Skip to main content

Critical Theoretical Methodology for Nonideal Contributions to Bioethics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Applying Nonideal Theory to Bioethics

Part of the book series: Philosophy and Medicine ((PHME,volume 139))

  • 438 Accesses

Abstract

Karl Marx argued that the preferable starting point for influencing social practices is to understand their workings—not to simply moralize social systems through idealization. This thread in Marx informs contemporary critical social theories such as feminism and critical race theory. Such work attempts to diagnose and analyze internal contradictions, limitations, and dysfunctions in social structures as they actually are in order to connect them to normative dissatisfactions in lived experience. This critical theoretical methodology thus embodies what Charles Mills calls for in nonideal explanatory models that abstract without idealizing. In this chapter I argue that Marx’s theory of society, which informs his critique of political economy in Capital, offers bioethics a nonideal framework through which to analyze normative dissatisfactions in health care practice. What may appear to be moral problems or dilemmas in health care can be the result of, or significantly influenced by, structural patterns in health care’s material production—not its abstract moral content. Therefore, understanding health care structurally, as a set of productive practices within a larger systematic whole of capitalist production, can help diagnose systemic dysfunctions in health care’s material production that produce or make worse normative dissatisfactions of concern for bioethics. I call such morally significant structural dysfunctions social pathologies of health care, and contend that a Marx-informed bioethics can descriptively theorize structural bases of moral discontent and conflict in health care, and therein inform its social and political transformation for the better.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See, for instance, Oliver (1989), Anderson (1993), Radin (1993), Radin (1996), Dickenson (2007), and Phillips (2013).

  2. 2.

    And for a particularly scathing critique of Navarro’s work, see Reidy (1984).

  3. 3.

    See, for instance, Daniels (2008, 18).

  4. 4.

    See, for instance, Radin (1996, 79–83).

  5. 5.

    I use the term “Marxian” to refer to theorization in Marx’s texts themselves, while I use “Marxist” to refer more to work of theorists (and political or state actors) who follow Marx and attempt to elaborate (or realize) his ideas. Among such Marxist theorists are Rosa Luxemburg, Georg Lukács and Vladimir Lenin. To offer an analogy, Marxian is to Marxism as Benthamian is to utilitarianism. The former singles out one thinker’s work (Jeremy Bentham) and interpretations of it, where the latter names the broader movement of which that thinker is considered a founder or foundational. This is a worthwhile distinction to maintain for Marx, given that the theories and politics of subsequent Marxism(s) are often taken to be more or less identical to Marx’s thought. Comparing this to other founder-movement distinctions helps indicate potential errors in such false equivalence for the sake of doing theory.

  6. 6.

    The concept of social structure is increasingly theorized and utilized in work on gender and race, especially, to conceive of oppressive forces as interrelated and semi-independent of individual intentions or actions. Thus understanding racial or gendered oppression requires understanding the raced and gendered individual in relation to a larger set of social forces that work in concert—as a whole—to marginalize, dominate, or constrain. This echoes fundamental feminist insights in Marilyn Frye (1983, 1–16), which are utilized further in Anne Donchin (2010), Iris Marion Young (2011), and Sally Haslanger (2012, 2016). These authors are especially informative in my descriptions of social-relational structures in understanding social phenomena for normative social theory.

  7. 7.

    For a more detailed examination of Rawls’s distinction between ideal and nonideal theory, see John Simmons (2010).

  8. 8.

    Simmons (2010) notes that Rawls invokes Rousseau with this phrase (7).

  9. 9.

    I use such modifiers as “mainstream” in part to acknowledge that there are already bioethics scholars doing alternative nonideal work less subject to my critique. Indeed, the present volume is clear evidence of this, as are my numerous attempts to draw connections to such authors and theories. My critiques of bioethics do not claim to apply universally, but instead more to predominant thinkers and approaches, and to common underlying metatheoretical assumptions.

  10. 10.

    References to Marx’s Capital are often directed only at its first and best-known volume, which was the only volume published in Marx’s lifetime. It is focused primarily on the capitalist process of production. A posthumously published second volume (Marx 1992) analyzes processes of exchange and circulation in markets, and a third volume (Marx 1991) is especially concerned with finance capital and surplus value production in the cyclical workings of the capitalist system as a whole. Marx had originally planned six volumes in total for his Capital project that would include, among others, analyses of landed property, the state, international trade, and the world market (Heinrich 2013, 200).

  11. 11.

    Marx generally avoids outright normative or moral condemnation, in favor of more anormative description. The present chapter does not permit a deeper exploration of this tension, however. For an account of anti-normativity from Marx to Foucault, and a Foucauldian argument against normative political theorizing, see Kelly (2018). See also Seyla Benhabib (1986) on the methodological foundations of Marxist and critical theory, including its anormative dimensions in defetishizing and immanent critique.

  12. 12.

    It is worth noting that, despite not identifying as Marxist, the philosophy of economics might be moving closer to Marx on this claim—even if the field of economics itself is not following suit. In the introduction to the Oxford handbook of philosophy of economics, editors Harold Kincaid and Don Ross (2009) argue: “If it becomes widely recognized in economics, as we think it should, that methodological individualism is an ideological or philosophical prejudice rather than a scientifically justified principle, then an eventual fusion of economics and sociology seems to us more likely than the much-prophecied [sic] merger of economics and psychology” (18, [my emphasis]). Methodological individualism here refers precisely to the claim that social and economic phenomena are properly understood when reduced to individual actions and therein to the cognitive activity of individuals. Thus individual cognition, judgment, and action are taken as the underlying drivers of economics, and thus capitalism and society itself.

  13. 13.

    For an alternative to capitalism and a response to the “TINA argument” (“there is no alternative”), see Schweickart (1993, 2017).

  14. 14.

    See Althusser (2014) for a more detailed consideration of the Marxian notion of modes of production.

  15. 15.

    For contemporary Marxian approaches to social ontology, see Feenberg’s notion of Marx’s “philosophy of praxis” (2014) and Krier and Worrell (2016). For other contemporary approaches, see Sally Haslanger (2012, 2016) and her interlocutors (I believe that both discourses stand to benefit mutually from greater dialogue with one another).

  16. 16.

    This is significant because Marx’s work is often understood as having turned away from philosophy after his early humanistic work (such as the 1844 Economic and philosophical manuscripts) and turned toward purely descriptive social science in works like Capital. Yet the somewhat recent discovery and 1973 English translation of Grundrisse is widely said to help reveal the truly philosophical nature of his later work and its links to the early humanism.

  17. 17.

    On social ontological theory in Marx, see Michael Thompson (2016). For another insightful treatment of social ontology and social-structural explanations of phenomena, see Haslanger (2016).

  18. 18.

    I find Marilyn Frye’s (1983) theorization of oppression as analogous to a birdcage (1–16) to be especially insightful regarding this structural notion of gender, understood in Haslanger’s (2012) words as “a social category whose definition makes reference to a broad network of social relations” (86–7), or what I refer to here as a totality. To say that gender oppression is like a birdcage is precisely to say that its oppressive effects are only adequately grasped from a holistic vantage point. This reveals social oppression as a plurality of constrictive social forces working systematically or in concert, which can become invisible when examining only an individual barrier or setback.

  19. 19.

    I should differentiate my use of “naturalize” here from calls to “naturalize ethics” and bioethics. See Alison Jaggar (2000), Margaret Urban Walker (2002, 2007), and Lindemann et al. (2009). One naturalizes gender, race, or disability (in the bad way that I intend here) by depicting them as reflecting biological sex, genetics, or malfunction, respectively. Such moves reproduce a popular tacit claim that what is natural is also what is good—or at least what should be accepted because it cannot be changed. Thus naturalizing capitalism, gender, race, or ability tends to protect the status quo from critical scrutiny. On the other hand, calls to “naturalize ethics” aim to theorize moral understandings or epistemologies together with corresponding and co-producing practices in a critical, self-reflexive, and interdisciplinary accounting for the actual practices of moral categories like blame, responsibility, accountability, etc. The latter kind of naturalizing work in ethics clearly motivates and informs nonideal theory, where the former is precisely the problematic kind of naturalizing to which nonideal theory is largely a reaction.

  20. 20.

    See Lukács (1971, especially 197–209), Heinrich (2012, 29–38), and Feenberg (2014).

  21. 21.

    See Marx (1990, 163–177, 716; 1993, 157); Lukács (1971); Habermas (1987, 332–73). For explication of alienation in Marx, see Blackledge (2012, 87–91). On reification and Lukács, see Feenberg (2014, 61–89). For an assessment of Habermas’s colonization thesis as a reification concept, see Jütten (2011).

  22. 22.

    For an attempt to theorize alienating effects of social-relational structures as they relate to justice and moral responsibility, see Alison Jaggar (2009) and Iris Marion Young (2011). Another noteworthy work in nonideal theorizing in alienated modernity is Alexis Shotwell (2016). Shotwell notes the nonideal nature of contemporary developed-world existence: “there is no food we can eat, clothing we can buy, or energy we can use without deepening our ties to complex webs of suffering” (5). She asks in response, “what happens if we start from there?” (5). Shotwell’s nonideal aim is “to shape better practices of responsibility and memory for our placement in relation to the past, our implication in the present, and our potential creation of different futures” (8). Her theorizing against purity therefore is an instance of grappling critically and descriptively with actual alienation while deriving normative content.

  23. 23.

    On relational autonomy as a nonideal account of autonomy, see Meyers (1989), Mackenzie and Stoljar (2000), and Donchin (2001).

  24. 24.

    To connect a social pathology in health care to structural modes of profit production is not to deny, for instance, their potentially gendered or racial components. It is instead an attempt to begin illustrating their interconnections, amplify motivation for action, and inform transformative strategies.

  25. 25.

    On this distinction between the growth of costs and the rate of growth of costs, and its economic/policy significance, see Chernew and May (2011; especially 317).

  26. 26.

    See for instance Callahan (1998); Reinhardt (2009); Chernew and May (2011); Kennedy (2015).

  27. 27.

    Uwe Reinhardt (2009) echoes this idea.

  28. 28.

    See Schweickart (2009), Dittrich et al. (2012), and Hickel (2018).

References

  • Abelson, Reed. 2018. When hospitals merge to save money, patients often pay more. New York Times, November 14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Althusser, Louis. 2014. What is a mode of production? In On the reproduction of capitalism: Ideology and ideological state apparatuses. Trans. G.M. Goshgarian, 18–46. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Elizabeth. 1993. Value in ethics and economics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andrews, Michelle. 2016. More rural hospitals are closing their maternity units. Shots: Health News from NPR, February 24, https://www.npr.org/sections/health-shots/2016/02/24/467848568/more-rural-hospitals-are-closing-their-maternity-units. Accessed 1 July 2019.

  • Beauchamp, Tom L., and James F. Childress. 2019. Principles of biomedical ethics. 8th ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, Seyla. 1986. Critique, norm, and utopia: A study of the foundations of critical theory. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackledge, Paul. 2012. Marxism and ethics: Freedom, desire, and revolution. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brill, Steven. 2013. Bitter pill: Why medical bills are killing us. Time 181 (8): 16–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. America’s bitter pill: Money, politics, backroom deals, and the fight to fix our broken healthcare system. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callahan, Daniel. 1998. False hopes: Why America’s quest for perfect health is a recipe for failure. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chernew, Michael E., and Dustin May. 2011. Health care cost growth. In The Oxford handbook of health economics, ed. Sherry Glied and Peter C. Smith, 308–328. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chernomas, Robert, and Ian Hudson. 2013. To live and die in America: Class, power, health, and healthcare. London: Pluto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Choudhry, N.K., H.T. Stelfox, and A.S. Detsky. 2002. Relationships between authors of clinical practice guidelines and the pharmaceutical industry. Journal of the American Medical Association 287 (5): 612–617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, Norman. 1985. Just health care. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Just health: Meeting health needs fairly. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickenson, Donna. 2007. Property in the body: Feminist perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dittrich, Monika, Stefan Giljum, Stephan Lutter, and Christine Polzin. 2012. Green economies around the world? Implications of resource use for development and the environment. Vienna. https://www.researchgate.net/publication/301790657_Green_economies_around_the_world_Implications_of_resource_use_for_development_and_the_environment. Accessed 11 Apr 2019.

  • Donchin, Anne. 2001. Understanding autonomy relationally: Toward a reconfiguration of bioethical principles. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 26 (4): 365–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Reproductive tourism and the quest for global gender justice. Bioethics 24 (7): 323–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, Carl. 2010. White coat, black hat: Adventures on the dark side of medicine. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Entwistle, Vikki A., and Ian S. Watt. 2013. Treating patients as persons: A capabilities approach to support delivery of person-centered care. American Journal of Bioethics 13 (8): 29–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, Brian. 2018. Social ontology. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/social-ontology/. Accessed 15 Oct 2019.

  • Feenberg, Andrew. 2014. The philosophy of praxis: Marx, Lukács and the Frankfurt school. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frye, Marilyn. 1983. The politics of reality: Essays in feminist theory. Trumansburg: Crossing Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaynor, M., and W.B. Vogt. 2003. Competition among hospitals. RAND Journal of Economics 34 (4): 764–785.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, Jeremy A. 2007. Prescribing by numbers: Drugs and the definition of disease. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1987. The theory of communicative action, vol. 2, Lifeworld and system: A critique of functionalist reason. Trans. Thomas McCarthy. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, Sally. 2012. Resisting reality: Social construction and social critique. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. What is a (social) structural explanation? Philosophical Studies 173 (1): 113–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heinrich, Michael. 2012. An introduction to the three volumes of Karl Marx’s capital. Trans. Alexander Locascio. New York: Monthly Review Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. The ‘fragment on machines’: A Marxian misconception in the Grundrisse and its overcoming in Capital. In In Marx’s laboratory: Critical interpretations of the Grundrisse, ed. Riccardo Bellofiore, Guido Starosta, and Peter D. Thomas, 197–212. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hickel, Jason. 2018. Why growth can’t be green, Foreign Policy, September 12, https://foreignpolicy.com/2018/09/12/why-growth-cant-be-green/. Accessed 11 Apr 2019.

  • Howley, Elaine K. 2018. How some communities are freeing doctors from medical school debt. US News and World Report, May 11, https://health.usnews.com/health-care/patient-advice/articles/2018-05-11/how-some-communities-are-freeing-doctors-from-medical-school-debt. Accessed 1 July 2019.

  • Hunt, Linda M., Meta Kreiner, and Howard Brody. 2012. The changing face of chronic illness management in primary care: A qualitative study of underlying influences and unintended outcomes. The Annals of Family Medicine 10 (5): 452–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaggar, Alison. 2000. Ethics naturalized: Feminism’s contribution to moral epistemology. Metaphilosophy 31 (October): 452–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. L’Imagination au Pouvoir: Comparing John Rawls’s method of ideal theory with Iris Marion Young’s method of critical theory. In Feminist ethics and social and political philosophy: Theorizing the non-ideal, ed. Lisa Tessman, 59–66. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jütten, Timo. 2011. The colonization thesis: Habermas on reification. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 19 (5): 701–727.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, Mark G.E. 2018. For Foucault: Against normative political theory. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, Peter. 2015. The contradictions of capitalist healthcare systems. Critique: Journal of Socialist Theory 43 (2): 211–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, Harold, and Don Ross. 2009. Introduction: The new philosophy of economics. In Oxford handbook of philosophy of economics, ed. Harold Kincaid and Don Ross, 3–32. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, Suzanne M. 2013. Physician practices: Background, organization, and market consolidation, CRS Report No. R42880. Washington, DC: Congressional Research Service. https://www.fas.org/sgp/crs/misc/R42880.pdf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krier, Daniel, and Mark P. Worrell, eds. 2016. The social ontology of capitalism. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindemann, Hilde, Marian Verkerk, and Margaret Urban Walker, eds. 2009. Naturalized bioethics: Toward responsible knowing and practice. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lukács, Georg. 1971. History and class consciousness: Studies in Marxist dialectics. Trans. Rodney Livingstone. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, Catriona, and Natalie Stoljar, eds. 2000. Relational autonomy: Feminist perspectives on autonomy, agency, and the social self. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magee, Mike. 2019. Code blue: Inside America’s medical industrial complex. New York: Atlantic Monthly Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, Karl. 1990. Capital: A critique of political economy, vol. 1. Trans. Ben Fowkes. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1991. Capital: A critique of political economy, vol. 3. Trans. David Fernbach. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1992. Capital: A critique of political economy, vol. 2. Trans. David Fernbach. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. Grundrisse: Foundations of the critique of political economy (Rough Draft). Trans. Martin Nicolaus. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mead, Nicola, and Peter Bower. 2000. Patient-centredness: A conceptual framework and review of the empirical literature. Social Science & Medicine 51 (7): 1087–1110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meyers, Diana T. 1989. Self, society and personal choice. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, Charles W. 2005. ‘Ideal theory’ as ideology. Hypatia 20 (3): 165–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Contract of breach: Repairing the racial contract. In Contract and domination, ed. Carole Pateman and Charles Mills, 106–133. Malden: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Naci, Huseyin, and John P.A. Ioannidis. 2013. Comparative effectiveness of exercise and drug interventions on mortality outcomes: Metaepidemiological study. BMJ 347: f5577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Navarro, Vicente. 1976. Medicine under capitalism. New York: Prodist.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1985. U.S. Marxist scholarship in the analysis of health and medicine. International Journal of Health Services 15 (4): 525–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. Why some countries have national health insurance, others have national health services, and the U.S. has neither. Social Science and Medicine 28 (9): 887–898.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. Dangerous to your health: Capitalism in health care. New York: Monthly Review Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oldani, Michael J. 2010. Assessing the “relative value” of diabetic patients treated through an incentivized, corporate compliance model. Anthropology & Medicine 17 (2): 215–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oliver, Kelly. 1989. Marxism and surrogacy. Hypatia 4 (3): 95–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, Anne. 2013. Our bodies, whose property? Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Radin, Margaret Jane. 1993. The rhetoric of alienation. In Reinterpreting property, 191–202. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Contested commodities. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. The law of peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reidy, Angela. 1984. Marxist functionalism in medicine: A critique of the work of Vicente Navarro on health and medicine. Social Science and Medicine 19 (9): 897–910.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reinhardt, Uwe, interviewed by Sarah Koenig. 2009. 391: More is less. This American Life, podcast audio, October 9, http://www.thisamericanlife.org/radio-archives/episode/391.

  • Rosenthal, Elisabeth. 2013. As hospital prices soar, a single stich tops $500. New York Times, December 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. An American sickness: How healthcare became big business and how you can take it back. New York: Penguin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheiber, Noam. 2016. Doctors unionize to resist the medical machine. New York Times. January 9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schweickart, David. 1993. Against capitalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Is sustainable capitalism an oxymoron? Perspectives on Global Development and Technology 8: 559–580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. After capitalism. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shotwell, Alexis. 2016. Against purity: Living ethically in compromised times. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegler, Kirk. 2019. The struggle to hire and keep doctors in rural areas means patients go without care, All Things Considered, May 21, https://www.npr.org/sections/health-shots/2019/05/21/725118232/the-struggle-to-hire-and-keep-doctors-in-rural-areas-means-patients-go-without-c. Accessed 1 July 2019.

  • Silverman, Lauren. 2015. Texas strives to lure mental health providers to rural counties. All Things Considered. September 1, https://www.npr.org/sections/health-shots/2015/09/01/436386850/texas-strives-to-lure-mental-health-providers-to-rural-counties. Accessed 1 July 2019.

  • Simmons, A. John. 2010. Ideal and nonideal theory. Philosophy and Public Affairs 38 (1): 5–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starr, Paul. 2011. Remedy and reaction: The peculiar American struggle over health care reform. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sulzberger, A.G. 2011. New path for small-town doctors starts in a Kansas small town. New York Times, July 23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Michael J. 2016. Social ontology and social critique: Toward a new paradigm for critical theory. In The social ontology of capitalism, ed. Daniel Krier and Mark Worrell, 15–45. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Todres, Les, Kathleen Galvin, and Karin Dahlberg. 2007. Lifeworld-led healthcare: Revisiting a humanising philosophy that integrates emerging trends. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 10: 53–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tronto, Joan C. 1993. Moral boundaries: A political argument for an ethic of care. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valentini, Laura. 2009. On the apparent paradox of ideal theory. The Journal of Political Philosophy 17 (3): 332–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waitzkin, Howard. 1979. A Marxian interpretation of the growth and development of coronary care technology. American Journal of Public Health 69 (12): 1260–1268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1981. A Marxist analysis of the health care systems of advanced capitalist societies. In The relevance of social science for medicine, ed. Leon Eisenberg and Arthur Kleinman, 333–369. Boston: D. Reidel Publishing.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1983. The second sickness: Contradictions of capitalist health care. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984. The micropolitics of medicine: A contextual analysis. International Journal of the Health Services 14 (3): 339–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. A critical theory of medical discourse: Ideology, social control, and the processing of social context in medical encounters. Journal of Health and Social Behavior 30 (2): 220–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Medicine and public health at the end of empire. Boulder: Paradigm.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———, ed. 2018. Health care under the knife: Moving beyond capitalism for our health. New York: Monthly Review Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, Margaret Urban. 2002. Moral contexts. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Moral understandings: A feminist study in ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, Iris Marion. 2011. Responsibility for justice. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alex B. Neitzke .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Neitzke, A.B. (2021). Critical Theoretical Methodology for Nonideal Contributions to Bioethics. In: Victor, E., Guidry-Grimes, L.K. (eds) Applying Nonideal Theory to Bioethics. Philosophy and Medicine, vol 139. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-72503-7_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics