AI’s impact on human rights, (2018, November 7), https://edri.org/our-work/un-special-rapporteur-report-artificial-intelligence-impact-human-rights/.

  45. 45.

    UN GA, Promotion and protection of the right to freedom of opinion and expression, Note by the Secretary-General, A/73/348, (2018, August 29), at paras. 47–51.

  46. 46.

    Special Rapporteur on the promotion and protection of the right to freedom of opinion and expression, Report on Artificial Intelligence technologies and implications for freedom of expression and the information environment.

  47. 47.

    Waser, Discovering The Foundations Of A Universal System of Ethics As A Road To Safe Artificial Intelligence.

  48. 48.

    Tegmark (2017), pp. 402–404; Omohundro (2008), pp. 483–492.

  49. 49.

    Chen (2019). Forthcoming. <https://ssrn.com/abstract=3302507>. A. Liptak, Sent to Prison by a Software Program’s Secret Algorithms, The New York Times (2017).

  50. 50.

    Tegmark (2017).

  51. 51.

    E. Yudkowsky, Creating Friendly AI 1.0: The Analysis and Design of Benevolent Goal Architectures, (2001), <singinst.org/CFAI.html>. H. de Garis, The Artilect War: Cosmists Vs. Terrans (2005).

  52. 52.

    M. Anderson & S. L. Anderson, Machine Ethics (2011), pp. 7–13.

  53. 53.

    Scherer (2016), p. 367.

  54. 54.

    UDHR Preamble: “Whereas recognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family is the foundation of freedom, justice and peace in the world,” ICCPR, Preamble, “The States Parties to the present Covenant, Considering that, in accordance with the principles proclaimed in the Charter of the United Nations, recognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family is the foundation of freedom, justice and peace in the world”.

  55. 55.

    The issue is further mentioned in the concluding remarks of the book.

References

  • Adams D (2005) The prohibition of widespread rape as jus cogens. San Diego Int Law J 6:357

    Google Scholar 

  • Alston P (1984) Conjuring up new human rights: a proposal for quality control. Am J Int Law 78:607 et seq

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson RJ (2010) Reimagining human rights law: toward global regulation of transnational corporations. Denver Univ Law Rev 88:183

    Google Scholar 

  • Bassiouni MC (2001) Universal jurisdiction for international crimes: historical perspectives and contemporary practice. Vanderbilt J Int Law 42:81

    Google Scholar 

  • Brownlie I (1979) Principles of public international law, 3rd edn. Oxford University Press, p 512

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan A (2004) Justice, legitimacy and self-determination, moral foundations of international law. Oxford University Press, p 119

    Google Scholar 

  • Byers M (1999) Custom, power and the power of rules: international relations and customary international law. Cambridge University Press, p 194

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carozza (2003) “My Friend is a Stranger”: the death penalty and the global ius commune of human rights. Tex Law Rev 81:1031

    Google Scholar 

  • Carozza PG (2008) Human dignity and judicial interpretation of human rights: a reply. Eur J Int Law 19(5):931

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cassese A (1986) International law in a divided world. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 377–379

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassese A (2012) For an enhanced role of jus cogens. In: Cassese A (ed) Realizing Utopia: the future of international law. Oxford University Press, p 166

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chen D (2019) Machine learning and the rule of law. In: Livermore M, Rockmore D (eds) Computational analysis of law

    Google Scholar 

  • Conklin WE (2012) The peremptory norms of the international community. Eur J Int Law 23:837

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crawford J (2002) The International Law Commission’s articles on state responsibility: introduction, text, and commentaries. Cambridge University Press, pp 148–150, 158–160

    Google Scholar 

  • Crawford J (2006) Creation of states in international law. Clarendon Press, p 102

    Google Scholar 

  • Criddle EJ, Decent EF (2009) A fiduciary theory of jus cogens. Yale J Int Law 34:331

    Google Scholar 

  • Domingo R (2012) The new global human community. Chic J Int Law 12(2):563

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitzmaurice G (1973) The future of public international law and of the international legal system in the circumstances of today. Institut De Droit International, p 323

    Google Scholar 

  • Janis MW (2003) An introduction to international law. Aspen Publishers, pp 62–63

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamminga MT (1992) Inter-state accountability for violations of human rights. University of Pennsylvania Press, p 163

    Google Scholar 

  • Ogilvy G (2009) Belhas V. Ya’alon: the case for a jus cogens exception to the foreign sovereign immunities act. J Int Bus Law 8:169

    Google Scholar 

  • Omohundro S (2008) The basic AI drives. In: Wang P, Goertzel B, Franklin S (eds) Artificial General Intelligence 2008: proceedings of the first AGI conference, pp 483–492

    Google Scholar 

  • Orakhelashvili A (2005) The impact of peremptory norms on the interpretation and application of United Nations Security Council Resolutions. Eur J Int Law 16:59

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parker K, Neylon LB (1989) Jus cogens: compelling the law of human rights. Hastings Int Comp Law Rev 12:414

    Google Scholar 

  • Perkins SC (1992) Guide to researching international human rights law. Case West Reserve J Int Law 24:379

    Google Scholar 

  • Petsche M (2010) Jus cogens as a vision of the international legal order. Penn State Int Law Rev 29:233

    Google Scholar 

  • Provost R (2004) International human rights and humanitarian law. Cambridge University Press, pp 16–17

    Google Scholar 

  • Rozakis CL (1976) The concept of jus cogens in the law of treaties. North-Holland Publications Co., Amsterdam, p 1

    Google Scholar 

  • Scherer MU (2016) Regulating artificial intelligence systems: risks, challenges, competencies, and strategies. Harv J Law Technol 29:353 et seq

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzenberger G (1965) International jus cogens? Tex Law Rev 43:455

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwebel SM (1991) Human rights in the world court. Vanderbilt J Transnatl Law 24:945

    Google Scholar 

  • Shleton D (2006) Normative hierarchy in international law. Am J Int Law 100:291

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spagnoli F (2008) The globalization of human rights law: why do human rights need international law? Tex Wesleyan Law Rev 14:317

    Google Scholar 

  • Spijkers O (2009–2010) What’s running the world: global values, international law, and the United Nations. Interdisciplinary J Hum Rights Law 4:77

    Google Scholar 

  • Stamatopoulou E (1999) The importance of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights in the past and future of the United Nation’s Human Rights efforts. ILSA J Int Comp Law 5:281

    Google Scholar 

  • Tams CJ (2005) Enforcing obligations erga omnes in international law. Cambridge University Press, New York, p 141

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tegmark M (2017) Life 3.0, being human in the age of artificial intelligence. Random House, Grk. Edition

    Google Scholar 

  • Teng Y-S (2012) Chapter 9 who is afraid of human rights? A Taiwanese perspective. IUS Gentium 16:155

    Google Scholar 

  • Trnavci G (2005) The meaning and scope of the law of nations in the context of the Alien Tort claims act and international law. Univ Pa J Int Econ Law 26:194

    Google Scholar 

  • Verdross A (1966) Jus dispositivum and jus cogens in international law. Am J Int Law 60:55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisburd AM (1995) The emptiness of the concept of jus cogens, as illustrated by the war in Bosnia-Herzegovina. Mich J Int Law 17:1

    Google Scholar 

  • Weston BH (2008) Human rights and nation-building in cross-cultural settings. Maine Law Rev 60:318

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Tzimas, T. (2021). AI and Human Rights. In: Legal and Ethical Challenges of Artificial Intelligence from an International Law Perspective. Law, Governance and Technology Series(), vol 46. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-78585-7_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-78585-7_6

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-78584-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-78585-7

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics