Skip to main content

The Archaeology and Philosophy of Health: Navigating the New Normal Problem

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Explorations in Archaeology and Philosophy

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 433))

Abstract

It is often taken for granted that notions of health and disease are generally applicable across the biological world, in that they are not restricted to contemporary human beings, and can be unproblematically applied to a variety of organisms both past and present (taking relevant differences between species into account). In the historical sciences it is also common to normatively contrast health states of individuals and populations from different times and places: e.g., to say that due to nutrition or pathogen load, some lived healthier lives than others. However, health concepts in contemporary philosophy of medicine have not been developed with such cross-lineage, non-human, or diachronic uses in mind, and this generates what I call the ‘new normal’ problem. I argue that the new normal problem shows that current naturalistic approaches to health (when based on biological reference classes) are worryingly incomplete. Using examples drawn from evolutionary archaeology and the human fossil record, I outline an alternative, function-based strategy for naturalizing health that might help address the new normal problem. Interestingly, this might also reconstruct a certain uniqueness for humans in the philosophy and science of health, due to the deep history of obligate enculturation and cultural adaptation that archaeology demonstrates.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See for example Murphy (2020), and the absence of such considerations in significant handbooks and collected volumes (e.g., Carel and Cooper 2014; Humber and Almeder 1997; Huneman et al. 2015; Marcum 2016; Schramme and Edwards 2017; Solomon et al. 2017).

  2. 2.

    It should be noted that this casts doubt on the biological objectivity of the reference classes used in medical practice, as ‘you are healthy for a man/woman your age’ typically carries with it an implicit ‘… in your country/territory/ethnic group’.

  3. 3.

    Approaches appealing to common accounts of biological function (such as the selected effects account) include Chin-Yee and Upshur (2017); Griffiths and Matthewson (2018); Matthewson and Griffiths (2017); Neander (2016); Wakefield (1992, 2007). The organizational account of function has also been appealed to for health-naturalist purposes (Saborido and Moreno 2015). The arguments in this chapter are intended to be broadly compatible with any of these, though I err on the side of language friendly to the selected effects account. 

  4. 4.

    Boorse, when pressed, makes a similar suggestion: “to the problem of typical disease, I see no solution but to retreat to a concept of ideal design which, so far, I am unable to define” (Boorse 2014, p. 707).

  5. 5.

    I am using ‘homology’ here in a very loose sense. Functionally homologous groups (in my sense) would be the result of both common selective pressures that explain the origin of that function, and subsequent maintaining selection. They would therefore often be paraphyletic, i.e., subsequent divergent selective pressures could split some lineages away from the functionally homologous group. This may be a problematic use of the terminology (Griffiths 2006).

  6. 6.

    Though this should not be over-stated, see Pearson et al. (2006).

  7. 7.

    However, tooth shape in early Homo species had already changed to become more capable of eating tougher and more elastic foods than the hard, brittle foodstuffs that Australopithecus afarensis specialized in (Ungar 2004).

  8. 8.

    Though lack of convergence is by no means definitive proof—drift and other evolutionary processes can be sources of variation that are fitness-neutral and not pathological.

  9. 9.

    As hypothesized by Ogilvie et al. (1989), the widespread underdevelopment of the tooth enamel in their sample (of 699 crowns) is indicative of nutritional stress from weaning to adolescence.

  10. 10.

    Cultural evolution theory is divided regarding whether ‘selection’ is the best way (or even necessary at all) to describe the mechanisms by which successful cultural traits are propagated and/or upregulated. See for example Tim Lewens’ taxonomy of cultural evolutionary thinking and related discussion (Brusse 2017; Heyes 2016; Lewens 2015). Indeed, clarifying relevant notions of success and cultural analogues of fitness and adaptiveness are non-trivial (Ramsey and De Block 2017), meaning that the idea of a cultural adaptation should be approached with reasonable caution. I am assuming that some such useful account is possible for the purposes of this discussion, though perhaps only in a very loose sense.

  11. 11.

    This is not to say that the basic cognitive capacities to acquire traits did not evolve through biological natural selection, but even this is disputed (e.g., by Heyes 2018, who argues that there is a degree of cultural propagation even for the enabling capacity-traits of cultural propagation).

  12. 12.

    For example, we might perhaps understand cultural adaptations as adaptations proper to the degree that they are intergenerationally stable and partake in other paradigmatic features of adaptations, in a multi-dimensional conceptual space (à la Mitchell 2000), though this obviously presents further challenges.

  13. 13.

    Famously culminating in the conference and subsequent book Man the Hunter (Lee and DeVore 1968).

  14. 14.

    This is of course also bracketing off exogenous drivers like climatic change.

References

  • Aktipis CA, Boddy AM, Jansen G, Hibner U, Hochberg ME, Maley CC, Wilkinson GS (2015) Cancer across the tree of life: cooperation and cheating in multicellularity. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 370(1673):20140219. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2014.0219

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Argue D, Groves CP, Lee MSY, Jungers WL (2017) The affinities of Homo floresiensis based on phylogenetic analyses of cranial, dental, and postcranial characters. J Hum Evol 107:107–133

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baab KL, Brown P, Falk D, Richtsmeier JT, Hildebolt CF, Smith K, Jungers W (2016) A critical evaluation of the Down Syndrome diagnosis for LB1, type specimen of Homo floresiensis. PLoS One 11(6):e0155731

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker G (2006) The agricultural revolution in prehistory: why did foragers become farmers? Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Berger TD, Trinkaus E (1995) Patterns of trauma among the Neandertals. J Archaeol Sci 22(6):841–852

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse C (1977) Health as a theoretical concept. Philos Sci 44(4):542–573

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse C (1997) A rebuttal on health. In: Humber JM, Almeder RF (eds) What is disease. Humana Press, Totowa, pp 1–134

    Google Scholar 

  • Boorse C (2011) Concepts of health and disease. In: Gifford F (ed) Philosophy of medicine. North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp 13–64. https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-444-51787-6.50002-7

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse C (2014) A second rebuttal on health. J Med Philos 39(6):683–724

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R, Richerson PJ, Henrich J (2011) The cultural niche: why social learning is essential for human adaptation. Proc Natl Acad Sci 108(suppl-2):10918–10925. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1100290108

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown P (2012) LB1 and LB6 Homo floresiensis are not modern human (Homo sapiens) cretins. J Hum Evol 62(2):201–224

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown P, Sutikna T, Morwood MJ, Soejono RP et al (2004) A new small-bodied hominin from the Late Pleistocene of Flores, Indonesia. Nature 431(7012):1055–1061

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brusse C (2017) Making do without selection—review essay of “cultural evolution: conceptual challenges” by Tim Lewens. Biol Philos 32(2):307–319

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brusse C (2020) Signaling theories of religion: models and explanation. Relig Brain Behav 10(3):272–291. https://doi.org/10.1080/2153599X.2019.1678514

  • Bulbulia J (2004) Religious costs as adaptations that signal altruistic intention. Evol Cognit 10(1):19–38

    Google Scholar 

  • Canguilhem G (1989) The normal and the pathological. Zone Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Carel H, Cooper R (eds) (2014) Health, illness and disease: philosophical essays. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Caspari R, Lee S-H (2004) Older age becomes common late in human evolution. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 101(30):10895–10900

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caspari R, Lee S-H (2006) Is human longevity a consequence of cultural change or modern biology? Am J Phys Anthropol 129(4):512–517

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chin-Yee B, Upshur REG (2017) Re-evaluating concepts of biological function in clinical medicine: towards a new naturalistic theory of disease. Theor Med Bioeth 38(4):245–264

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper R (2017) Health and disease. In: Marcum J (ed) Bloomsbury companion to contemporary philosophy of medicine. Bloomsbury Academic, London, pp 275–296

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond JM (1998) Guns, germs and steel: a short history of everybody for the last 13,000 years. Random House, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Eckhardt RB, Henneberg M, Weller AS, Hsu KJ (2014) Rare events in earth history include the LB1 human skeleton from Flores, Indonesia, as a developmental singularity, not a unique taxon. Proc Natl Acad Sci 111(33):11961–11966

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grauer AL (ed) (2012) A companion to paleopathology. Wiley-Blackwell, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Grauer AL (2018) A century of paleopathology. Am J Phys Anthropol 165(4):904–914

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (2006) Function, homology, and character individuation. Philos Sci 73(1):1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE, Matthewson J (2018) Evolution, dysfunction, and disease: a reappraisal. Br J Philos Sci 69(2):301–327

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Handfield T (2020) The coevolution of sacred value and religion. Relig, Brain Behav 10(3):252–271. https://doi.org/10.1080/2153599X.2019.1678512

  • Hawkes K, Coxworth JE (2013) Grandmothers and the evolution of human longevity: a review of findings and future directions. Evol Anthropol Issues News Rev 22(6):294–302

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawkes K, O’Connell JF (2005) How old is human longevity? J Hum Evol 49(5):650–653

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henneberg M, Thorne A (2004) Flores human may be pathological Homo sapiens. Before Farm 4(1):2–4

    Google Scholar 

  • Henneberg M, Eckhardt RB, Chavanaves S, Hsu KJ (2014) Evolved developmental homeostasis disturbed in LB1 from Flores, Indonesia, denotes Down syndrome and not diagnostic traits of the invalid species Homo floresiensis. Proc Natl Acad Sci 111(33):11967–11972

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henrich J (2015) The secret of our success: how culture is driving human evolution, domesticating our species, and making us smarter. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heyes C (2016) Tim Lewens: cultural evolution. Br J Philos Sci 67(4):1189–1193. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axv05

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heyes C (2018) Cognitive gadgets: the cultural evolution of thinking. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Humber JM, Almeder RF (eds) (1997) What is disease? Humana Press, Totowa

    Google Scholar 

  • Huneman P, Lambert G, Silberstein M (eds) (2015) Classification, disease and evidence: new essays in the philosophy of medicine. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaifu Y, Kono RT, Sutikna T, Saptomo EW, Jatmiko Awe RD, Baba H (2015) Descriptions of the dental remains of Homo floresiensis. Anthropol Sci. https://doi.org/10.1537/ase.150501

  • Kingma E (2007) What is it to be healthy? Analysis 67(294):128–133

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kingma E (2014) Health and disease: social constructivism as a combination of naturalism and normativism. In: Carel H, Cooper R (eds) Health, illness and disease: philosophical essays. Routledge, New York, pp 37–56

    Google Scholar 

  • Klepinger LL (1983) Differential diagnosis in paleopathology and the concept of disease evolution. Med Anthropol 7(1):73–77

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland KN (2017) Darwin’s unfinished symphony: how culture made the human mind. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Larsen CS (2006) The agricultural revolution as environmental catastrophe: implications for health and lifestyle in the Holocene. Quat Int 150(1):12–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee RB, DeVore I (eds) (1968) Man the hunter. Aldine de Gruyte, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewens T (2015) Cultural evolution: conceptual challenges. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Marcum JA (2016) The Bloomsbury companion to contemporary philosophy of medicine. Bloomsbury Academic, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthewson J, Griffiths PE (2017) Biological criteria of disease: four ways of going wrong. J Med Philos 42(4):447–466

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McBrearty S (2007) Down with the revolution. In: Mellars P, Boyle L, Bar-Yosef O, Stringer C (eds) Rethinking the human revolution: new behavioural and biological perspectives on the origin and dispersal of modern humans. McDonald Institute Archaeological Publications, Cambridge, pp 133–151

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell SD (2000) Dimensions of scientific law. Philos Sci 67(2):242–265

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montgomery SH (2013) Primate brains, the ‘island rule’ and the evolution of Homo floresiensis. J Hum Evol 65(6):750–760

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morwood MJ, Soejono RP, Roberts RG, Sutikna T, Turney CSM, Westaway KE et al (2004) Archaeology and age of a new hominin from Flores in eastern Indonesia. Nature 431(7012):1087–1091

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy D (2020) Concepts of disease and health. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (summer 2020 edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/health-disease

  • Neander K (1995) Misrepresenting and malfunctioning. Philos Stud 79(2):109–141

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander K (2016) Mental illness, concept of. In: Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy, 1st edn. Routledge, London. https://doi.org/10.4324/9780415249126-V021-1

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Norenzayan A, Shariff AF, Gervais WM, Willard AK, McNamara RA, Slingerland E, Henrich J (2016) The cultural evolution of prosocial religions. Behav Brain Sci. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X14001356

  • Nunn CL, Samson DR (2018) Sleep in a comparative context: investigating how human sleep differs from sleep in other primates. Am J Phys Anthropol 166(3):601–612

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Obendorf PJ, Oxnard CE, Kefford BJ (2008) Are the small human-like fossils found on Flores human endemic cretins? Proc R Soc B Biol Sci 275(1640):1287–1296

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ogilvie MD, Curran BK, Trinkaus E (1989) Incidence and patterning of dental enamel hypoplasia among the Neandertals. Am J Phys Anthropol 79(1):25–41

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearson OM, Cordero RM, Busby AM (2006) How different were Neanderthals’ habitual activities? A comparative analysis with diverse groups of recent humans. In: Hublin J-J, Harvati K, Harrison T (eds) Neanderthals revisited: new approaches and perspectives. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 135–156

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Perreault C (2012) The pace of cultural evolution. PLoS One. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0045150

  • Ramsey G, De Block A (2017) Is cultural fitness hopelessly confused? Br J Philos Sci 68(2):305–328

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robson SL, Wood B (2008) Hominin life history: reconstruction and evolution. J Anat 212(4):394–425

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saborido C, Moreno A (2015) Biological pathology from an organizational perspective. Theor Med Bioeth 36:83–95. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-015-9318-8

  • Samson DR, Nunn CL (2015) Sleep intensity and the evolution of human cognition. Evol Anthropol 24(6):225–237

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schramme T, Edwards S (eds) (2017) Handbook of the philosophy of medicine. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon M, Simon JR, Kincaid H (eds) (2017) The Routledge companion to philosophy of medicine. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Spikins P, Needham A, Wright B, Dytham C, Gatta M, Hitchens G (2019) Living to fight another day: the ecological and evolutionary significance of Neanderthal healthcare. Quat Sci Rev 217:98–118

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2010) Minds: extended or scaffolded? Phenomenol Cogn Sci 9(4):465–481

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2012) The evolved apprentice: how evolution made humans unique. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2015) Optimizing engines: rational choice in the Neolithic? Philos Sci 82(3):402–423

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tucci S, Vohr SH, McCoy RC, Vernot B, Robinson MR, Barbieri C et al (2018) Evolutionary history and adaptation of a human pygmy population of Flores Island, Indonesia. Science 361(6401):511–516

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ungar P (2004) Dental topography and diets of Australopithecus afarensis and early Homo. J Hum Evol 46(5):605–622

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ungar P (2017) Evolution’s bite: a story of teeth, diet, and human origins. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield JC (1992) The concept of mental disorder: on the boundary between biological facts and social values. Am Psychol 47(3):373–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield JC (2007) The concept of mental disorder: diagnostic implications of the harmful dysfunction analysis. World Psychiatry 6(3):149–156

    Google Scholar 

  • Wrangham R (2010) Catching fire: how cooking made us human. Profile, London

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

My thanks to Paul Griffiths and to the editors of this collection for written comments on earlier drafts of this chapter. Thanks also for insights and feedback from Benjamin Jeffares, John Matthewson, Emily Parke, an audience at the New Zealand Association of Philosophy, and the team at Theory and Methods in Bioscience at the Department of Philosophy and Charles Perkins Centre, University of Sydney. This publication was written while a visiting fellow at the School of Philosophy and Centre for Philosophy of the Sciences at the Australian National University, and was made possible through the support of a grant from the John Templeton Foundation (Grant ID 60811). The views expressed in this publication are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of the John Templeton Foundation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Carl Brusse .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Brusse, C. (2021). The Archaeology and Philosophy of Health: Navigating the New Normal Problem. In: Killin, A., Allen-Hermanson, S. (eds) Explorations in Archaeology and Philosophy. Synthese Library, vol 433. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-61052-4_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics