Skip to main content

Prehistoric Stone Tools and their Epistemic Complexity

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Engineering and Philosophy

Part of the book series: Philosophy of Engineering and Technology ((POET,volume 37))

Abstract

In his 1997 paper “Technology and Complexity” Dasgupta draws a distinction between systematic and epistemic complexity. Entities are called systematically complex when they are composed of a large number of parts that interact in complicated ways. This means that even if one knows the properties of the parts one may not be able to infer the behaviour of the system as a whole. In contrast, epistemic complexity refers to the knowledge that is used in, or generated by the making of an artefact and is embodied in it. Interestingly, a high level of systematic complexity does not entail a high level of epistematic complexity and vice versa. Prehistoric stone tools, for example, display a unique combination of systematic simplicity with epistemic complexity. In order to attract the attention of philosophers of technology and engineering to the domain of prehistoric technology or what is called “First Technology”, the present chapter aims to examine the epistemic complexity of, (that is to say the amount, variety and kind of knowledge embodied in) ancient Oldowan stone tools. The aim is addressed by critically reviewing and extending Karl Popper’s unconventional objective approach to epistemology and by drawing upon recent experimental-archaeological research on Oldowan stone tool production.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    The terms ‘artificial things,’ ‘artefacts’ and ‘technical artefacts’ used interchangeably in this chapter refer to any product of human (or hominin) activities, conceived, manufactured or modified in response to some need, want or desire to produce an intended result.

  2. 2.

    For the distinction between explicit and tacit knowledge see. e.g., Vincenti (1984), and (Houkes 2009).

  3. 3.

    We do not assume here that technological knowledge is simple know-how or non-propositional, practical knowledge. For more details on the heterogenous nature of technological knowledge see Dasgupta (1996).

  4. 4.

    How technical ideas or thoughts can be expressed and conveyed through  visual or pictorial forms has been brilliantly illustrated by Ferguson (1977). We will take up the issue in the next section.

  5. 5.

    But the converse is not true because our thought contents or products are largely autonomous and not entirely reducible to our thought processes.

  6. 6.

    Things which are ‘based on’ certain processes but cannot be ‘explained by’ the theories of the underlying processes are to be understood as ‘emergent’ (Niemann 2014: 68).

  7. 7.

    Italian engineer Ramelli’s 1588 Le Diverse et Artificiose Machine or the German instrument maker Leupold’s series of machine books entitled Theatrum Machinarum are examples of works that transmitted a huge amount of new technical ideas and information through mere illustrations of artefacts.

  8. 8.

    To our surprise, Dasgupta (1996) has been inexplicably absent from Baird’s (2004) book.

  9. 9.

    Despite its unmatched significance Ferguson’s (1977) study of how non-verbal thought recorded in technical drawings and images is not useful in a direct way for our investigation into the epistemic complexity of stone tools.  

  10. 10.

    Nordmann (2006), for example, argues that the knowledge of making, building, repairing artefacts or that of design cannot be properly examined by considering knowledge as a species of belief.

  11. 11.

    For a discussion of how to understand the partially autonomous nature of World 3 products see Chakrabarty (2014).

  12. 12.

    Such embodied objects do not exhaust World 3. Popper accepted the possibility of the existence of unembodied World 3 objects which are neither materially embodied nor do they exist as World 2 memories nor has been discovered by anyone yet (Popper and Eccles 1977/1995: 41).

  13. 13.

    Baird has been criticised (e.g., Kletzl 2014) for not providing a more plausible explanation of the problem of justification of instruments. Had he interpreted ‘knowledge’ in the strict Popperian sense he could have easily explained to his critics why the issue of justification whether of theories or of instruments in the traditional way is a relatively unimportant problem for Popper’s objective epistemology and his ‘thing knowledge.’ For a review of this problem of justification see Musgrave (1974).

  14. 14.

    By stating that science is just one component of technological knowledge Dasgupta (1996) challenges the popular perception that technology emerges from science and entails the mere application of scientific knowledge.

  15. 15.

    Operational-principles-as-knowledge may generate in different ways. The most explicit means possibly are the processes of design but experiments and experience also produce operational principles. For details see Dasgupta (1996).

  16. 16.

    Leakey’s view has been questioned by contemporary scholars like Jeffares (2010a) who thinks Homo habilis definitely had tool using ancestors.

  17. 17.

    The distinction between the tool-assisted foraging of some primates or birds and the tool-dependent foraging of the human genus that indicates a new level of integration between brain, hand and tool is worth noting here (Bruner and Iriki 2016: 4).

  18. 18.

    Such scrutiny generally consists of replication of artefact- forms, followed by experimental assessment of the feasibility of performing a series of tasks with each artefact form, microscopic study of use-wear polishes, and the examination of marks made by stone tools on other materials, notably bones (Isaac 1989: 129).

  19. 19.

    The controlled fracture of stone by hand is called knapping.

  20. 20.

    The experiments of Stout and colleagues (Stout et al. 2005) at the early (2.6–2.5 Mya) sites at Gona, Ethiopia also suggest that the early toolmakers were able to identify and preferentially select higher quality materials (finer-grained volcanic materials with fewer phenocrysts that could produce hard, sharp edges when flaked).

  21. 21.

    Many World 3 objects, though not all, are embodied or physically realized in World 1 physical objects (Popper 1978: 145).

  22. 22.

    Toth (1987) has, in fact, replicated the entire range of Oldowan core forms along with a variety of flakes.

References

  • Baird, D. (2004). Thing knowledge: A philosophy of scientific instruments. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Basalla, G. (1988). The evolution of technology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, E., & Iriki, A. (2016). Extending mind, visuospatial integration, and the evolution of the parietal lobes in the human genus. Quaternary International, 405, 98–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakrabarty, M. (2014). A philosophical inquiry into the character of material artifacts. Philosophia Scientiae, 18(3), 153–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coolidge, F. L., & Wynn, T. (2016). An Introduction to Cognitive Archaeology. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 25(6), 386–392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, S. (1996). Technology and creativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, S. (1997). Technology and complexity. Philosophica, 59(1), 113–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delagnes, A., & Roche, H. (2005). Late Pliocene hominid knapping skills: the case of Lokalalei 2C, West Turkana, Kenya. Journal of Human Evolution, 48(5), 435−472.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferguson, E. S. (1977). The mind’s eye: Nonverbal thought in technology. Science, 197(4306), 827–836.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Houkes, W. (2009). The Nature of Technological Knowledge. In A. W. M. Meijers (Ed.), Handbook of Philosophy of Technology and Engineering Sciences (pp 309–350), Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hovers, E. (2009). Learning from mistakes: Flaking accidents and knapping skills in the assemblage of A.L. 894 (Hadar, Ethiopia). In K. Schick & N. Toth (Eds.), The cutting edge: New approaches to the archaeology of human origins. Gosport: Stone Age Institute Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Isaac, B. (Ed.). (1989). The archaeology of human origins: Papers by Glynn Isaac. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffares, B. (2010a). The co-evolution of tools and minds: Cognition and material culture in the hominin lineage. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9, 503–520.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeffares, B. (2010b). The evolution of technical competence: Strategic and economic thinking. In W. Christensen, E. Schier, & J. Sutton (Eds.), ASCS09: Proceedings of the 9th conference of the Australasian Society for Cognitive Science. Sydney: Macquarie Centre for Cognitive Science. https://doi.org/10.5096/ASCS200925.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kletzl, S. (2014). Scrutinizing thing knowledge. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science (Part A), 47, 118–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leaky, M. (1971). Olduvai Gorge: Volume5: Excavations in beds I and II. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leaky, R. (1994). The origin of human kind. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L. (2013). How things shape the mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. W. (Ed.). (1995). Popper selections. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. W. (2011). Objective knowledge. https://warwick.ac.uk/fac/soc/philosophy/people/miller/foreword2009.pdf

  • Musgrave, A. E. (1974). The objectivism of Popper’s epistemology. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Karl Popper (Vol. 1). La Salle: Open Court Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (1993). Common sense, science and scepticism: A historical introduction to the theory of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niemann, H.-J. (2014). Karl Popper and the two new secrets of life. Tuebingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nordmann, A. (2006). Collapse of distance: Epistemic strategies of science and technoscience. Danish Yearbook of Philosophy, 41, 7–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petroski, H. (1992). The evolution of useful things. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1962). Personal knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1972). Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1979). Three worlds. Michigan Quarterly Review, 18(1), 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R., & Eccles, J. C. (1977). The self and its brain: An argument for indeterminism. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roche, H. (2005). From simple flaking to shaping: Stone-knapping evolution among early hominins. In V. Roux & B. Bril (Eds.), Stone knapping: The necessary conditions for a uniquely hominin behaviour. Cambridge: McDonald Institute for Archaeological Research.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schick, K. D., & Toth, N. P. (1993). Making silent stones speak: Human evolution and the dawn of technology. London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1962). The architecture of complexity. Proceedings of American Philosophical Society, 106, 467–482.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stout, D. (2002). Skill and cognition in stone tool production. Current Anthropology, 43, 693–722.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stout, D. (2011). Stone tool making and the evolution of human culture and cognition. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London (Series B), 366, 1050–1059.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stout, D., Quade, J., Semaw, S., & Levin, N. E. (2005). Raw material selectivity of the earliest stone toolmakers at Gona, Afar, Ethiopia. Journal of Human Evolution, 48, 365–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toth, N. (1987). The first technology. Scientific American, 1, 112–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toth, N., & Schick, K. D. (2009). The Oldowan: The tool making of early hominins and chimpanzees compared. Annual Review of Anthropology, 38, 289–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toth, N. P., & Schick, K. D. (2018). An overview of the cognitive implications of the Oldowan Industrial Complex. Azania: Archaeological Research in Africa, 53(1), 3–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vincenti, W. G. (1984). Technological knowledge without science: The innovation of flush riveting in American airplanes, ca. 1930–ca. 1950. Technology and Culture, 25(3), 540–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wynn, T. G., & Coolidge, F. L. (2016). Archaeological insights into hominin cognitive evolution. Evolutionary Anthropology: Issues, News, and Reviews, 25(4), 200–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wynn, T. G., & McGrew, W. C. (1989). An Ape’s view of the Oldowan. Man, New Series, 24(3), 383–398.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wynn, T. G., Hernandez-Aguilar, R. A., Marchant, L. F., & McGrew, W. C. (2011). An ape’s view of the Oldowan revisited. Evolutionary Anthropology, 20(5), 181–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Manjari Chakrabarty .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Chakrabarty, M. (2021). Prehistoric Stone Tools and their Epistemic Complexity. In: Pirtle, Z., Tomblin, D., Madhavan, G. (eds) Engineering and Philosophy. Philosophy of Engineering and Technology, vol 37. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-70099-7_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics