Skip to main content

On Mathematical Language: Characteristics, Semiosis and Indispensability

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Language and Scientific Research
  • 216 Accesses

Abstract

Mathematicians and others often discuss mathematics as a universal language, and say that mathematics holds a special status among sciences. In particular, it is the language of science. In some way, it is the basis of the physical world, but globally it is beyond any other science, and it is not a mere servant of sciences. Apparently, mathematical language is simple, with a little grammar and a limited vocabulary, but very different from others. Unlike natural languages, it is a rigorously defined and unambiguous one. This characteristic constitutes its greatest advantage: its complete lack of ambiguity. Although it is limited in the range of things that can express, it can be adapted to the needs of any application, what constitutes a real challenge in terms of effectiveness. A language is a medium for expressing verbally or visually facts, opinions, thoughts, feelings, desires, commands, etc. Each language employs abstract symbols (verbal or visual) to represent things. Mathematics exhibits these characteristics as a language, albeit with different emphasis and importance. The range of topics communicated in natural languages and those communicated in mathematical language differ in significant ways. Feelings and emotions are not expressed in mathematical terms, and imprecisely defined terms are not allowed in mathematical language. The aim of this contribution will be to analyze some of the characteristics of mathematical language, the role of semiotic modes in reproducing the effectiveness of mathematics in science, and the relation of the problem of indispensability to the one of the reasonable effectiveness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    This image comes from Descartes (1682) p. 226. The author is grateful to the Biblioteca Històrica (Historical Library), Universitat de València, for the right to reproduce it.

  2. 2.

    This image comes from Descartes (1682) p. 228. The author is grateful to the Biblioteca Històrica (Historical Library), Universitat de València, for the right to reproduce it.

References

  • Baber, R. L. (2011). The language of mathematics. Utilizing math in practice. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bateman, J. (2014). Text and image. A critical introduction to the visual/verbal divide. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Berger, J. (1972). Ways of seeing. London: BBC and Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burton, L., & Morgan, C. (2000). Mathematicians writing. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 31(4), 429–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cifoletti, G. (2006). Mathematics and rhetoric. Introduction. Early Science and Medicine, 11, 369–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2009). Mathematics and the world. In A. D. Irvine (Ed.), Philosophy of mathematics (pp. 651–702). Oxford: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, P. J. (1974). Visual geometry, computer graphics and theorems of perceived type. In J. P. LaSalle (Ed.), The influence of computing on mathematical research and education (pp. 113–127). Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1682). Renati Descartes epistolae: partim ab auctore latino sermone conscriptae, partim ex Gallico translatae: in quibus Omnis generis quaestiones philosophiae tractantur...: pars prima. Amstelodami: Ex typographia Blauiana: sumptibus societatis, Universitat de València, Biblioteca Històrica.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devlin, K. (1998). The language of mathematics. Making the invisible visible. New York: W. H. Freeman and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1989). Realism, mathematics and modality. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1953). The foundations of arithmetic (2nd revised ed., J. L. Austin, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grattan-Guinness, I. (2008). Solving Wigner’s mystery: The reasonable (though perhaps limited) effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. The Mathematical Intelligencer, 30(3), 7–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halliday, M. A. K. (2004). The collected works of M. A. K. Halliday. Volume 5: The Language of Science (J. J. Webster, Ed.). London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jewitt, C. (Ed.). (2009). The Routledge handbook of multimodal analysis (2nd ed.). London: Routledge, 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1786). The metaphysical foundations of natural science (M. Friedman, Trans. & Ed.). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvasz, L. (2008). Patterns of change. Linguistic innovations in the development of classical mathematics. Basel: Birkhäuser.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, C. (2014). Mathematical language. In S. Lerman (Ed.), Encyclopedia of mathematics education (pp. 388–391). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Halloran, K. L. (2005). Mathematical discourse. Language, symbolism and visual images. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Halloran, K. L. (2009). Historical changes in the semiotic landscape: From calculation to computation. In C. Jewitt (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of multimodal analysis (pp. 98–113). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Halloran, K. L. (2015). Mathematics as multimodal semiosis. In E. Davis & P. J. Davis (Eds.), Mathematics, substance and surmise views on the meaning and ontology of mathematics (pp. 287–303). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Panza, M., & Sereni, A. (2015). On the indispensable premises of the indispensability argument. In G. Lolli, M. Panza, & G. Venturi (Eds.), From logic to practice. Italian studies in the philosophy of mathematics (pp. 241–276). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pólya, G. (1954). Mathematics and plausible reasoning (2nd ed.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1968.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pólya, G. (1963). Mathematical methods in science. Washington, DC: The Mathematical Association of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1979). Mathematics matter and method: Philosophical papers vol. I (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1980). From a logical point of view (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1981). Theories and things. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarukkai, S. (2005). Revisiting the “unreasonable effectiveness” of mathematics. Current Science, 88(3), 415–422.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sfard, A. (2008). Thinking as communicating. Human development, the growth of discourses, and mathematizing. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, M. (1998). The applicability of mathematics as a philosophical problem. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, M. (2005). Mathematics — Application and applicability. In S. Shapiro (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mathematics and logic (pp. 625–650). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, S. (1993). Dreams of a final theory. New York: Vintage.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. (1949). Philosophy of mathematics and natural science (Revised and augmented English edition based on a O. Helmer, Trans.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. P. (1960). The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics, 13(1), 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author is grateful to the Spanish Ministry of Science and Innovation for supporting this work (FFI2014-53164 and PGC2018-095941-B-I009).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jesus Alcolea .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Alcolea, J. (2021). On Mathematical Language: Characteristics, Semiosis and Indispensability. In: Gonzalez, W.J. (eds) Language and Scientific Research. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-60537-7_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics