Skip to main content

An Artifactual Perspective on Idealization: Constant Capacitance and the Hodgkin and Huxley Model

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Models and Idealizations in Science

Abstract

Natalia Carrillo and Tarja Knuuttila claim that there are two traditions of thinking about idealization offering almost opposite views on their functioning and epistemic status. While one tradition views idealizations as epistemic deficiencies, the other one highlights the epistemic benefits of idealization. Both of them treat idealizations as deliberate misrepresentations, however. They then argue for an artifactual account of idealization, comparing it to the traditional accounts of idealization, and exemplifying it through the Hodgkin and Huxley model of the nerve impulse. From the artifactual perspective, the epistemic benefits and deficiencies introduced by idealization frequently come in a package due to the way idealization draws together different resources in model construction. Accordingly, idealization tends to be holistic in that it is not often easily attributable to some specific parts of the model. They conclude that the artifactual approach offers a unifying view into idealization in that it is able to recover several basic philosophical insights motivating both the deficiency and epistemic benefit accounts, while being simultaneously detached from the idea of distortion by misrepresentation.

This project received funding from the European Research Council (ERC) under the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme (grant agreement No 818772) and from the UNAM PAPIIT project “Cognición, artefactualidad y representación en la ciencia.” IN402018.

Natalia Carrillo and Tarja Knuuttila contributed equally to this work.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Frigg and Hartmann (2012) have introduced a somewhat similar distinction between Aristotelian and Galilean idealization.

  2. 2.

    Potochnik (2017) considers idealization rampant and unchecked in science. In her account idealizations help limited cognitive agents to set aside complicating factors to identify causal patterns. Consequently, Potochnik’s notion of idealization contains features of both deficiency and epistemic benefit accounts.

  3. 3.

    Artifacts do not have to be human made objects. A rock used to open a clam may be thought of as an artifact even though it is not constructed by humans for that purpose. Artifactuality in general can rather be defined through the roles an object plays in some human (or animal) activity.

  4. 4.

    Models are typically multipurpose tools: the aims of modeling may and do change, and multiple aims may co-exist as models are being reused, reconstructed and repurposed by different groups and stakeholders.

  5. 5.

    The epistemic benefit account by Batterman and Rice (2014) seems to be in line with the artifactual account, since they focus on the epistemic work done by limiting operations.

  6. 6.

    Rice has recently argued that applying mathematical methods involves holistic distortion that enables researchers to “to extract various kinds of modal information” (2018, 2802).

  7. 7.

    A solution in which each ion has a valence of 1, and produces two ions when dissociated.

  8. 8.

    The voltage clamp fixes the transmembrane voltage of the membrane to a value set by the experimenter, and records the current that had to be injected in order to maintain voltage steady at that value. That recording is the inverse of the actions that took place in the membrane, and was interpreted by Hodgkin and Huxley and others as the inverse of the transmembrane currents.

  9. 9.

    A capacitor is usually constructed of two plates of conducting material separated at a distance small enough so that charges on one side will feel electric repulsion or attraction from charges on the other plate. If connected to a battery, one plate becomes negatively charged with respect to the other.

  10. 10.

    This is the equivalent of a battery. When a cable connects one pole of the battery to the other, the charges tend to move from the pole with excess negative charge to the one with less negative charge.

  11. 11.

    Hodgkin and Huxley used the term “conductance,” which is the multiplicative inverse of the resistance, but for simplicity we describe them as resistances since both terms retain the same underlying concept.

  12. 12.

    Hodgkin and Huxley also considered the contribution of a “leak” current, which accounted for minor errors in prediction and measurement. We are not discussing this for simplicity since it does not contribute substantially to the excitable behavior of the axon.

  13. 13.

    Craver’s criticism of Weber is a part of his more comprehensive mechanistic account of explanation, whose main target of criticism is the covering law account of explanation.

  14. 14.

    Discrete ion fluxes were detected by Neher and Sackmann in the 1970s, supporting the idea of a passive mechanism of ionic transport. Later, in the late 1990s, evidence of the existence of the potassium ion channel was obtained with x-ray crystallography. These results were considered as sound evidence for the hypothesis that it is voltage-sensitive protein ion channels that change the permeability of the membrane during a nerve impulse.

  15. 15.

    We consider aggregative abstraction an idealization, since we take that omissions and distortions cannot sharply be distinguished, in contrast to Levy (2018), who holds that we ought—and can—differentiate between them. Another justification for considering aggregative abstraction as an idealization is due to the distinction between Galilean and minimalist idealization. If minimalist idealization is understood as removing non-difference-making factors (or their contributions), it would amount to the conventional abstraction-by-omission account. So, by the standards of already established discussion of idealization, it is legitimate to regard Levy’s “aggregative abstraction” as idealization.

  16. 16.

    Except for the initial charging of the capacitor at the instant when the voltage is fixed to a particular value with the voltage-clamp.

References

  • Alexandrova, A. (2006). Connecting economic models to the real world: Game theory and the FCC spectrum auctions. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 36(2), 173–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. (2009). Idealization and modeling. Synthese, 169(3), 427–446.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R., & Rice, C. (2014). Minimal model explanations. Philosophy of Science, 81(3), 349–376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, J. (1902). Untersuchungen zur Thermodynamik der bioelektrischen Ströme. Pflüger Archiv Für Die Gesammte Physiologie Des Menschen Und Der Thiere, 92, 521–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogen, J. (2008). The Hodgkin-Huxley equations and the concrete model: Comments on Craver, Schaffner, and Weber. Philosophy of Science, 75(5), 1034–1046.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carrillo, N. (2018). Integración de analogías en la modelación científica. Revista Colombiana de Filosofía de la Ciencia, 18(37), 317–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrillo, N. (2019). Modelación y abstracción en la investigación de la señal nerviosa. PhD Dissertation. http://132.248.9.195/ptd2019/mayo/0789695/Index.html.

  • Cartwright, N. (1999). The vanity of rigour in economics: Theoretical models and Galilean experiments. Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science. Discussion paper series 43/99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cole, K., & Baker, R. (1941). Longitudinal impedance of the squid giant axon. The Journal of General Physiology, 24(6), 771–788.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2006). When mechanistic models explain. Synthese, 153(3), 355–376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2008). Physical law and mechanistic explanation in the Hodgkin and Huxley model of the action potential. Philosophy of Science, 75(5), 1022–1033.

    Google Scholar 

  • El Hady, A., & Machta, B. (2015). Mechanical surface waves accompany action potential propagation. Nature Communications, 6(6697), 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., & Hartmann, S. (2012). Models in science. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved January 26, 2020 from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/models-science/.

  • Gelfert, A. (2016). How to do science with models. Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Abstractions, idealizations, and evolutionary biology. In A. Barberousse, M. Morange, & T. Pradeu (Eds.), Mapping the future of biology: Evolving concepts and theories (pp. 47–56). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heimburg, T., & Jackson, A. (2005). On soliton propagation in biomembranes and nerves. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 102(28), 9790–9795.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgkin, A. L., Huxley, A., & Katz, B. (1952). Measurement of current-voltage relations in the membrane of the giant axon of Loligo. The Journal of Physiology, 116, 424–448.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgkin, A. L., & Huxley, A. (1952a). Currents carried by sodium and potassium ions through the membrane of the giant axon of Loligo. The Journal of Physiology, 116, 449–472.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgkin, A., & Huxley, A. L. (1952b). A quantitative description of membrane current and its application to conduction and excitation in nerve. The Journal of Physiology, 117, 500–544.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, A. (1999). Overton on the indispensability of sodium ions. Brain Research Bulletin, 50(5–6), 307–308.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iwasa, K., & Tasaki, I. (1980). Mechanical changes in squid giant axons associated with production of action potentials. Topics in Catalysis, 95(3), 1328–1331.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T. (2005). Models, representation, and mediation. Philosophy of Science, 72(5), 1260–1271.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T. (2011). Modelling and representing: An artefactual approach to model-based representation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 42(2), 262–271.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T. (2017). Imagination extended and embedded: Artifactual versus fictional accounts of models. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1545-2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T., and Morgan, M. (2019). Deidealization: No easy reversals. Philosophy of Science, 86(4), 641–661.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T., and Loettgers, A. (2014). Varieties of noise: Analogical reasoning in synthetic biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 48, 76–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A. (2013). What was Hodgkin and Huxley’s achievement? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65(3), 469–492.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A. (2018). Idealization and abstraction: Refining the distinction. Synthesehttps://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1721-z

  • Lowenhaupt, B. (1996). Gated, ion-selective sodium and potassium channels of the giant axon: Do they have a role in bioelectric excitation? Electro-and Magnetobiology, 15(2), 151–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1985). Galilean idealization. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 16(3), 247–273.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (1992). On the method of isolation in economics. Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities (Special Issue Idealization IV: Intelligibility in Science, edited by Craig Dilworth). 26, 319–354.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nernst, W. (1889). Die elektromotorische Wirksamkeit der Jonen. Zeitschrift für Physikalische Chemie, 4(1), 129–181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostwald, W. (1890). Elektrische Eigenschaften halbdurchlässiger Scheidewände. Zeitschrift für Physikalische Chemie, 6(1), 71–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik, A. (2017). Idealization and the aims of science. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rice, C. (2018). Idealized models, holistic distortions, and universality. Synthese, 195(6), 2795–2819.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rice, C. (2019). Models don’t decompose that way: A holistic view of idealized models. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 70(1), 179–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. (2008). Theories, models, and equations in biology: The heuristic search for emergent simplifications in neurobiology. Philosophy of Science, 75(5), 1008–1021.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sklar, L. (2000). Theory and truth: Philosophical critique within foundational science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2008). Depth: An account of scientific explanation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Takashima, S. (1979). Admittance change of squid axon during action potentials: Change in capacitive component due to sodium currents. Biophysical Journal, 26(1), 133–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tasaki, I. (1982). Physiology and electrochemistry of nerve fibers. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Teller, P. (2008). Of course idealizations are incommensurable! In L. Soler, H. Sankey & P. Hoyningen-Huene (Eds.), Rethinking scientific change and theory comparison (pp. 247–264). Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (2005). Philosophy of experimental biology. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (2008). Causes without mechanisms: Experimental regularities, physical laws, and neuroscientific explanation. Philosophy of Science, 75(5), 995–1007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2007). Three kinds of idealization. Journal of Philosophy, 104(12), 639–659.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Natalia Carrillo .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Carrillo, N., Knuuttila, T. (2021). An Artifactual Perspective on Idealization: Constant Capacitance and the Hodgkin and Huxley Model. In: Cassini, A., Redmond, J. (eds) Models and Idealizations in Science. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 50. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-65802-1_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics