Skip to main content

Chapter 8 Imperfect Legal Rights

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Architecture of Rights
  • 138 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter offers a functionalist explanation of what is wrong with unenforceable (yet valid) legal rights. Such cases are ‘imperfect’ because they lack the means for securing officials’ binding determinations of their existence, content, and/or scope. Hence, right-holders—and correlative duty-bearers—lack (the grounds for obtaining) sufficient information and guidance about what their respective legal positions mean and entail.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    E.g., Terry (1884: 116–9); Salmond (1902: 223); Vinogradoff (1924: 61–2); Feinberg (1980: 150); MacCormick (2007: 122–3, 129).

  2. 2.

    E.g., Martin (1993: 60, 83–4).

  3. 3.

    See Matthew Kramer, Chapter 5 note 38; Chapter 7 note 53.

  4. 4.

    Raz (1996: 256–7). For discussions of hypothetical systems with legally unenforceable rights, see Reiff (2005: 47–9).

  5. 5.

    There are different senses of ‘imperfect rights’ and ‘imperfect duties’ in the philosophy of rights literature beyond that of rights being imperfect for being unenforceable in some way or other. For example, a duty is sometimes deemed to be imperfect: for lacking a correlative right (e.g., Etinson (2013: 465)); because the holder lacks a liberty or claim by which to fulfil it (cf. White (1984: 58)); or because it is unenforceable (e.g., Varden (2011: 280)). Sometimes, a right is also deemed imperfect for altogether lacking a correlative duty. E.g., MacCormick (2007: 123); cf. White (1984: 71). See also Terry (1884: 116, 119).

  6. 6.

    This candidate ‘point’ of rights need not be reducible to will vindication or protection per se and need not be framed in terms of a ‘theory’ of rights either.

  7. 7.

    Raz (1996: 256).

  8. 8.

    Martin (1993: 83).

  9. 9.

    To my mind, no jurisprudential account (and not simply in the philosophy of rights literature) has, to date, provided an adequate account of the extent to which a right, rather than just the correlative duty, provides duty-bearers with information to guide them—especially if and when the correlative positions are not deemed to be identical in content. See also Chapter 2 note 87 for some worries about how rights, rather than duties, contrain others.

  10. 10.

    It is not a complete explanation because it does not explain what would be ‘defective’ about lacking waiver powers for primary rights or enforcement powers for tertiary rights. For an argument that could be characterised as showing what would be defective about a legal system lacking tertiary rights (and, I would add, their enforcement), see Hughes (2013: 196).

  11. 11.

    More specifically, Raz’s argument aims to show that sanctions are ‘inessential’ to ‘our’ concept, LAW. See Raz (1999: 157–61); Chapter 1 note 59.

  12. 12.

    Co-trustees who (have the right to) seek direction from a court about the content or scope of their duties or powers, via an original summons, need not use their imaginations here.

  13. 13.

    See Raz (2009b: 108); Chapter 4 note 112. Alternatively, the parties may just seek counsel from lawyers about what their legal rights and duties entail. They might do this for both a substantive answer and as a ground to try to avoid future liability.

  14. 14.

    For example, see Pavlos Eleftheriadis’ view discussed in Chapter 3 note 32 and the accompanying text. Eleftheriadis (2008: 123–8, 168).

  15. 15.

    Furthermore, even if social practices or concepts ought to be interpreted in light of their purpose or function, that does not take us all the way to the Normativists’ (e.g., Ronald Dworkin and John Finnis’) claim that one must engage in moral or political evaluation and justification in order to explain that function. See Dickson (2004: 142–3).

  16. 16.

    What if the legal right in question is not a moral one? A person who finds a given legal RCTD morally repugnant might not comply with its requirements. Irrespective of whether legal duties are exclusionary reasons or merely weighty ones, there may be overriding moral or prudential reasons militating against conformity. This may also be the case even when the duty is a moral(ly acceptable) one.

Bibliography

  • Dickson J., ‘Methodology in Jurisprudence: A Critical Survey’ (2004) 10 Legal Theory 117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eleftheriadis P., Legal Rights (OUP 2008).

    Google Scholar 

  • Etinson A., Human Rights, Claimability and the Uses of Abstraction’ (2013) 25(4) Utilitas 463.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg J., ‘The Nature and Value of Rights’, in Rights, Justice, and the Bounds of Liberty: Essays in Social Philosophy (Princeton University Press 1980).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes R., ‘Law and the Entitlement to Coerce’, in Wil Waluchow & Stefan Sciaraffa (eds), Philosophical Foundations of the Nature of Law (OUP 2013).

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick N., Institutions of Law: An Essay in Legal Theory (OUP 2007).

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin R., A System of Rights (OUP 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J., Practical Reason and Norms (2nd edn, OUP 1999).

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J., Ethics in the Public Domain: Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics (revised edn, OUP 1996).

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J., The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality (2nd edn, OUP 2009) [‘Raz (2009b)’].

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmond J., Jurisprudence, or The Theory of the Law (1st edn, Stevens & Haynes 1902).

    Google Scholar 

  • Terry H., Some Leading Principles of Anglo-American Law Expounded with a View To its Arrangement and Codification (T & J W Johnson & Co 1884).

    Google Scholar 

  • Varden H., ‘Duties, Perfect and Imperfect’, in Deen K. Chatterjee (ed), Encyclopedia of Global Justice (Springer 2011).

    Google Scholar 

  • Vinogradoff P., ‘The Foundations of a Theory of Rights’ (1924) 34(1) Yale L. J. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  • White A., Rights (Clarendon Press 1984).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Frydrych, D. (2021). Chapter 8 Imperfect Legal Rights. In: The Architecture of Rights. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-76039-7_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-76039-7_8

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-76038-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-76039-7

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics