Skip to main content

Peirce, Russell and Abductive Regression

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Abduction in Cognition and Action

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 59))

Abstract

Below are reflections on Peirce’s conception of abductive methods and Russell’s conception of regressive methods. Along the way, it will be necessary to examine the marked differences between Russell and Frege on the ins and outs of logicism, from which latter the regressivist ideas first emerged. Russell was aware of Peirce’s contributions to the algebraization of logic and Peirce was aware of Russell’s writings on logicism. However, in framing his thoughts about regressive methods, Russell showed no familiarity with Peirce’s treatment of abductive methods. In 1907, Russell read to the Cambridge Mathematics Club an essay entitled “The regressive method of discovering the premises of mathematics.” Since that paper didn’t see the published light of day until three years after Russell’s death in 1970, Peirce couldn’t have taken notice of it in developing his ideas about abduction. Even so, it has been suggested that there exists a noteworthy similarity between Russell’s regressivism and Peirce’s abductivism. The principal purpose of this essay is to show the resemblance to have been misjudged, in which case, my title would have to be corrected.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Peirce [25,26,27]. Putnam [32, p. 297] and Quine [34, p. 259]. See oppositely (and earlier) Goldfarb [12]. We needn’t settle the matter here.

  2. 2.

    Peirce [28, p. 143], Hereafter RLT.

  3. 3.

    Peirce (CP 5.189), in [29] Citations are structured as follows: “CP 5.189” denotes Volume V of Collected Papers, p. 189. Line numbers are for referential convenience, and I have changed the original schematic letters to more intuitive ones and removed the italics.

  4. 4.

    For a recent more detailed exposition, see Woods [45]. See also Gabbay and Woods [11], Magnani [22] and Park [23]. All these works adopt naturalistic assumptions for the logic of inference. A still unsettled disagreement is about whether all abductions are inferences to the best explanation. The authors cited in this note think that it is not that intrinsically. But here, too, we needn’t settle the question for what matters here.

  5. 5.

    For expositionary ease, I use “F” ambiguously. In Peirce’s Schema it names some given fact or state of affairs. When it occurs as the conclusion of a piece of reasoning, it names a proposition that states that fact. I leave it to context to disambiguate.

  6. 6.

    Fruitful conjecture is nicely discussed by philosophically trained historians of science. See, for example, Tappenden [42] and Ferreirós and Gray [7].

  7. 7.

    More on this can be found in Chap. 9, “Putting inconsistency in its place”, of Woods [46].

  8. 8.

    A causal-response epistemology sees the beliefs that qualify as knowledge as causal responses to information-processing under specified conditions. (Woods [44], Sect. 3.5). In contrast, a causal-contact epistemology, requires a believer’s causal contact with the object of belief [13].

  9. 9.

    For more enriched versions see Chiffi and Pietarinen [3, 4].

  10. 10.

    Poincaré’s Conjecture says that every simply connected closed 3-manifold is homeographic to the 3-sphere. Riemann’s Hypothesis is that all non-trivial zeros of the Riemann zeta function have a real part equal to 0.5. Hodge’s Conjecture is that certain de Rham cohomology classes are algebraic.

  11. 11.

    Since most epistemologies require that truth be a condition on knowledge, henceforth I’ll frame the worry as epistemic.

  12. 12.

    Notwithstanding some occasional slippage. For example, he endorsed the idea that the functions of which the True and the False were their respective values could be left to arbitrary stipulation.

  13. 13.

    Frege [9].

  14. 14.

    Frege [8].

  15. 15.

    Gray [15].

  16. 16.

    Poincaré [30].

  17. 17.

    Dedekind [5]. Reference here to the Foreword of the first edition.

  18. 18.

    Dedekind [6] and Peano [24].

  19. 19.

    Grattan-Guinness [14].

  20. 20.

    Whitehead and Russell [43].

  21. 21.

    In about these same words, Frege characterizes the à priori, thus collapsing the Kantian distinction between the alethic property of analyticity and the epistemic property of apriority.

  22. 22.

    Blanchette [2, p. 31].

  23. 23.

    For a fuller discussion of this difficulty, readers could consult Woods [47].

  24. 24.

    Russell [38].

  25. 25.

    In “On the axioms of geometry” of 1899, Russell lists seven simple and indefinable concepts: addition, number, order, equality, less, greater and manifold. See Griffin and Lewis [17].

  26. 26.

    Russell took a somewhat rigourist approach even to mathematical stipulation. He dismisses definition by abstraction, which “… suffers from a wholly fatal formal effect: it does not show that only one object satisfies the definition.” (p. 114).

  27. 27.

    See, for example, Putnam [31], Griffin [16] and Krall [21].

  28. 28.

    For reservations, see Griffin [16].

  29. 29.

    Principles, xviii.

  30. 30.

    Irvine [20].

  31. 31.

    Russell [36, 29–44]. Reprinted in the first edition of Russell (1910).

  32. 32.

    Bertrand Russell, Letter to Frege, in van Heijenoort [39, 40]. Frege’s letter in reply follows at pages 127–128.

  33. 33.

    Russell appears to have been unaware of Zermelo’s derivation of it the year before. See Hallett [19].

  34. 34.

    Russell [35]. Reprinted with revisions and a new title in Russell (1918).

  35. 35.

    This view is developed in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics and Metaphysics [1]. Details can be found in Woods [47].

  36. 36.

    Irvine [20] reports that suggestion in ft. 26, p. 322. Kleiner is a philosopher of science at the University of Georgia.

  37. 37.

    Of course, volume one of Principia has yet to appear. Shouldn’t we instead take Russell to be thinking of the logic of the Principles? I think not. On May 13, 1903, a few days after its publication, Russell had lost confidence in Principles, writing that “it seems to me a foolish book, and I am ashamed to think that I have spent the best part of six years upon it. Now that it is done, I can allow myself to believe that it was not worth doing—an odd luxury!” See Griffin [18]. Even allowing for Russell’s habit of self-effacement, it is better to locate his logical thinking in 1907 in Russell [37] in van Heijenoort [10], pages 152–182, which would appear a year later and would be absorbed into Principia, whose first appearance was two years after that.

References

  1. Aristotle: The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised English Translation, vol. 2. In: Barnes, J. (ed.) Princeton University Press, Princeton (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Blanchette P.A.: Axioms in Frege. In: Rossberg, M., Ebert, P. (eds.) Essays on Frege’s Basic Laws of Arithmetic. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  3. Chiffi, D., Pietarinen, A.-V.: Abductive inference with a pragmatic framework. Synthese. 1007/s11239-018-1824-6

    Google Scholar 

  4. Chiffi, D., Pietarinen, A.-V.: The extended Gabbay-Woods Schema and scientific practice. In: Gabbay, D.M., Magnani, L., Park, W., Pietarinen, A.-V. (eds.) Natural Arguments, A Volume in the Tributes Series. College Publications, London (2019)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Dedekind, R.: Essays on the Theory of Numbers, Dover, New York. Reference here to the foreword of the first edition. First published in 1872 (1963a)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Dedekind, R. The Nature and Meaning of Numbers. Reissued in two volumes by Dover. First published in 1888 (1963b)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ferreirós, J., Gray, J. (eds.): The Architecture of Modern Mathematics: Essays in History and Philosophy. Oxford University Press, New York (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Frege, G.: Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Wilhelm Koebner, Breslau (1884). Translated into English as Foundations of Arithmetic, J. L. Austin, Blackwell, Oxford (1950)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Frege, G.: Grundgesteze der Arithmetik. Herman Pohle, Jena (1893/1903). In: Ebert, P.A., Rossberg, M., Wright, C. (eds.) Translated into English as Basic Laws of Arithmetic. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Frege, G., Letter to Russell. In: van Heijenoort, J. (ed.) From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931, pp. 127–128 (1967)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Gabbay, D.M., Woods, J.: The Reach of Abduction: Insight and Trial. North-Holland, Amsterdam (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  12. Goldfarb, W.: Logtic in the twenties: the nature of the quantifier. J. Symbol. Logic 44, 351–368 (1979)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Goldman, A.: A causal theory of knowing. J. Philos. 64, 357–372 (1967)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Grattan-Guinness, I.: The Search for Mathematical Roots, 1870–1940. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Gray, J.J.: Anxiety and abstraction in nineteenth-century mathematics. Sci. Context 17, 23–47 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Griffin, N.: New work on Russell’s early philosophy. Russell 2, 69–83 (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  17. Griffin, N., Lewis, A.C. (eds.) The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell Volume II Philosophical Papers, 1876–1899, pp. 390–415. George Allen & Unwin, London (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  18. Griffin, N. (ed.) The selected letters of Bertrand Russell, vol. 1. In: The Private Years, 1884–1914, Letter 120. Houghton Mifflin, Boston (1992)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Hallett, M.: Cantorian Set Theory and Limitations of Size. Clarendon Press, Oxford (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Irvine, A.D.: Epistemic logicism and Russell’s regressive method. Philos. Stud. 55, 303–327 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Krall, A.: The aim of Russell’s logicism. Synthese 191, 1493–1510 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Magnani, L.: The Abductive Structure of Scientific Creativity: An Essay on the Ecology of Cognition, Cham. Springer, Switzerland (2017)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  23. Park, W.: Abduction in Context: The Conjectural Dynamics of Scientific Reasoning, Cham. Springer, Switzerland (2017)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  24. Peano, G.: The principles of arithmetic, presented by a new method. In: van Heijenoort, pp. 85–97. First published in 1889 (1967)

    Google Scholar 

  25. Peirce, C.S.: Description of a notation for the logic of relatives, resulting from an amplification of the conceptions of Boole’s calculus of logic. Memoirs Am. Acad. 9, 317–378 (1870)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Peirce, C.S.: The logic of relatives. In: Peirce, C. S. (ed.) Studies in Logic, pp. 1870-203. Little, Brown & Co., Boston (1883a)

    Google Scholar 

  27. Peirce, C.S.: Second intentional logic. In: Peirce, pp. 56–58 (1883b)

    Google Scholar 

  28. Peirce, C.S.: Reasoning and the Logic of Things: The Cambridge Conference Lectures of 1898. In: Kettner, K. L. (ed.) With an Introduction by Kettner and Hilary Putnam. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA (1992)

    Google Scholar 

  29. Peirce, C.S.: Collected Papers. In: Hartshorne, C., Weiss, P. (vol. I–VI) Burks, A.W. (vols. VII and VIII) (eds.) Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA (1931–1958)

    Google Scholar 

  30. Poincaré, H.: Du rôle de l’intuition de la logique in mathematiques. Compte Rendue der Deuxième Congrés International des Mathématiciens, Paris (1902)

    Google Scholar 

  31. Putnam, H.: The thesis that mathematics is logic. In: Shoenman, R. (ed.) Bertrand Russell: Philosopher of the Century, pp. 273–303. Allen & Unwin, London (1967)

    Google Scholar 

  32. Putnam, H.: Peirce as a logician. Hist. Math. 9, 290–301 (1982)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Quine, W.V.: Peirce’s Logic. In: Quine [34]

    Google Scholar 

  34. Quine, W.V.: Selected Logic Papers, pp. 258–265. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA (1995)

    Google Scholar 

  35. Russell, B.: Recent work on the principles of mathematics. Int. Month. 4, 83–101 (1901). Reprinted with revisions and a new title in Russell (1918)

    Google Scholar 

  36. Russell, B.: The study of mathematics. New Q. I, 29–44 (1907). Reprinted in the first edition of Russell (1910) Bertrand Russell Philosophical Essays. Longmans, Green & Co., London (1910)

    Google Scholar 

  37. Russell, B.: Mysticism and Logic. Longmans Green, London (1918)

    Google Scholar 

  38. Russell, B.: The Principles of Mathematics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1903); second edition. Allen & Unwin, London (1937)

    Google Scholar 

  39. Russell, B.: Letter to Frege. In: van Heijenoort (ed.), pp. 124–125 (1967a)

    Google Scholar 

  40. Russell, B.: Mathematic logic as based on the theory of types. In: van Heijenoort (ed.), pp. 152–182 (1967b)

    Google Scholar 

  41. Russell, B.: The regressive method of discovering the premises of mathematics. In: Lackey, D., Russell (eds.) Essays in Analysis. George Allen & Unwin, London (1973)

    Google Scholar 

  42. Tappenden, J.: Metatheory and mathematical practice in Frege. Philos. Topics 25, 213–264 (1997)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Whitehead, A.N., Russell, B.: Principia Mathematica, vol. 3. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1910–1913). Second edition, 1925 and 1927

    Google Scholar 

  44. Woods, J. Errors of Reasoning: Naturalizing the Logic of Inference, vol. 45. Studies in Logic. College Publications, London (2013); reprinted with corrections 2014

    Google Scholar 

  45. Woods, J.: Reorienting the logic of abduction. In: Magnani, L., Bertolotti, T. (eds.) Springer Handbook of Model-Based Science, pp. 137–150. Springer, Berlin (2017)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  46. Woods, J.: Truth in Fiction: Rethinking its Logic, vol. 391. Synthese Library: Springer, Cham, Switzerland (2018)

    Google Scholar 

  47. Woods, J.: What did Frege take Russell to have proved? Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02324-4 (2019)

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Woods .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Woods, J. (2021). Peirce, Russell and Abductive Regression. In: Shook, J.R., Paavola, S. (eds) Abduction in Cognition and Action. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 59. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-61773-8_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics