Skip to main content

Between Particularism and Universalism: The Promise of Epistemic Contextualism in African Epistemology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Pathways to Alternative Epistemologies in Africa

Abstract

This chapter proposes a version of epistemic contextualism, called inferentialist contextualism, as a promising research program within African epistemology. My suggestion should be seen against the background of the earlier debate between the seemingly incompatible positions of universalism and particularism. Whilst universalism has been charged with not allowing for diversity, of forcing African culture into the Procrustean bed of Western thought, particularism seems to block cross-cultural dialogue. A compromise is therefore called for. I argue that inferentialist contextualism can fill this need. One promising feature is that whilst traditional epistemology always places the burden of justification on the subject of knowledge, inferentialist contextualism distinguishes between three different contexts: except for the traditional one, a second where the burden of proof is shared by both the subject and any fellow who might challenge the belief and a third context where the burden lies solely on the inquiring fellow. The notion of default entitlement depicts beliefs falling within this third context and will be elaborated in some detail here. I argue that inferential contextualism permits greater contextual variety than traditional epistemology without collapsing into relativism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Wiredu (1996, 47). See also Bello (2004), Falola (2003) and Hallen (2009) for further references to traditionalism.

  2. 2.

    Indeed it is characteristic of those who pose as antiuniversalists to use the term universalism as if it meant pseudouniversalism, and the fact is that their complaint is not with universalism at all. What they truly object to–and who would not?–is Eurocentric hegemony posing as universalism. (Appiah 1992, 58, italics in original)

  3. 3.

    Bello (2004, 264). See also Wiredu (1996, 26–7). In another good passage Wiredu writes

    [I]ronically, anti-relativism is liable, through a certain adulteration of logic with psychology, to be transformed into some form of authoritarian absolutism, which turns off many intellectuals who have their hearts in the right place. (ibid., 69)

    Note that I do not mean to suggest that the impossibility of intercultural exchange was an intended consequence of particularist traditionalism.

  4. 4.

    Decolonalization is one important aspect of Wiredu’s program within African philosophy. The other aspect consists in “domestication”. This program is thus another example of steering such a middle course between the poles of universalism and particularism (Wiredu 1996). See also Bello (2004, 267) and Falola (2003, 12): “When Africans reject their categorization of inferiority, a cultural project of self-affirmation is implied”. Note here Wiredu’s dictum “language can only incline, not necessitate” Wirdeu (1980, 35) and Wiredu (1996, 101 and 118); also quoted by Bello (2004, 267).

    It is also a striking feature of the traditionalist view how it appears to agree with the characterization of African cognitive constitution by the colonizing Western powers as “precritical, prereflective, protorational, prescientific, emotive, expressive, poetic and so forth” Hallen (2009, 27–8), but then attempts to replace the negative evaluation of these characteristics with a positive one. As Hallen remarks “it more or less confirmed and reinforced the reason/emotion dichotomy between the West and Africa” (Hallen 2004, 296).

  5. 5.

    See Ogungbure (2012) and Òkè (1995, 206).

  6. 6.

    Despite being a former student of Richard Rorty, Williams’ version of contextualism crucially differs from Rorty’s version in several aspects to Williams’ credit. Incidentally, the previous attempts to apply contextualism within African epistemology, which I know of, spring from Rorty. Whilst Udefi (2009) is in favor, Hallen (2006) is highly critical of Rorty’s view as applied to the African context.

  7. 7.

    Humans are not the only animals that hold beliefs for that matter – see Kornblith (2012). Williams’ view on the matter is actually less clear, see Williams (2004).

  8. 8.

    See Janvid (2017). The dialectic pertaining to the three different kinds of contexts presented below in the main text spells out what the defeasible character of justification more precisely amounts to in those different contexts.

  9. 9.

    See also, for instance, (Williams 2001) especially Ch. 13 and 14. The qualifier “inferential” is often added to distinguish his version from more common “attributor” versions of contextualism. See, for instance, Pritchard (2016). Although both versions were launched to solve the two problems mentioned in section “Introduction”, their contextualist solutions differ. In fact, Pritchard (2016) criticizes inferentialist contextualism for being too relativist.

  10. 10.

    Williams employs different terms for depicting these illegitimate challenges in different works. I have elaborated on the symmetry requirement in Janvid (2013, 2017).

  11. 11.

    Williams (2001, 160), as part of what Williams calls the methodological necessities that constrain justification and epistemic dialectic.

  12. 12.

    Hallen and Sodipo (1997).

  13. 13.

    In fact, I give a negative verdict on the contextualist response to skepticism in Janvid (2006).

  14. 14.

    Hallen gives a Yoruba example of such “clear-cut situations” and the lack of examination and further discourse in Hallen (2000, 25).

  15. 15.

    This claim is subject to several provisos, one of them being that the stakes are not high in the particular everyday context. Contextualists typically take rising stakes (an example of what Williams calls economic factors in Williams 2001, 161) to bring about a shift to higher epistemic standards. Simply put, the more that is at stake in a particular context the higher the standards are for knowledge: the more important it is for me that the nearest bank office is open, the stronger justification I need to secure knowledge of its opening hours. According to contextualism such practical factors have an epistemic impact. See also note no. 17 below.

  16. 16.

    Wiredu (1980, 1996). Note that prolonged discussions under philosophy seminars will also eventually reveal default entitled beliefs, but they will not be found immediately on the surface of the exchange as in everyday contexts.

  17. 17.

    To allow for shifts in standards unite inferential and attributor contextualism. One reason why it would be very interesting to know more in detail what questions were asked to the participating onisègùn (Yoruba masters of medicine, see Hallen and Sodipo 1997, 10–11; Hallen 2000, 176) during their fieldwork is whether it was the questions that gave rise to the shift to higher standards. This feature is crucial for assessing the applicability of contextualism to Yoruba epistemic practices. I hope to address this issue in future work. When their fieldwork was conducted it was classified as ordinary language philosophy, but today it would be labeled experimental philosophy.

  18. 18.

    Interestingly, Wiredu argues that his own language Akan is fallibilist in Wiredu (1996, 139–40).

    It should be noted that one praiseworthy aim driving Hallen and Sodipo in their book is to defy the image of African communities in general, and Yoruba in particular, as an uncritical and prereflective traditional culture. My own remarks are of course not meant to restore that demeaning image of the epistemic practice of African communities like the Yoruba.

  19. 19.

    Locke is a famous example in Locke (1975).

  20. 20.

    Note that sufficiency holds with certain provisos, more precisely to overriding challenges. As a response to an undermining challenge, precisely questioning your ability to form reliable firsthand experience, providing such justification would of course not be sufficient. Such a response would instead be obviously question-begging. See Janvid (2013, 2017).

  21. 21.

    See Òkè (1995, 214). It should also be noted that inferentialist contextualism is a pronounced internalist position, i.e. the subject must have an internal access to her justification in order to be so. See, for instance, Williams (2001). Ogungbure calls for this neglected aspect in African epistemology Ogungbure (2013). Intrapersonal access often goes hand in hand with interpersonal access.

  22. 22.

    I am grateful to Adebayo Ogungbure, participants at The Toyin@65 conference “African Knowledges and Alternative Futures” at Ibadan in January 2018 and an anonymous referee for helpful comments on earlier versions of this chapter.

References

  • Appiah, K.A. 1992. In My Father’s House. Africa in the Philosophy of Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bello, A.G.A. 2004. Some Methodological Controversies in African Philosophy. In A Companion to African Philosophy, ed. K. Wiredu, 263–272. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Falola, Toyin. 2003. The Power of African Cultures. Rochester: University of Rochester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hallen, Barry. 2000. The Good, the Bad and the Beautiful. Discourse About Vales in Yoruba Culture. Bloomington/Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Yoruba Moral Epistemology. In A Companion to African Philosophy, ed. K. Wiredu, 296–303. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006. African Philosophy. The Analytic Approach. Trenton: Africa World Press, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. A Short History of African Philosophy. 2nd ed. Bloomington/Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hallen, Barry, and Olubi Sodipo. 1997. Knowledge, Belief and Witchcraft. Analytic Experiments in African Philosophy. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janvid, Mikael. 2006. Contextualism and the Structure of Skeptical Arguments. Dialectica 60: 63–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. The Challenges of Traveling Without Itinerary. The Overriding Case. Grazer Philosophische Studien 87: 59–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Defeater Goes External. Philosophia 45: 701–715.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. 2012. On Reflection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1975. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ogungbure, Adebayo. 2012. The Problem of Justification in African Epistemology: A Critical Study. Saarbrücken: Lap Lambert Academic Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Two Notions of Justification in African Epistemology. Journal on African Philosophy 8: 31–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Òkè, Moses. 1995. Towards an African (Yoruba) Perspective on Empirical Knowledge: A Critique of Hallen and Sodipo. International Philosophical Quarterly XXXV: 205–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. 2016. Epistemic Angst. Radical Skepticism and the Groundlessness of Our Believing. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Udefi, Amaechi. 2009. Rorty’s Neopragmatism and the Imperative of the Discourse of African Epistemology. Human Affairs 79: 78–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, M. 2001. Problems of Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Is Knowledge a Natural Phenomenon? In The Externalist Challenge, ed. R. Schantz, 193–210. Berlin/New York: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Why (Wittgensteinian) Contextualism Is Not Relativism. Episteme 4: 93–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiredu, Kwasi. 1980. Philosophy and an African Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Cultural Universals and Particulars: An African Perspective. Bloomington/Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Janvid, M. (2021). Between Particularism and Universalism: The Promise of Epistemic Contextualism in African Epistemology. In: Afolayan, A., Yacob-Haliso, O., Oloruntoba, S.O. (eds) Pathways to Alternative Epistemologies in Africa. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-60652-7_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics