Skip to main content

The Work of Art as a Living System: A Deweyan Approach

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Phenomenology of the Object and Human Positioning

Part of the book series: Analecta Husserliana ((ANHU,volume 122))

  • 364 Accesses

Abstract

This paper aims to develop Dewey’s aesthetics in relation to the epistemology of complexity. The focus is particularly on the convergence between a work of art and a living system. Indeed, a work of art, much like a living system, is a unity in variety, being integrated and differentiated. This characteristic is not the result of linear causality, for which each part affects only the contiguous aspects, but the consequence of dynamics of the whole (or, of the field) coordinating the activities of the elements through to their most remote junctions. Every part “feels” the whole, which in turn is realized via articulation in all its parts. Congruently, a work of art contains a perfect integration between “spiritual” and “sensorial” levels, between “bodily” and “ideal.” Thus, it is evident that amongst the various levels comprising a work of art, there is continuity. Ultimately, a work of art is the result of a historical process during which it advances, interacting with the medium, like a living organism that develops, acquiring articulation and volume, learning from experience, embodying and internalizing the learned meanings. In developing this perspective, the concepts of emergence and organicism will be assumed as the focal points for both Dewey’s (aesthetic) thinking and the epistemology of complexity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    More recently, attempts to re-read Dewey’s thoughts in the direction of the epistemology of complexity are being made (for example: Godfrey-Smith, 1996; Semetsky, 2008). El-Hania and Pihlströmb (2002) further the concept of emergence also with reference to pragmatism and, specifically, to Dewey’s thought without drawing the final consequences from Deweyan emergent naturalism. In their view, “perhaps a notion of emergence based on non-reductive physicalism [...] does some interesting, pragmatically valuable work in certain specific fields, e.g., in the philosophy of biology—possibly in accounting for the relation between biological and physico-chemical properties. But when we move on to other, ontological regions, particularly the mental and cultural realms, we do not seem to have a sufficiently clear idea of how the program of non-reductive physicalism could be the carried through (with or without emergence)” (24–25).

  2. 2.

    Even if “a clear understanding of the concept of experience is undoubtedly a more difficult theoretical task for those who turn to the study of Deweyan philosophy” (Calcaterra, 2011, 118, transl. my own), adopting the organismic approach, we can say that the experience, as a whole, is its meaning, in an almost phenomenological sense, without further additions. In this regard, please refer to the Sect. 8 in this paper.

  3. 3.

    In From Absolutism to Experimentalism, Dewey (1930) recognizes that “Hegel has left a permanent deposit in my thinking” (21). We have to recall that, even before knowing the Hegelian philosophy, Dewey had come into contact with the idea of organicism during the physiology course held by T. Huxley. Dewey recalls that meeting as follows: “I have an impression that there was derived from that study a sense of interdependence and interrelated unity that gave form to intellectual stirrings that had been previously inchoate and created a kind of type or model of a view of things to which material in any field ought to conform. Subconsciously, at least, I was led to desire a world and a life that would have the same properties as had the human organism in the picture of it derived from study of Huxley’s treatment” (13).

  4. 4.

    For Calcaterra (2011), “if you are willing to accept a certain degree of exaggeration and provocation in the historical work, you could describe the whole evolution of Deweyan thought as an attempt to make the theoretical content of this fundamental youth intuition more and more pervasive and logically compelling” (14, transl. my own). In Knowing and the Known, this attempt succeeded. In this book, Dewey comes to develop the concept of transaction, with which he ultimately takes the distances from any “ontological reference”—such as “‘elements’ or other presumptively detachable or independent ‘entities’, ‘essences’, or ‘realities’” (1949/1991, 101–102), to adopt an organismic logic that examines the dynamics of the whole situation. What’s more, in that book Dewey’s thought is projected in the direction of those thinkers—from J.C. Maxwell to K. Goldstein, from J.V. Uexkull to the Gestalt psychologists—who were working to develop an organismic (or field) perspective within their respective areas of competence. For example, complaining that, “The new foundation that has been given physics on a transactional basis [...] has not yet been made complete” (107), Dewey comments—citing Maxwell—that “the properties of the field alone appear to be essential for the description of phenomena” and that “[t]he electromagnetic field is, in Maxwell’s theory, something real” (108). Likewise, in physiological and biological sciences “against the vitalisms [...] Views of the type called ‘organismic’, ‘organismal’ etc., except where they contain reminiscences of the old self-actional forms, stand for the transactional approach intra-dermally” (116–117). This organismic-transactional approach has the “desire to allot the leading adjective rather to the full living procedure of the organism than to minor specialized processes within it” (117).

  5. 5.

    Dewey knows full well the risk of reductionism inherent in concepts such as emergence or statements such as “the spirit and life emerge” (Dewey & Bentley, 1949/1981, 155). It is not simply, as El-Hania and Pihlströmche evidences, that “Dewey did not reject the idea [of emergence] altogether but only what he saw as its magical overtones. He simply required scientific research on the emergence of life and mind”, rather he is entirely aware of the risk that a concept such as emergence “still retains an independence and an unnatural isolation of the old type” (Dewey & Bentley, 1949/1981, 155). In this way, emerge results that are extrinsic and not inherent to the dynamics of the phenomena, incorporating dualisms or containing the remnants of old vitalistic or mechanistic concepts. The new approach is to dispense of any “must be” of the phenomenon, looking at it as a pure relational-transactional becoming. It is no coincidence that, in this regard, Dewey mentions the concept of “field”. The direction that Dewey suggests is to make a more careful analysis of the phenomena: “the conception transactional emergency [...] will in the descriptions enriched primary processes of life in their environments and more complex behavioral processes in them”. Reductionism implies to stop simplified explanations. To invoke the respect of the phenomenon as a whole, in fact, does not hint at a rejection of the analytic approach, as is sometimes argued, as the true “complex” attitude is to compare oneself with the infinite complexity of reality, renouncing the temptation to introduce extraneous explanations. As Stengers (1985, 50) observes, whilst reductionism says “nothing but …”, the analytical method “could lead to ‘this’…, but in other circumstances, ‘that’, and then to ‘that yet’” (transl. my own). Therefore, at every step, upon each discovery, others lie in wait.

  6. 6.

    To this regard, cf. notes no. 4 and 5.

  7. 7.

    Cf. note no. 5.

  8. 8.

    “Through art, meanings of objects that are otherwise dumb, inchoate, restricted and resisted are clarified and concentrated, and not by thought working laboriously upon them, nor by escape into a world of mere sense, but by creation of a new experience” (Dewey, 1934/1980, 132–133).

References

  • Alexander, T. M. (1987). John Dewey’s theory of art, experience, and nature: The horizons of feeling. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, P. W. (1972). More is different. Science, 177(4047), 393–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anwar, Y. (2015, February 2). Add nature, art and religion to life’s best anti-inflammatories. Berkeley News. Retrieved August 20, 2015, from http://newscenter.berkeley.edu/2015/02/02/anti-inflammatory/.

  • Blumenbach, J. F. (1781/1971). Über den Bildungstrieb und das Zeugungsgeschäfte. Stuttgard: Fischer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calcaterra, R. M. (2011). Idee concrete. Percorsi nella filosofia di John Dewey. Genova-Milano: Marietti.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1916). Democracy and education. An introduction to the philosophy of education. The Macmillan Company: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1917). The need for a recovery of philosophy. In Creative intelligence: Essays in the pragmatic attitude (pp. 3–69). New York: Henry Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1929). Experience and nature (2nd ed.). London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, John. 1930. “From absolutism to experimentalism.” In Contemporary American philosophy: Personal statements, George P. Adams and Wm. Pepperell Montague. New York: Russell and Russell: 13–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1934/1980). Art as experience. New York: Perigee Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1938). Logic: The theory of inquiry. New York: Henry Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J., & Bentley, A. F. (1949/1991). Knowing and the known. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), The later works, 1925–1952 (Vol. 16). Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • El-Hani, C. N., & Pihlström, S. (2002). Emergence theories and pragmatic realism. Essays in Philosophy, 3(2), 3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1996). Complexity and the function of mind in nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1823/2000) Lezioni di estetica (The Heinrich Gustav Hotho transcript of the 1823 Berlin Lectures) (P. D’Angelo, Trans.). Roma-Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. (2008). Reinventing the sacred: A new view of science, reason, and religion. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Köhler, W. (1938/1939). The place of value in a world of facts. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pareyson, L. (1966). La contemplazione della forma. In Conversazioni di estetica (pp. 20–24). Milano: Mursia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pirandello, L. (1910/1990). Leviamoci questo pensiero. In G. Macchia (Ed.), Novelle per un anno (I Meridiani) (Vol. 3, pp. 394–405). Milan: Mondadori.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pirandello, L. (1925/1997). Prefazione a Sei personaggi in cerca d’autore. In A. D’Amico (Ed.), Maschere nude (I Meridiani) (Vol. 2). Milano: Mondadori.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pirandello, L. (1931/1977). Discorso alla Reale Accademia d’Italia. In M. L. V. Musti (Ed.), Saggi, poesie, scritti varii (4th ed., pp. 391–406). Milan: Mondadori.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prigogine, I., & Stengers, I. (1979/1984). Order out of chaos. Man’s new dialogue with nature. New York: Bantam Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Semetsky, I. (2008). Re-reading Dewey through the lens of complexity science, or: On the creative logic of education. In M. Mason (Ed.), Complexity theory and the philosophy of education (pp. 79–90). Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stengers, I. (1985). Perché non può esserci un paradigma della complessità. In G. Bocchi & M. Ceruti (Eds.), La sfida della complessità (pp. 37–59). Milano: Feltrinelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. (2001, January 29). La coscienza nelle neuroscienze. Conversation with Sergio Benvenuto. Paris. Retrieved July 10, 2015, from http://www.psychomedia.it/pm/science/psybyo/varela.htm.

  • von Bertalanffy, L. (1967). Robots, men and minds. Psychology in the modern world. New York: George Brallizer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiss, P. A. (1969). The living system: Determinism stratified. In A. Koestler & J. R. Smythies (Eds.), Beyond reductionism: New perspectives in the life sciences (pp. 3–55). London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiss, P. A. (1973). The science of life: The living system. A system for living. Mount Kisco, NY: Futura Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, M. (1924). Untersuchungen zur Lehre von der Gestalt, II. Psychologishe Forschung, IV, 301–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A. N. (1933/1962). Adventures of ideas. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zajonc, A. G. (1987). Facts as theory: Aspect of Goethe’s philosophy of science. In F. Amrine, F. J. Zucker, & H. Wheeler (Eds.), Goethe and the sciences: A reappraisal. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stefano Polenta .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Polenta, S. (2021). The Work of Art as a Living System: A Deweyan Approach. In: Hornbuckle, C.A., Smith, J.S., Smith, W.S. (eds) Phenomenology of the Object and Human Positioning. Analecta Husserliana, vol 122. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-66437-4_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics