Skip to main content

On the Performance of Axiom Systems

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Axiomatic Thinking II

Abstract

One of the aims of proof theory is to calibrate the strength of axiom systems by invariants. According to Gödel’s discoveries these invariants will in general not be finite but rather transfinite objects. Pioneering work in this direction had been done by Gerhard Gentzen who characterized the axiom system for Peano arithmetic by the transfinite ordinal \({\varepsilon _0}\). In this paper we try to develop a general framework for characterizing ordinals of axiom systems and study to what extend these ordinals embody a measure for their performance.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    By the elementary language of a structure we understand the basis language of \(\mathfrak {M}\). This is in principle always a first-order language. However, it does not exclude many sorted first-order languages, e.g. weak second-order languages.

  2. 2.

    The properties of the ordinal \(\pi ^{\mathfrak M}\) are studied in [31]. In case that the structure \({\mathfrak M}\) is the structure \({\mathfrak N}\) of arithmetic, we get \(\pi ^{\mathfrak N}=\omega _1^{\hbox {\tiny CK}}\).

  3. 3.

    This theorem, in a different formulation, already appears in [15].

  4. 4.

    By a pseudo \(\Pi _{1}^{1}\)-sentence we understand a formula in the elementary language of \({\mathfrak M}\), which must not contain free first-order variables but may well contain free second-order variables. Semantically pseudo \(\Pi _{1}^{1}\)-sentences are treated as \(\Pi _{1}^{1}\)-sentences.

  5. 5.

    That similarly \(\pi ^\mathfrak {M}\) is characteristic rather for an universe above \(\mathfrak {M}\) than for \({\mathfrak M}\) itself follows from Sect. 5 in [31].

  6. 6.

    Therefore many of the mathematical results presented here are not new. Most of them are already contained in [33] but are presented here in a different context.

  7. 7.

    Cf. Definition 3.25 and Note 3.30.

  8. 8.

    \(\pi ^\mathfrak {M}\) corresponds to \(o(\Gamma )\) if \(\Gamma \) is the least Spector class above \(\mathfrak {M}\) (cf. Theorems 3.32 and 3.34).

  9. 9.

    Therefore, in some sense, we are selling “old wine in new skins”. Nevertheless we decided to include—at least extended sketches of—many of the old proofs. First, of course, to make the paper more self-contained and thus retain the survey character of the paper. Secondly because in many cases the central ideas of the proofs are helpful (or even needed) to make our approach transparent.

  10. 10.

    Here one should observe that the spectrum of an axiomatization \(\textsf{ID}_{\nu }({\textsf{T}})\) for \({\mathfrak M}_{\nu }\) also comprises the ordinal \(\pi ^{{\mathfrak M}_{\nu }}(\textsf{ID}_{\nu }({\textsf{T}}))\).

  11. 11.

    Introduced in Sect. 3.3.3.

  12. 12.

    A more elaborated sketch is in [33].

  13. 13.

    For a complete proof cf. e.g. [31] Theorem 4.4.

  14. 14.

    By an axiomatization of \({\mathfrak M}\) we understand a set \(\textsf{T}\) of \({\mathscr {L}}(\mathfrak {M})\)-sentences such that \(\mathfrak {M}\models \textsf{T}\).

  15. 15.

    This is just because any axiom system \(\textsf{T}\) is consistent iff there is a formula F such that \(\textsf{T}\not \vdash F\).

  16. 16.

    A full proof is given in [1].

  17. 17.

    This implies that the well-ordering on the countable domain of \({\mathfrak M}\) is elementarily definable.

  18. 18.

    Cf. Sects. 5.3 and 5.4 in [31].

  19. 19.

    To what extend the ordinal also has a meaning for the ground structure \(\mathfrak {M}\) will be briefly touched in Sect. 3.5.

  20. 20.

    Rumor has it that this observation is due to Kreisel. Unfortunately I know no reference.

  21. 21.

    This is familiar from “Reverse Mathematics” as, e.g. presented in [38]. The increasing strength of the axiom systems treated there is due to additional set-existence axioms.

  22. 22.

    To distinguish Analysis in the meaning of “Real Analysis” from analysis in concepts such as “ordinal analysis” we capitalize Analysis, whenever we mean it in the former sense.

  23. 23.

    Spector classes are introduced in [24] Chap. 9.

  24. 24.

    In abuse of notation we will often use \({\vec x}\in R\) and \(R({\vec x})\) synonymously.

  25. 25.

    For strictly acceptable structures \(\mathfrak {M}\) and acceptable axiom systems \(\textsf{T}\) which prove Weak König’s Lemma we always have \(\delta ^{\mathfrak M}(\textsf{T})=\kappa ^{\mathfrak M}(\textsf{T})\) (cf. [30] Thm. 6.7).

  26. 26.

    The lack of direct access to ordinals in \({\mathscr {L}}^2(\mathfrak {M})\) is one of the reasons why ordinal analysis shifted from the study of analytical universes to the study of set-theoretic universes in which ordinal numbers occur naturally (cf. [32] for a brief overview).

  27. 27.

    The theory of fixed points is studied in [25]. We will, however, by far not exhaust the very general approach in [25].

  28. 28.

    See [24, 25] for details.

  29. 29.

    Cf. [25] Sect. 8.

  30. 30.

    Cf. [36].

  31. 31.

    Although some proof-theoretic ordinals are known via embeddings into set-theoretic universes.

  32. 32.

    Hence the notation \(\kappa ^\mathfrak {M}_{\mu +1}\).

  33. 33.

    Cf. e.g. [27] Sect. 7.2.

  34. 34.

    The proof of the modification follows in principle the same pattern as the proof of Theorem 3.14. Because of the more blurred estimate \(2^\alpha \) it is even a bit easier and does not need the notion of co-enumeration. However, the extra 2-power is indispensable.

  35. 35.

    An assumption that will be substantiated later.

  36. 36.

    This axiom system is essentially the axiom system for iterated inductive definitions as introduced by Sol Feferman in [8].

  37. 37.

    Cf. [22].

  38. 38.

    Cf. e.g. [8, 11, 10] and the bibliographic notes given there.

  39. 39.

    Observe that \(\mu \) in the derived formula stands for the ordinal notation and \(\mu \) in the derivation height for its order-type in \(\prec \).

  40. 40.

    The idea to control semi-formal derivations by ordinal operators has been introduced by Wilfried Buchholz in [5] as a simplification of local predictivity which has been used in [26].

  41. 41.

    By \(\aleph \) we denote the enumerating function of the infinite cardinals. As usual we write \(\aleph _\mu \) instead of \(\aleph (\mu )\).

  42. 42.

    This is the familiar diagonal argument.

  43. 43.

    Cf. e.g. [24] Theorem 2B.1.

  44. 44.

    Cf. [5] for a survey and further citations.

  45. 45.

    The assumption that \(\nu +1\) is among the generators of \(\mathcal{H}\) is usually omitted. For example, I omitted it in [33]. This is harmless since it suffices to know that (3.24) is provable with an upper bound \(\Omega _{\nu }+\Omega _{1}\), which is operator controlled.

  46. 46.

    Cf. Sect. 3.4.2.

  47. 47.

    More details are in [33] Theorem 8.4.

  48. 48.

    One of the “simplest” examples for a theory which is not simple is \({\textsc {ID}}_1\) (i.e. \(\textsf{ID}_{1}({\mathord {\textsc {PA}}})\)). Its spectrum consists of two points \(\{\Psi _{\Omega _1}({\varepsilon _{\Omega _{1}+1}}),\varepsilon _{\Omega _{1}+1}\} \).

  49. 49.

    In case that the notation for \(\alpha \) needs n-ary Veblen functions it is wise to count also these functions among the generating functions of \(\mathcal{H}\). This is, however, not absolutely necessary. Even in our definition of \(\mathcal{H}\) the Veblen functions \(\varphi _{\xi }\) for \(\xi >0\) are dispensable in principle. These Veblen functions can be expressed in terms of the \(\Psi \)-functions. However, the then obtained results look somewhat weird, very unfamiliar and thus much less attractive (and are therefore also more difficult to read and to memorize).

  50. 50.

    Examples could be systems in weak second-order logic, e.g. (\(\Delta ^1_1\)-CA).

  51. 51.

    Cf. [19].

  52. 52.

    As an example the Peano axioms suffice to prove the properties of \(\mathcal{H}^{\Gamma _{\Omega _{\nu }+1}}(0)\).

  53. 53.

    Recall that an axiom system is simple, if its spectrum is a singleton.

  54. 54.

    Recall that in general we have no ordinals in \({\mathfrak M}_{\mu }\) but have to represent them by elements in \(O_\mu \) as discussed in Sect. 3.3.3.1.

  55. 55.

    Cf. Sect. 3.3.2.2.

  56. 56.

    Without having checked that we conjecture that also the “No Enhancement Theorem” can be generalized to this situation.

  57. 57.

    A more detailed proof sketch can be found in [33].

  58. 58.

    E.g. \(\Phi (n):=3^{n+2}\) is sufficiently increasing for the basis structure \({\mathfrak N}\).

  59. 59.

    Cf. [7].

  60. 60.

    Such a result has been first obtained by Andreas Weiermann. (Cf. [40, 2]).

  61. 61.

    The intersection with \(\Omega _{1}\) is of course superfluous and should only illustrate the bridge to the previous results.

References

  1. Arnold Beckmann and Wolfram Pohlers. Application of cut–free infinitary derivations to generalized recursion theory. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 94: 1–19, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Benjamin Blankertz and Andreas Weiermann. How to characterize provably total functions by the Buchholz operator method. Number 6 in Lecture Notes in Logic. Springer-Verlag, Heidelberg/New York, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Jane Bridge. A simplification of the Bachmann method for generating large countable ordinals. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 40: 171–185, 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Wilfried Buchholz. A simplified version of local predicativity. In Peter Aczel, Harold Simmons, and Stanley S. Wainer, editors, Proof Theory, pages 115–147, Cambridge, July 1992. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Wilfried Buchholz. A survey on ordinal notations around the Bachmann–Howard ordinal. In [20], pages 71–100.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Wilfried Buchholz, Solomon Feferman, Wolfram Pohlers, and Wilfried Sieg, editors. Iterated Inductive Definitions and Subsystems of Analysis: Recent Proof-Theoretical Studies. Number 897 in Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, Heidelberg/New York, 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Wilfried Buchholz, E. Adam Cichon, and Andreas Weiermann. A uniform approach to fundamental sequences and hierarchies. Mathematical Logic Quarterly, 40: 273–286, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Solomon Feferman. Formal theories for transfinite iteration of generalized inductive definitions and some subsystems of analysis. In Akiko Kino, John Myhill, and Richard E. Vesley, editors, Intuitionism and Proof Theory, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, pages 303–326, Amsterdam, August 1970. North-Holland Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Solomon Feferman. Preface: How we got from there to here. In [6], pages 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Solomon Feferman. The proof theory of classical and constructive inductive definitions. A forty year saga, 1968–2008. In [37], pages 79–95.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Solomon Feferman and Wilfried Sieg. Inductive definitions and subsystems of analysis. In [6], pages 16–77.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Kentaro Fujimoto. Notes on some second order systems of inductive definitions and \({\Pi }^1_1\)–comprehensions and relevant subsystems of set theory. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 166: 409–463, 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Gerhard Gentzen. Die Widerspruchsfreiheit der reinen Zahlentheorie. Mathematische Annalen, 112: 493–565, 1936.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Gerhard Gentzen. Neue Fassung des Widerspruchsfreiheitsbeweises für die reine Zahlentheorie. Forschungen zur Logik und Grundlegung der exakten Wissenschaften, 4: 19–44, 1938.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Gerhard Gentzen. Beweisbarkeit und Unbeweisbarkeit von Anfangsfällen der transfiniten Induktion in der reinen Zahlentheorie. Mathematische Annalen, 119: 140–161, 1943.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Kurt Gödel. Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der ‘Prinzipia Mathematica’ und verwandter Systeme. Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, 38: 173–198, 1931.

    Google Scholar 

  17. David Hilbert. Mathematische Probleme. Archiv für Mathematik und Physik, 1. 3. Reihe: 44–63, 1901.

    Google Scholar 

  18. David Hilbert. Axiomatisches Denken. Mathematische Annalen, 78: 405–415, 1918.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Gerhard Jäger. Metapredicative and explicit Mahlo: a proof-theoretic perspective. In Rene Cori, Alexander Razborov, Stevo Todorcevic, and Carol Wood, editors, Logic Colloquium ’00, volume 19 of Lecture Notes in Logic, pages 272–293, Wellesley, MA, 2005. AK Peters.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Gerhard Jäger and Wilfried Sieg, editors. Feferman on Foundations, Outstanding Contributions to Logic, Heidelberg, Berlin, 2017. Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Georg Kreisel. Generalized inductive definitions. Reports of seminars on the foundation of Analysis. (Stanford Report), mimeographed, section III, 1963a.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Georg Kreisel. Theory of free choice sequences of natural numbers. Reports of seminars on the foundation of Analysis. (Stanford Report), mimeographed, section IV, 1963b.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Michael Möllerfeld. Systems of inductive definitions. PhD Thesis, Münster, 2003.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Yiannis N. Moschovakis. Elementary Induction on Abstract Structures. Number 77 in Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics. North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam, 1974a.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Yiannis N. Moschovakis. On nonmonotone inductive definability. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 82: 39–83, 1974b.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Wolfram Pohlers. Proof-theoretical analysis of ID\(_{\nu }\) by the method of local predicativity. In [6], pages 261–357.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Wolfram Pohlers. Computability theory of hyperarithmetical sets. Lecture notes (www.uni-muenster.de/imperia/logik/skripte), Westfälische Wilhelms–Universität, Münster, 1996.

  28. Wolfram Pohlers. Subsystems of set theory and second order number theory. In Samuel R. Buss, editor, Handbook of Proof Theory, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, pages 209–335. North-Holland Publishing Company, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Wolfram Pohlers. Ordinal analysis of non–monotone \(\Pi ^0_1\)–definable inductive definitions. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 156: 160–169, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Wolfram Pohlers. Proof Theory. The first step into impredicativity. Universitext. Springer-Verlag, Berlin/Heidelberg/New York, 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Wolfram Pohlers. Semi–formal calculi and their applications. In Reinhard Kahle and Michael Rathjen, editors, Gentzen’s Centenary: The quest for consistency, pages 317–354. Springer-Verlag, 2015.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Wolfram Pohlers. From subsystems of Analysis to subsystems of set theory. In Reinhard Kahle, Thomas Strahm, and Thomas Studer, editors, Advances in Proof Theory, Progress in Computer Science and Applied Logic 28, pages 319–338. Birkhäuser Verlag, 2016.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Wolfram Pohlers. Iterated inductive definitions revisited. In [20], pages 209–251.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Michael Rathjen. Untersuchungen zu Teilsystemen der Zahlentheorie zweiter Stufe und der Mengenlehre mit einer zwischen \({\Delta }^1_2-CA und {\Delta }^1_2-CA+BI\) liegenden Beweisstärke. Dissertation, Westfälische Wilhelms-Universität, Münster, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Michael Rathjen. Investigations of subsystems of second order arithmetic and set theory in strength between \({\Pi }^1_1\)–CA and \({\Delta }_2^1\)–CA + BI: Part I. In [37], pages 363–439.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Wayne Richter. Recursively Mahlo ordinals and inductive definitions. In Robin O. Gandy and C. M. E. Yates, editors, Logic Colloquium ’69, number 61 in Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, pages 273–288, Amsterdam, August 1971. North-Holland Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ralf Schindler, editor. Ways of Proof Theory. Number 2 in Ontos Mathematical Logic. Ontos Verlag, Frankfurt, Paris, Lancaster, New Brunswick, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Stephen G. Simpson. Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic. Springer-Verlag, Berlin/Heidelberg/New York, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Clifford Spector. Provably recursive functionals of analysis: a consistency proof of analysis by an extension of principles formulated in current intuitionistic mathematics. In James C. E. Dekker, editor, Recursive Function Theory, number 5 in Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics, pages 1–27, Providence, April 1962. American Mathematical Society.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Andreas Weiermann. How to characterize provably total functions by local predicativity. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 61: 52–69, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I want to thank the anonymous referee for her or his criticism and the many extremely helpful comments and corrections.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wolfram Pohlers .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Pohlers, W. (2022). On the Performance of Axiom Systems. In: Ferreira, F., Kahle, R., Sommaruga, G. (eds) Axiomatic Thinking II. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-77799-9_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics