Skip to main content

Partitives, Comparatives and Proportional Measurement

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Measurements, Numerals and Scales

Part of the book series: Palgrave Studies in Pragmatics, Language and Cognition ((PSPLC))

  • 268 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter discusses the interaction between partitive constructions and the grammar of measurement. It begins by reviewing Solt 2018, in particular Solt’s account of why partitive constructions force proportional interpretations when combining with many but yet permit both proportional and direct comparisons when combining with more (Solt’s Generalization). To capture this pattern, Solt hypothesizes that partitive phrases are interpreted as partial measure functions, restricted by their nominal complement. However, Solt’s account critically relies on limiting grammatically accessible proportional scales to those that can be derived from a restricted, partial measure function. Unfortunately for Solt (2018), there are grammatically accessible proportional scales that go far beyond this limit (see Bale and Schwarz 2020). In fact, the accessibility of such scales in non-partitive constructions demonstrates that the limitation imposed on scales in partitives is much stronger than originally thought. This chapter proposes that Solt’s theory can be salvaged by hypothesizing that partitive phrases always relativize their degree interpretations to an underspecified scalar “limit,” i.e. the highest or lowest degree within the range of a restricted measure function. Such a theory, if on the right track, might lend support to the idea that all mass noun denotations have a lower bound (as suggested in Chierchia 1998, 2010).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Solt (2015) argues that there is an additional operator in these types of constructions that captures the differences between many and few on the one hand and much and little on the other. The details are relevant for the overall semantic theory but pull us slightly off topic in terms of the focus of this chapter. For the sake of simplicity, I will not include such operators in the syntactic or semantic representations here, nor will I review the arguments for this additional operator.

  2. 2.

    For now, I will leave it open whether meas is sometimes phonologically realized as many/much (as argued in Bresnan 1973) or whether it is always phonologically null (as argued in Solt 2015).

  3. 3.

    Given time and space limitations, in this chapter I will only discuss examples with many and more. However, parallel observations hold for few and fewer.

  4. 4.

    There is more that can be said about the existence and uniqueness of such a partial order. Within a system like the ones proposed by Link (1983), Chierchia (1998), Barker (1998), an entity can participate in only one such “part-whole” relation that orders the domain of discourse. In other types of ontologies, an entity could be allowed to participate in more than one “part-whole” relations (e.g., Gillon 1992; Rothstein 2010).

  5. 5.

    The literature on how comparison classes influence a standard is vast, but see in particular the different implementations of this idea for adjectives in Bartsch and Vennemann (1972), Klein (1991), Kennedy and McNally (2005), Kennedy (2007), Bale (2011) and references therein. See the implementation of this idea with respect to many and few in Penka (2018), Romero (2015, 2016) and references therein.

  6. 6.

    Penka (2018) offers an almost identical account of this restriction, however she implements the restriction using focus structures rather than partial measure functions.

  7. 7.

    For any partial order \(\le \), if \(\mu _{\text {dim}}\) is monotonic with respect to \(\le \), then so is \(\mu _{\text {dim};z}\) and \(\mu _{\text {dim}_\%;z}\).

  8. 8.

    Such a reading is often called a reverse proportional reading (Westerståhl 1985; Herburger 1997) since it appears that the relevant entity in the denominator value is the number of applicants (i.e., the denotation of the VP) rather than the number of cooks (i.e., the denotation of the NP).

  9. 9.

    The motivation for this assumption has two sources. First, in adjectival comparisons, sometimes two different measure functions are overtly expressed as in [This table is longer than it is wide]. Second, sometimes there are overt instances of a second many/much morpheme in the than-clause, as in [I have more stuffed animals than how many you think I have].

References

  • Abbott, Barbara. 1996. Doing without a partitive constraint. In Partitives, 25–56. Berlin, Germany: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ahn, Dorothy, and Uli Sauerland. 2015. The grammar of relative measurement. In Semantics and linguistic theory (SALT), ed. Sarah D’Antonio, Mary Moroney, and Carol-Rose Little, volume 25, 125–142. Ithaca, NY: LSA and CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ahn, Dorothy, and Uli Sauerland. 2017. Measure constructions with relative measures: Towards a syntax of non-conservative construals. The Linguistic Review 34:215–248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bale, Alan. 2011. Scales and comparison classes. Natural Language Semantics 19:169–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bale, Alan, and David Barner. 2009. The interpretation of functional heads: Using comparatives to explore the mass/count distinction. Journal of Semantics 26:217–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bale, Alan, and Bernhard Schwarz. 2020. Proportional readings of many and few: The case for an underspecified measure function. Linguistic and Philosophy 43:673–699.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker, Chris. 1998. Partitives, double genitives and anti-uniqueness. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 16:679–717.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartsch, Renate, and Theo Vennemann. 1972. Semantic structures: A study in the relation between semantics and syntax. Frankfurt am Main: Athen aum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bresnan, Joan. 1973. Syntax of the comparative clause construction in English. Linguistic Inquiry 4:275–343.

    Google Scholar 

  • Büring, Daniel. 1996. A weak theory of strong readings. In Semantics and linguistic theory 6, ed. Teresa Galloway and Justin Spence, volume 6, 17–34. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University, CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, Gennaro. 1998. Plurality of mass nouns and the notion of “semantic parameter”. In Events and grammar, ed. Susan Rothstein, 53–104. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, Gennaro. 2010. Mass nouns, vagueness and semantic variation. Synthese 174:99–149.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cresswell, M. J. 1976. The semantics of degree. In Montague grammar, ed. B. Partee, 261–292. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillon, B. 1992. Towards a common semantics for English count and mass nouns. Linguistics and Philosophy 15:597–640.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hackl, Martin. 2000. Comparative quantifiers. Doctoral Dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herburger, Elena. 1997. Focus and weak noun phrases. Natural Language Semantics 5:53–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoeksema, Jacob. 1996. Floating quantifiers, partitives and distributivity. In Partitives, 57–106. Berlin, Germany: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Hoop, Helen. 1997. A semantic reanalysis of the partitive constraint. Lingua 103:151–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Hoop, Helen, and Jaume Solà. 1996. Determiners, context sets, and focus. In Proceedings of the Fourteenth West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. Jose Camacho, Lina Choueiri, and Maki Watanabe, 155–167. Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford Linguistics Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, Ray. 1977. X\(^{\prime }\)syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, Christopher. 1999. Projecting the adjective: The syntax and semantics of gradability and comparison. New York: Garland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, Christopher. 2007. Vagueness and grammar: The semantics of relative and absolute gradable adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy 30:1–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, Christopher, and Louise McNally. 2005. Scale structure, degree modification, and the semantics of gradable predicates. Language 81:345–381.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, Ewan. 1981. The interpretation of adjectival, nominal, and adverbial comparatives. In Formal methods in the study of language, ed. J. Groenendijk, T. Janssen, and M. Stokhof, 381–398. Amsterdam: Mathematical Center Tracts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, Ewan. 1991. Comparatives. In Semantik/semantics: An international handbook of contemporary research, ed. A. von Stechow and D. Wunderlich, 673–691. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladusaw, William. 1982. Semantic constraints on the English partitive construction. In Proceedings of First West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. Daniel Flickinger, Marlys Macken, and Nancy Wiegand, 231–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Link, Godehard. 1983. The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms: A lattice-theoretical approach. In Meaning, use and interpretation of language, ed. R. Baeuerle, C. Schwarze, and Arnim von Stechow, 302–323. Berlin: DeGruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, Barbara. 1989. Many quantifiers. In ESCOL 1988. Columbus: Ohio State University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penka, Doris. 2018. One many, many readings. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeuting 21, ed. Robert Trusswell, Chris Cummins, Caroline Heycock, Brian Rabern, and Hannah Rohde, 933–950. https://semanticsarchive.net.

  • Reed, Ann. 1996. Partitives, existentials, and partitive determiners. In Partitives, 143–178. Berlin, Germany: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romero, Maribel. 2015. The conservativity of many. In Proceedings of the 20th Amsterdam Colloquium, ed. Thomas Brochhagen, Floris Roelofsen, and Nadine Theiler, 20–29. Amsterdam: Institute for Logic, Language, and Computation (ILLC), University of Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romero, Maribel. 2016. Pos, -est, and reverse readings of many and most. In Proceedings of 46th Annual Meeting of the North East Linguistic Society (NELS 46), ed. Brandon Prickett and Christopher Hammerly, 141–154. GLSA (Graduate Linguistics Student Association), Department of Linguistics, University of Massachusetts. https://www.createspace.com/6604179.

  • Rothstein, Susan. 2010. Counting and the mass/count distinction. Journal of Semantics 27:343–397.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzschild, Roger. 2006. The role of dimensions in the syntax of noun phrases. Syntax 9:67–110.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selkirk, Elizabeth. 1977. Some remarks on noun phrase structure. In Formal syntax, ed. Peter Culicover, Tom Wasow, and Adrian Akmajian. New York, NY: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solt, Stephanie. 2009. The semantics of adjectives of quantity. Doctoral Dissertation, City University of New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solt, Stephanie. 2015. Q-adjectives and the semantics of quantity. Journal of Semantics 32:1–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solt, Stephanie. 2018. Proportional comparatives and relative scales. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 21, ed. Robert Truswell, Chris Cummins, Caroline Heycock, Brian Rabern, and Hannah Rohde, 1123–1140. Edinburgh: University of Edinburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Stechow, Arnim. 1984. Comparing semantic theories of comparison. Journal of Semantics 3:1–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellwood, Alexis. 2015. On the semantics of comparison across categories. Linguistics and Philosophy 38:67–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellwood, Alexis. 2018. Structure preservation in comparatives. In Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 28, ed. Katherine Blake, Forrest Davis, Sireemas Maspong, and Brynhildur Stefánsdóttir, 78–99. Linguistic Society of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westerståhl, Dag. 1985. Logical constants in quantifier languages. Linguistics and Philosophy 8:387–413.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Bale, A. (2022). Partitives, Comparatives and Proportional Measurement. In: Gotzner, N., Sauerland, U. (eds) Measurements, Numerals and Scales. Palgrave Studies in Pragmatics, Language and Cognition. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-73323-0_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-73323-0_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-73322-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-73323-0

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics