Skip to main content

The Foundational Document of Cognitive Science

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
A Life in Cognition

Part of the book series: Language, Cognition, and Mind ((LCAM,volume 11))

Abstract

David Hume’s Treatise of Human Nature is arguably the best candidate for the first ever overarching attempt at a descriptive-explanatory science of the mind. This paper characterizes the key tenets of Hume’s undertaking and situates its central features in the context of then-contemporary science. According to the present argument, Hume’s science of man provides a chemical-organismic account of mental functioning that fits an intellectual environment dominated by post-Newtonian natural philosophy.

I am grateful for discussions with László Kocsis and Krisztián Pete. My work has been supported by the MTA Lendület ‘Morals and Science’ Project.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It is convenient to interpret Hume’s distinction here with Sellars’ (1963) famous contrast in mind between the manifest and the scientific image.

  2. 2.

    There are similar revisionary tendencies in contemporary Newtonian medicine and natural philosophy, too. John Keill’s introductory text to natural philosophy, which might have been well known to Hume (see Barfoot, 1990, 171, 172), also complained about the explanatory emptiness of “faculty” in the hands of the Perpateticks who, instead of discovering causes, had “invented such Terms, as are very fit to express natural Actions.” This, however, does not mean that one should be “ashamed to use” such terms as “Quality, Faculty, Attraction, and the like”, only that we should not “pretend to define the true and physical Cause or Modus of Action” (Keill, 1745, 2, 4).

  3. 3.

    The classic statement of this interpretation is Kemp Smith (1941, 71, 72). For more recent formulations see Bennett (2001, 2:352), Pitson (2002, 14), Wilson (2009, 61), Garrett (2015, 50), de Pierris (2015, 17 etc.).

  4. 4.

    The idea of Hume’s commitment to cognitive atomism is still influential today. Some of its features are discussed in the context of contemporary cognitive psychology in Fodor, (2003, 146–152).

  5. 5.

    As for magnetism see Norton and Norton (2000, 429). Interestingly, in the editorial material published as the second volume of the Clarendon Edition of the Treatise Norton and Norton (T 2:701) point out, rightly I think, that attraction for Newton had a broader sense than gravitation.

  6. 6.

    I know of no direct evidence that Hume was acquainted with Geoffroy’s achievements, but they were widely known and discussed in France, and they were also appropriated in a Malebranchian fashion by Fontenelle (see Shank, 2008, 114–120). It is not implausible to think that while at La Flèche Hume encountered these ideas. Besides, through unofficial public lecture courses Geoffroy’s affinity table became part of “informal pedagogy” in Britain by the 1730s (see Taylor 2016, 36).

References

Hume’s Works

  • EHU. (2000). An enquiry concerning human understanding (T. Beauchamp, Ed.). Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • T. (2007). A treatise of human nature (2 Vols., D.F. Norton & M.J. Norton, Eds.). Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

Secondary Sources

  • Barfoot, M. (1990). Hume and the culture of science in the early eighteenth century. In M. A. Stewart (Ed.), Studies in the philosophy of Scottish enlightenment (pp. 151–190). Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. (2001). Learning from six philosophers (Vol. 2). Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Biro, J. (2009). Hume’s new science of the mind. In D. Norton & J. Taylor (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Hume (2nd ed., pp. 40–69). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohon, R. (2008). Hume’s morality: Feeling and fabrication. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Demeter, T. (2016). David Hume and the culture of Scottish newtonianism: Methodology and ideology in enlightenment inquiry. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demeter, T. (2017). A chemistry of human nature: Chemical imagery in Hume’s Treatise. Early Science and Medicine, 22(2–3), 208–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demeter, T. (2020). The science in Hume’s science of man. Journal of Scottish Philosophy, 18(3).

    Google Scholar 

  • de Pierris, G. (2015). Ideas, evidence, and method: Hume’s skepticism and naturalism concerning knowledge and causation. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dixon, T. (2003). From passions to emotions: The creation of a secular psychological category. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Garrett, D. (2015). Hume. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (2003). Hume variations. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keill, J. (1745). An introduction to natural philosophy, or philosophical lectures read in the University of Oxford A.D. 1700.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kemp Smith, N. (1941). The philosophy of David Hume. Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, M. G. (2003). Affinity, that elusive dream: A genealogy of the chemical revolution. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Landy, D. (2017). Hume’s science of human nature: Scientific realism, reason, and substantial explanation. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Penelhum, T. (2000). Themes in Hume. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitson, A. E. (2002). Hume’s philosophy of the self. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pléh, Cs. (2008). History and theories of the mind. Akadémiai Kiadó.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1963). Philosophy and the scientific image of man. In W. Sellars (Ed.), Science, perception, and reality (pp. 1–40). Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shank, J. B. (2008). The Newton wars and the beginning of the French enlightenment. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, B. (1977). Hume. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, G. (2016). Choice or no choice? Affinity and theory choice. In E. Tobin & C. Ambrosio (Eds.), Theory choice in the history of chemical practices (pp. 29–54). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D. B. (2009). Seeking nature’s logic: Natural philosophy in the Scottish enlightenment. University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tamás Demeter .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Demeter, T. (2022). The Foundational Document of Cognitive Science. In: Gervain, J., Csibra, G., Kovács, K. (eds) A Life in Cognition. Language, Cognition, and Mind, vol 11. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-66175-5_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics