Skip to main content

Moral Certainty

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Moral Change
  • 219 Accesses

Abstract

Nussbaum claims that ‘it is very difficult to think of traditional values as having any normative authority at all: tradition gives us only a conversation, a debate, and we have no choice but to evaluate the different positions within it’. This line of thinking is argued to be too rationalistic and is contrasted with the idea of ‘moral certainty’ as a prominent trait of human life, designating what is beyond being morally justified and unjustified, but as enabling practices of ethical investigation, debate and justification.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Pleasants (2008), Prichard (2012), Brice (2013), Brandhorst (2015), De Mesel (2015), Hermann (2015) and O’Hara (2018) are examples of philosophers who use Wittgenstein’s work to develop and discuss conceptions of ‘moral certainty’.

  2. 2.

    ‘Stand fast’ is a translation of Wittgenstein’s expression ‘fest stehen’, which denotes our relation to, for example, basic certainties.

  3. 3.

    See Pleasant’s discussion of what he sees as moral philosophers’ misguided attempts at explaining why ‘killing is wrong’ (Pleasants 2008: 257–265), and De Mesel’s discussion of Singer’s suggestion that infanticide can be morally warranted for analogous argumentations (De Mesel 2015).

  4. 4.

    I write that this is an image this quote could suggest, as I doubt Nussbaum, if asked, holds this view of human life, as her early writings suggest otherwise. But modern humans do occasionally get caught up in a rationalistic image of human life, where instincts, habits and traditions are considered suspect if not based on enlightened debate and rational choice or on scientific knowledge and proofs. Being captivated by this image can be problematic because it can have us ask for ‘more information’ and ‘proofs’ before being willing to act in cases where we ought to have acted (the opposite default position, captured in the phrase ‘shoot first and ask afterward’, is from a moral point of view of course equally problematic).

Bibliography

  • Archard, D. 2015. Children: Rights and Childhood. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandhorst, M. 2015. Correspondence to Reality in Ethics. Philosophical Investigations 38 (3): 227–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brice, R.G. 2013. Mistakes and Mental Disturbance: Pleasants, Wittgenstein, and Basic Moral Certainty. Philosophia 41: 477–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, A.S. 2003. Wittgensteins etik. Slagmark 38: 125–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Mesel, B. 2015. Moral Arguments and the Denial of Moral Certainties. In Realism - Relativism - Constructivism: Contributions of the 38nd International Wittgenstein Symposium, ed. C. Kanzian, J. Mitterer, and K. Neges, 68–70. Frankfurt am Main: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hermann, J. 2015. On Moral Certainty, Justification and Practice: A Wittgensteinian Perspective. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moyal-Sharrock, D. 2015. Wittgenstein on Forms of Life, Patterns of Life and Ways of Living. Nordic Wittgenstein Review 4 (Special Issue): 21–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M.C. 2001a. Introduction. In Women, Culture, and Development, ed. M.C. Nussbaum and J. Glover, 1–36. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Creating Capabilities: The Human Development Approach. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Hara, N. 2018. Moral Certainty and the Foundations of Morality. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pleasants, N. 2008. Wittgenstein, Ethics and Basic Moral Certainty. Inquiry 51 (3): 241–267.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prichard, D. 2012. Wittgenstein and the Groundlessness of Our Believing. Synthese 189: 255–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, M. 2009. Normative Naturalism. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 18 (3): 355–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. 2001. Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Philosophische Untersuchungen. Ed. P. Hacker and J. Schulte. West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. On Certainty. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Cecilie Eriksen .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Eriksen, C. (2020). Moral Certainty. In: Moral Change. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-61037-1_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics