Skip to main content

The Semantics-Pragmatics Distinction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 314 Accesses

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 29))

Abstract

I argue that the theoretical basis we need for distinctions in the semantics-pragmatics dispute is to be found by noting that languages are representational systems of symbols that scientists attribute to species to explain their communicative behaviors. We then have a powerful theoretical interest in distinguishing, (a), the representational properties of an utterance that arise simply from the speaker’s exploitation of a linguistic system from, (b), any other properties that may constitute the speaker’s “message”. I call the former properties “what-is-said” and “semantic”, the latter, “what is meant but not said” and “pragmatic. From this theoretical basis I argue that what-is-said is constituted by properties arising from (i) linguistic conventions, (ii) disambiguations, and (iii) reference fixings. Setting aside novel uses of language, I then frame the semantics-pragmatics dispute as one between these two doctrines. According to SEM, what-is-said (in my sense) is typically the truth conditional speaker-meaning (content) of an utterance. According to PRAG, in contrast, the truth conditional speaker-meaning (content) of an utterance, the message conveyed, is seldom, perhaps never, constituted solely by what-is-said (in my sense). I foreshadow the argument in Chaps. 6, 7, 8, 9, 10, 11 and 12 that the striking examples produced by Linguistic Pragmatists can be accommodated by SEM. Evidence for this can be found in the regular use of a certain form with a certain speaker meaning, a regularity that is best explained by supposing that there is a linguistic, probably conventional, rule of so using the expression.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Earlier versions of some of the points in this chapter can be found in my “What makes a property ‘semantic’?” (2013c) and my Ignorance of language (2006b).

  2. 2.

    And it is worth noting that sometimes we are confident that an animal has a language because we have taught it one; think of some dolphins and primates that have been taught surprisingly complex languages.

  3. 3.

    For more on this issue see Devitt 2006c (pp. 585–6) responding to Smith 2006 (p. 440–1).

  4. 4.

    Just as the non-referential languages of animals (Sect. 3.2.2) have other functions that do not utilize representational properties, so has ours: we greet (“Hi”), cheer (“Bravo”), abuse (“Bastard”), and curse (“Shit”). I will return to this briefly in Sect. 4.2, but will mostly set it aside. The focus is always on the representational properties.

  5. 5.

    Chomskians have a different view. They see a human language as an internal state not a system of external symbols that represent the world. I argued (2003, 2006b: 17–41) that this is deeply misguided. This led to some always lively and sometimes nasty exchanges: Collins 2006, Matthews 2006, Rattan 2006, Rey 2006b, and Smith 2006, responded to in Devitt 2006c; Collins 2008a, b and Rey 2008, responded to in Devitt 2008a, b, c, 2013e; Antony 2008 and Pietroski 2008, responded to in Devitt 2008c; Longworth 2009 and Slezak 2009, responded to in Devitt 2009; Ludlow 2009, responded to in Devitt 2013h; Collins 2020 and Rey 2020b, responded to in Devitt 2020b. (Rey’s paper is marred by a serious misrepresentation: the allegation that my view of language arises from a methodological “commitment to Moorean commonsense” (2020b: 307). This charge is obviously baseless, as I point out, 2020b: 429–31.)

  6. 6.

    Some philosophers and linguists, impressed by the great difference between a human language and the representational systems used by other animals, resist calling those systems “languages”. I can see no theoretical point to this resistance. In any case, the point is merely verbal.

  7. 7.

    Consider also these from the classics:

    [N]o one is able to persuade me that the correctness of names is determined by anything besides convention… No name belongs to a particular thing by nature, but only because of the rules and usages of those who establish the usage and call it by that name—Hermogenes in Plato’s Cratylus (384c–d)

    A name is a spoken sound significant by convention… I say “by convention” because no name is a name naturally but only when it has become a symbol.—Aristotle De Interpretatione (16a.20–28)

  8. 8.

    Stephen Neale has the contrary view that although an expression type has a meaning we have no theoretical need to ascribe a meaning, a reference, etc. to a linguistic token; see Sect. 6.4 and 6.5 for discussion.

  9. 9.

    Multiplicity could, in principle, arise from multiple innate rules for a symbol but, so far as I know, there is no example of this in nature.

  10. 10.

    We doubtless have some theoretical interest also in the non-representational properties of our language used in greeting, cursing, and the like. But I am mostly setting them aside; see note 4.

  11. 11.

    What-is-said by an utterance of an “eternal sentence” would be constituted solely by properties of type (i).

  12. 12.

    This needs qualification because what-is-said using a sub-sentential is sometimes only a fragment of a proposition; see Chap. 12. Kent Bach has a more austere notion of what-is-said, discussed in Sects. 6.1, 6.2 and 6.3.

  13. 13.

    My what-is-said abstracts from differences between utterances that are assertions, rehearsals, questions, commands, and so on.

  14. 14.

    A speaker might intend to convey more than one message. I am simplifying by setting this possibility aside.

  15. 15.

    Of course, if it were not for the fact that a speaker’s utterance was intentionally produced, she would no more have thereby said the proposition p than she would have meant the proposition q. So we might ordinarily say that the speaker “meant” both propositions. But this ordinary way of speaking does not provide a theoretical motivation for treating the distinct items, what-is-said and the message, as parts of the one “meaning”. (There is a subtle issue about the relation of the intentional act of uttering to what-is-said; see Sect. 6.2.)

  16. 16.

    Salmon is used to hearing this response and is not impressed: “‘It’s all just terminology’ is the last refuge of the speech-act centered conception” (2005: 327). Kepa Korta and John Perry’s view (2007: 98–9) that “something has gone awry” in Cappelen and Lepore’s account of “semantic minimalism” (2005: 143–5) seems to rest simply on an insistence that ‘semantics’ be used narrowly.

  17. 17.

    This is nicely demonstrated by Bach 1999 and Ezcurdia and Stainton 2012.

  18. 18.

    Note that the common description of pragmatics as “the science of language in use” does not distinguish the two meanings.

  19. 19.

    This is presumably related somehow to the confusion of the metaphysics of meaning with the epistemology of interpretation that I discuss in Chap. 7.

  20. 20.

    See Pagin and Pelletier (2007: 35) for a nice statement of this sort of view.

  21. 21.

    Relevance theorists take the traditional view of communication to be “the code model” according to which “communication is achieved by encoding and decoding messages” (Sperber and Wilson 1995: 2). This is a bit misleading because the tradition had surely noted the obvious fact that understanding a message requires not just decoding but also reference fixing and disambiguation.

  22. 22.

    And to explain some non-communicative uses of language; see Sect. 4.2.

  23. 23.

    As Manuel García-Carpintero says: “the semantics/pragmatics divide is in my view ultimately about which meaning-properties are constitutive of natural languages and which are not” (2006: 43).

  24. 24.

    These novel implicatures are “particularized conversational implicatures”. What about “generalized” ones? These are more controversial and I’m dubious that there are any such pragmatic phenomena; see later (Sects. 8.4, 9.4, 11.2.6).

  25. 25.

    According to Falkum “the distinction between linguistic semantics and pragmatics is seen as corresponding to different processes involved in utterance comprehension” (2015: 89). The word “corresponding” is important here. For, categorizing utterances as having PM-meanings rather than the traditional WIS-meanings does indeed demand a corresponding difference in the process of understanding the utterances: “most of the interpretive work is performed…by pragmatic processes operating over underspecified semantic representations” (p. 89).

  26. 26.

    Also in reaction time studies, eye tracking, and electromagnetic brain potentials. Perhaps philosophers can get inspiration from these experiments too.

  27. 27.

    I sum up my discussion of linguistic evidence: “the main evidence for grammars is not found in the intuitions of ordinary speakers but rather in a combination of the corpus, the evidence of what we would say and understand, and the intuitions of linguists” (2006a: 488, 2006b: 100).

  28. 28.

    I draw on my 2010a: 94.

References

  • Antony, Louise. 2008. Meta-Linguistics: Methodology and ontology in Devitt’s Ignorance of Language. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86: 643–656.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle, 1984. De interpretatione, in The complete works of Aristotle, ed. Jonathan Barnes, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, Kent. 1994. Conversational impliciture. Mind and Language 9: 124–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. The semantics-pragmatics distinction: what it is and why it matters. In The semantics-pragmatics interface from different points of view, ed. Ken Turner, 65–84. Oxford: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Context ex machina. In Szabó 2005, 15–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bezuidenhout, Anne. 2002. Truth-Conditional pragmatics. Philosophical Perspectives 16: 105–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bianchi, Andrea, ed. 2020a. Language and reality from a naturalistic perspective: Themes from Michael Devitt, Andrea Bianchi, ed. Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bianchi, Claudia, ed. 2004. The semantic/pragmatics distinction, Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A., F. Lo Piparo, and M. Carapezza, eds. 2013. Perspectives on Pragmatics and Philosophy. Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, Herman, and Ernie Lepore. 2005. Insensitive semantics: A defense of semantic minimalism and speech act pluralism. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, Robyn. 2002. Thoughts and utterances: The pragmatics of explicit communication. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Truth-Conditional content and conversational implicature. In Bianchi 2004, 65–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Linguistic communication and the semantics/pragmatics distinction. Synthese 165: 321–345. https://doi.org/10.1007/S:1122900791918.

  • Churchland, Patricia S. 1986. Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind-brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, Paul M. 1989. A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, John. 2006. Between a rock and a hard place: A dialogue on the philosophy and methodology of generative linguistics. Croatian Journal of Philosophy VI: 469-503.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008a. Knowledge of language redux. Croatian Journal of Philosophy VIII: 3-43.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008b. A note on conventions and unvoiced syntax. Croatian Journal of Philosophy VIII, 241-7.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020. Invariance as the Mark of the Psychological Reality of Language. In Bianchi 2020a: 7-44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, Michael. 1974. Singular terms. Journal of Philosophy LXXI: 183‑205.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1976. Semantics and the ambiguity of proper names. Monist 59: 404‑423.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1981a. Designation. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1981b. Donnellan’s distinction. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Volume VI: The Foundations of Analytic Philosophy, ed. Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling Jr., and Howard K. Wettstein, 511-524. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Coming to our senses: A naturalistic program for semantic localism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Linguistics is not psychology. In Epistemology of language, ed. Alex Barber, 107–139. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006a. Intuitions in linguistics, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57: 481–513.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006b. Ignorance of language, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006c. Defending Ignorance of language: Responses to the Dubrovnik papers. Croatian Journal of Philosophy VI: 571–606.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008a. Explanation and reality in linguistics. Croatian Journal of Philosophy VIII: 203–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008b. A response to Collins’ note on conventions and unvoiced syntax. Croatian Journal of Philosophy VIII: 249–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008c. Methodology in the philosophy of linguistics. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86: 671–684.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Psychological conception, psychological reality. Croatian Journal of Philosophy IX: 35–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010a. Putting metaphysics first: essays on metaphysics and epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010c Linguistic Intuitions Revisited. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 61: 833–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011b. Experimental semantics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXXXII, 418–435.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012a. Whither experimental semantics? Theoria 73, 5–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013a. The myth of the problematic de se. In Attitudes de se: Linguistics, epistemology, metaphysics, ed. Neil Feit and Alessandro Capone, 133–162. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013c. What makes a property ‘semantic’? In Capone et al. 2013: 87-112.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013e. The “Linguistic Conception” of Grammars. Filozofia Nauki XXI: 5–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013h. Responding to a hatchet job: Ludlow’s review of Ignorance of Language. Revista Discusiones Filosóficas 14: 307–12. Online at http://devitt.commons.gc.cuny.edu/spirited-exchanges/

  • ———. 2015a. Testing theories of reference. In Advances in Experimental Philosophy of Language, ed. Jussi Haukioja, 31–63. London: Bloomsbury Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020b. Stirring the possum: Responses to the Bianchi papers. In Bianchi 2020a, 371–455.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———, and Nicolas Porot. 2018. The reference of proper names: Testing usage and intuitions. Cognitive Science: 1552–1585. doi.org/10.1111/cogs.12609.

  • ———, and Brian Cross Porter. 2021. Testing the reference of biological kind terms. Cognitive Science. https://doi.org/10.1111/cogs.12979.

  • Domaneschi, F., Vignolo, M., and Di Paola, S. (2017. Testing the causal theory of reference. Cognition, 161, 1–9. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2016.12.014.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dyer, F. C. 2002. The biology of the dance language. Annual Review of Entomology 47: 917–949.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elugardo, Reinaldo, and Robert J. Stainton. 2004. Shorthand, syntactic ellipsis, and the pragmatic determinants of what is said. Mind and Language 19: 442–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ezcurdia, Maite, and Robert J. Stainton. 2012. Introduction. InThe Semantics–Pragmatics Boundary in Philosophy, ed. Maite Ezcurdia and Robert J. Stainton, xiii–xxxiv. Peterborough, ON: Broadview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Falkum, Ingrid Lossius. 2015. The how and why of polysemy: A pragmatic account. Lingua 157: 83–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry A. 1987. Psychosemantics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———, T. G. Bever, and M. F. Garrett. 1974. The psychology of language: An introduction to psycholinguistics and generative grammar. New York: McGraw-Hill Book Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, Adam. 1997. Quantum honey bees. Discover: 80–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • García-Carpintero, Manuel. 2006. Recanati on the semantics/pragmatics distinction. Critíca, Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía 38 (112): 35–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1989. Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korta, Kepa, and John Perry. 2007. Radical minimalism, moderate contextualism. In Preyer and Peter 2007, 94–111.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David K. 1969. Convention: A philosophical study. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longworth, Guy. 2009. Ignorance of linguistics. Croatian Journal of Philosophy IX: 21–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludlow, Peter. 2009. Review of Devitt 2006b. Philosophical Review 118: 393–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, Robert J. 2006. Could competent speakers really be ignorant of their language? Croatian Journal of Philosophy VI: 457–467.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pagin, Peter, and Jeffry Pelletier. 2007. Context, content, and composition. In Preyer and Peter 2007, 25–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski, Paul. 2008. Think of the children. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86: 657–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plato, Cratylus, trans. C. D. C. Reeve. In Complete Works, ed. John Cooper, Indianapolis: Hackett, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preyer, Gerhard, and Georg Peter. 2007. Context-Sensitivity and semantic minimalism. Oxford: Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rattan, Gurpreet. 2006. The knowledge in language. Croatian Journal of Philosophy VI: 505–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, François. 2003. The limits of expressibility. In John Searle, ed. Barry Smith, 189–213. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Literal meaning, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rey, Georges. 2006b. Conventions, intuitions and linguistic inexistents: A reply to Devitt. Croatian Journal of Philosophy VI: 549–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. In defense offFolieism: Replies to critics. Croatian Journal of Philosophy VIII: 177–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020b. Explanation first: The priority of scientific over ‘commonsense’ metaphysics. In Bianchi 2020a, 299–327.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riley, J. R., U. Greggers, A. D. Smith, D. R. Reynolds, and R. Menzel. 2005. The flight of honey bees recruited by the waggle dance. Nature 435: 205–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, Nathan. 2005. Two conceptions of semantics. In Szabó 2005, 317–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, Stephen. 1972. Meaning. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slezak, Peter. 2009. Linguistic explanation and “psychological reality”. Croatian Journal of Philosophy IX: 3–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slobodchikoff, C. N. 2002. Cognition and communication in prairie dogs. In The cognitive animal: empirical and theoretical perspectives on animal cognition, ed. Colin Allen, and Gordon M. Burchardt, 257–264. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Barry C. 2006. Why we still need knowledge of language. Croatian Journal of Philosophy VI: 431–456.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, Dan, and Deirdre Wilson. 1995. Relevance: Communication and cognition. 2nd edn. 1st edn 1986. Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, Jason, and Zoltan G. Szabó. 2000a. On quantifier domain restriction. Mind and Language 15: 219–261.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szabó, Zoltan G. ed. 2005. Semantics versus pragmatics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thornton, Rosalind. 1995. Referentiality and wh-movement in child English: Juvenile d-linkuency. Language Acquisition 4: 139–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vladusich, Tony, Jan M. Hemmi and Jochen Zeil. 2006. Honeybee odometry and scent guidance. The Journal of Experimental Biology 209: 1367–1375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Devitt .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Devitt, M. (2021). The Semantics-Pragmatics Distinction. In: Overlooking Conventions. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 29. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-70653-1_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics