Skip to main content

Intersectional Metasemantic Adequacy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Metasemantics and Intersectionality in the Misinformation Age
  • 171 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter first introduces and argues for a constraint on metasemantic theorizing called General Metasemantic Adequacy, which says that any acceptable metasemantic theory must comport with our strongest first-order commitments, including our strongest first-order political commitments. Then, by taking this general principle together with the theory of intersectionality described in Chap. 8, I argue for another more specific constraint on metasemantic theorizing, Intersectional Metasemantic Adequacy. This constraint says that any acceptable metasemantics must comport with first-order truths about intersectionality, including most crucially facts about misinformation, misrepresentation, and the spread of false beliefs that undergird the matrix of domination.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Kamp (1981) for a canonical statement of this view, which is an evolution of Tarski’s (1933) concept of truth for formalized languages.

  2. 2.

    For extensive discussions about what metasemantics is, see the edited collection Burgess and Sherman (2014).

  3. 3.

    The theory developed was most centrally based on my readings of Collective (1977), Lorde (1984), Crenshaw (1989), Crenshaw (1990), Collins (2002), and Collins & Bilge (2016).

  4. 4.

    Note that this is a constraint even for error theorists and non-cognitivists, insofar as they must do work to explain away or incorporate the strong prima facie semantic evidence that these statements have straightforward truth-conditions and, moreover, that they appear to be straightforwardly true. It is also true for deflationists.

  5. 5.

    See Code’s (2012) discussion of ‘we-saying,’ which highlights the political nature of asserting what ‘our’ views are.

  6. 6.

    For a thorough discussion of disquotational schemas, including a thorough discussion of the difficulties of making a fully disquotational semantic theory, see David (1994). I am not proposing that the semantics for English is exhausted by disquotational principles. My semantics is not deflationary, it’s model-theoretic. My point is that any semantics for English must satisfy the disquotational schemas in straightforward cases. It must entail, for example, that “Trans women are women” is true if and only if trans women are women. But unlike a deflationary disquotational semantics, I am not saying this biconditional exhaustively specifies the semantics of that sentence.

  7. 7.

    Bettcher (2013). See also Bettcher (2009) for development of related themes.

  8. 8.

    To give Bettcher (2013) the full attention her work deserves, I should emphasize that my view fails to come to terms with certain elements of her view. Her theory is one on which the metaphysical construction of gender is done differently within different cultures, and so there is an attendant metaphysical difference between the way gender is constructed within the mainstream culture as opposed to the way it is constructed within trans-friendlier communities. The meaning conflict, the struggle between the two ways of using the word “woman,” is part of this larger conflict between two ways of constructing gender. Bettcher draws on Lugones (1987) in describing different worlds of sense in which we can find ourselves, some trans friendly and some transphobic. It is part of the trans person’s struggle that the world of sense in which they have the gender they identify as is constantly antagonized and sometimes destroyed by enforcers whose role is to impose the cis-normative world of sense on everyone. For Bettcher, conflicting meanings are part of this larger conflict between different cultures.

    I am not arguing against this picture of the struggle for trans inclusion within mainstream consciousness. I do believe there are different cultures that are in a sense at war with one another, that transforming the mainstream culture to accommodate trans friendly worldviews is crucial for the survival and flourishing of trans folks, and that trans gender identities can be delegitimated or even metaphysically destabilized by hostile enforcers who are wielding the power of a cis-supremacist matrix of domination. I want to disentangle these phenomena from a theory of metasemantics in the following way. I don’t think we must see this process as one in which the enforcers speak truly when they claim that trans women are men. We can see such linguistic violence as an attack on the metaphysical underpinnings of trans women’s identities while interpreting the shared public language in such a way as to recognize their statements as false, as ideological misinformation about gender that spreads ignorance and misunderstanding about gender and its relation to biology. A grocery store clerk acting as a cis enforcer might destabilize a trans woman’s gender in that context by calling her a “man,” even if what the clerk says is (unbeknownst to her) false.

  9. 9.

    For an extensive discussion of this idea, see Dotson (2013).

  10. 10.

    This reply owes its form in rough outline to Annas (2008) in her reply to an analogous objection to virtue ethics.

References

  • Annas, J. (2008). Virtue Ethics and the Charge of Egoism. Morality and Self-interest, 205, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bettcher, T. M. (2009). Trans Identities and First-person Authority. You’ve Changed: Sex Reassignment and Personal Identity, 1, 98–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bettcher, T. M. (2013). Trans Women and the Meaning of ‘Woman’.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1979). Individualism and the Mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4, 73–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2010). Origins of Objectivity. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Burgess, A., & Sherman, B. (Eds.). (2014). Metasemantics: New Essays on the Foundations of Meaning. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H. (2018). Fixing Language: An Essay on Conceptual Engineering. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Code, L. (2012). Taking Subjectivity into Account. In Education, Culture and Epistemological Diversity (pp. 85–100). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Collective, C. R. (1977/1983). The Combahee River Collective Statement. Home girls: A Black Feminist Anthology, 1 264-274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, P. H. (2002). Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness, and the Politics of Empowerment. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crenshaw, K. (1989/2018). Demarginalizing the Intersection of Race and Sex: A Black Feminist Critique of Antidiscrimination Doctrine, Feminist Theory, and Antiracist Politics [1989]. In Feminist Legal Theory (pp. 57-80). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crenshaw, K. (1990). Mapping the Margins: Intersectionality, Identity Politics, and Violence Against Women of Color. Stan. L. Rev., 43, 1241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • David, M. A. (1994). Correspondence and Disquotation: An Essay on the Nature of Truth. Oxford University Press on Demand.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dotson, K. (2013). How Is This Paper Philosophy? Comparative Philosophy, 3(1), 121–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1978/1990). The history of sexuality: An introduction. Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1980). Power/knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972-1977. Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S., & Haslanger, S. A. (2012). Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hill, C. S. (2002). Thought and World: An Austere Portrayal of Truth, Reference, and Semantic Correspondence. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, K. (2016). Amelioration and Inclusion: Gender Identity and the Concept of Woman. Ethics, 126(2), 394–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H. (1981). A Theory of Truth and Semantic Representation. Formal semantics-the Essential Readings, 1, 189–222.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorde, A. (1984/2020). Sister Outsider: Essays and Speeches. Penguin Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lugones, M. (1987). Playfulness,“world”-travelling, and Loving Perception. Hypatia, 2(2), 3–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. (1933/1956). The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages. Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics, 2(152-278), 7.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Derek Egan Anderson .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Anderson, D.E. (2021). Intersectional Metasemantic Adequacy. In: Metasemantics and Intersectionality in the Misinformation Age. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-73339-1_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics