Skip to main content

Light Verbs and the Syntactic Configurations of se

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Unraveling the complexity of SE

Part of the book series: Studies in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory ((SNLT,volume 99))

Abstract

This paper offers a novel analysis of the Spanish light verbs poner(se) ‘to become’ and quedar(se) ‘to become/stay’ in combination with adjectives. These verbs have the peculiarity that they may appear with or without se in these constructions, with clear effects on argument structure and thematic and aspectual interpretation. I propose a unified formal analysis that takes event complexity and argument coindexing as the common denominator of se in these complex predicates. I further observe that these effects with se are not exclusive to these light verbs, but can also be observed in certain types of lexical verbs, strongly suggesting that both lexical and light verbs lexicalize the same eventive spine.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    There are two other light verbs denoting change in Spanish, volver(se) and hacer(se) ‘to become’. The received wisdom is that these two verbs take Individual-level adjectives, whereas poner(se) and quedar(se) take Stage-level adjectives. See Demonte and Masullo (1999) and Morimoto and Pavón-Lucero (2007) for further discussion of these four verbs.

  2. 2.

    The term light verb was originally coined by Jespersen (1965). In Jespersen’s view, which I adopt here, a lexical verb is a conceptually rich verb that has meaning in isolation and belongs to the open class type of lexical items. Light verbs, on the other hand, belong to the closed (i.e. grammatical) class of lexical items and they are parasitic on a lexical predicate to form a syntactically and semantically coherent (complex) predicate.

  3. 3.

    In this respect, my work takes the stance that the so-called unaccusative se signals both reflexivity and aspectual complexity. As far as the reflexivity analysis is concerned—technical differences aside—I side with Chierchia (2004) and Koontz-Garboden (2009). In terms of the aspectual complexity of se, the reader is referred to Vivanco (this volume) and the overview therein.

  4. 4.

    For reasons of space, I will restrict my study of these light verbs to adjectival predicates. However, poner(se) and quedar(se) can also appear with other non-verbal predicates, such as PPs. Moreover, while many adjectives can take poner(se) and quedar(se) with equal ease, other adjectives can only combine with either one or the other (e.g. gordo ‘fat’ can only appear with poner(se) and débil ‘weak’ can only take quedar(se)). Focusing on these restrictions in depth goes beyond the scope of this work, but see Bybee and Eddington (2006) and Morimoto and Pavón-Lucero (2007) for discussion.

  5. 5.

    As Morimoto and Pavón-Lucero (2007) observe, there is also a counter-expectational presupposition involved with quedar(se). As such, it is odd to say, without further context, Se quedó despierto toda la mañana ‘He stayed awake all morning’, since the expectation is that one is typically awake in the morning.

  6. 6.

    The reader may wonder why a change-of-state reading is precluded in (3c). It is due to the selectional restrictions of change-of-state quedar(se) (see also ft. 4), which cannot take the adjective despierto.

  7. 7.

    For similar proposals, see Mendikoetxea (2000) and Cuervo (2003, 2014); for semantic accounts along the same lines, the reader is referred to Chierchia (2004) and Koontz-Garboden (2009).

  8. 8.

    An anonymous reviewer asks how the spell-out of se is restricted, given that it is not the case that all coindexed arguments trigger se. The reviewer points out the case of coindexed direct and indirect arguments (see (i), from Otero 1999:1462).

    A plausible solution would be to stipulate that ApplP cannot host reflexive morphology, under the assumption that the two internal arguments of ditransitive verbs are introduced by a low ApplP complement of V (Pylkkänen 2002). I leave aside this issue for future work.

  9. 9.

    The adverb casi ‘almost’ does not always deliver a clear ambiguity with these light verbs, as an anonymous reviewer rightly notes. This happens mostly when they select adjectives denoting psychological states. What is more, this adverb sounds weird with psychological predicates to begin with (e.g. (2)). A likely explanation is that it is hard to see how a psychological (change-of-)state would be compatible with any of the possible readings delivered by casi, i.e. how can one assess the degree to which a person can be said to be close to be nervous (i.e. with casi scoping below the process event and above the result state)? Or how can one assess whether the whole event of a person being or becoming nervous could have almost begun (i.e. with casi scoping over the whole event)?

  10. 10.

    It seems that the link between agentivity and se is indeed restricted to the stative version of quedarse. While stative quedarse is clearly agentive (e.g. (iiia), and see also (5) and (6)), change-of-state quedarse does not seem to be (e.g. (iiib)). This is not surprising, given that change-of-state quedarse does not include initP in its decomposition.

  11. 11.

    A reviewer points out that it is possible to have a reflexive stative verb (i.e. with se) and a participial complement, as in (iv) (example from the reviewer).

    While I agree this would be a potential counterexample for my theory, I note that the structure in (41b) is rather exceptional: there are very few inherently reflexive verbs that can take a passive participal complement whose internal argument is coindexed with the subject of such verb. Only sentirse ‘feel’ and considerarse ‘consider oneself’ come to mind. I leave aside a deeper study of the role of se in these specific constructions for future work.

References

  • Alexiadou, Artemis, Berit Gehrke, and Florian Schäfer. 2014. The argument structure of adjectival participles revisited. Lingua 149: 118–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexiadou, Artemis, Elena Anagnostopoulou, and Florian Schäfer. 2015. External Arguments in Transitivity Alternations: A Layering Approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arad, Maya. 1998. VP Structure and the Syntax–Lexicon Interface. PhD dissertation, University College London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arad, Maya. 2002. Universal features and language-particular morphemes. In Theoretical Approaches to Universals, ed. Artemis Alexiadou, 15–39. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Arche, Maria Jesus. 2006. Individuals in Time. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, Mark C. 2003. Lexical Categories: Verbs, Nouns and Adjectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, Mark, Kyle Johnson, and Ian Roberts. 1989. Passive arguments raised. Linguistic Inquiry 20(2): 219–251.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bybee, Joan, and David Eddington. 2006. A usage-based approach to Spanish verbs of ‘becoming’. Language 82(2): 323–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camacho, Jose. 2012. Ser and estar: The individual/stage level distinction and aspectual predication. In The Handbook of Hispanic Linguistics, eds. Jose Ignacio Hualde, Antxon Olarrea, and Erin O’Rourke, 453–476. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, Gennaro. 2004. A semantics for unaccusatives and its syntactic consequences. In The Unaccusativity Puzzle: Explorations of the Syntax-Lexicon Interface, eds. Artemis Alexiadou, Elena Anagnostopoulou, and Martin Everaert, 22–59. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cuervo, Maria Cristina. 2003. Datives at Large. PhD dissertation, Massachussets Institute of Technology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cuervo, Maria Cristina. 2014. Alternating unaccusatives and the distribution of roots. Lingua 141: 48–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demonte, Violeta, and Pascual Masullo. 1999. La predicacion: Los complementos predicativos. In Gramatica descriptiva de la lengua española, eds. Ignacio Bosque, and Violeta Demonte, 2461–2523. Madrid: Espasa Calpe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Embick, David. 2004. On the structure of resultative participles in English. Linguistic Inquiry 35(3): 355–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fábregas, Antonio, and Rafael Marín. 2015. Deriving individual-level and stage-level psych verbs in Spanish. The Linguistic Review 32(2): 227–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fernández-Soriano, Olga, and Amaya Mendikoetxea. 2011. Non-selected dative subjects in anticausative constructions. Archivio Glottologico Italiano XCVI: 87–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Folli, Raffaella, and Heidi Harley. 2005. Flavors of v: Consuming results in Italian and English. In Aspectual Inquiries, eds. Roumyana Slabakova, and Paula Kempchinsky, 95–120. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hale, Kenneth L., and Samuel J. Keyser. 2002. Prolegomenon to a Theory of Argument Structure. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jespersen, Otto. 1965. A Modern English Grammar on Historical Principles, Part VI, Morphology. London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koontz-Garboden, Andrew. 2009. Anticausativization. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 27(1): 77–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, Angelika. 2000. Building statives. In Proceedings of the 26th Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society, eds. Lisa J. Conathan, Jeff Good, Darya Kavitskaya, Alyssa B. Wulf, and Alan C. L. Yu, 385–399. Berkeley: Berkeley Linguistics Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luján, Marta. 1981. The Spanish copulas as aspectual indicators. Lingua 54: 165–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marín, Rafael. 2000. El componente aspectual de la predicacion. PhD dissertation, Universidad Autonoma de Barcelona.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marín, Rafael, and Louise McNally. 2011. Inchoativity, change of state and telicity: Evidence from Spanish reflexive psychological verbs. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 29(2): 467–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marín, Rafael, and Cristina Sanchez-Marco. 2012. Verbos y nombres psicologicos: juntos y revueltos. Borealis: An International Journal of Hispanic Linguistics 2: 91–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mendikoetxea, Amaya. 2000. Relaciones de interficie: Los verbos de cambio de estado. Cuadernos de Linguistica del IUOG 7: 125–144.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morimoto, Yuko, and María Victoria Pavón-Lucero. 2007. Los verbos pseudo-copulativos del español. Madrid: Arco Libros.

    Google Scholar 

  • Otero, Carlos P. 1999. Pronombres reflexivos y recíprocos. In Gramática descriptiva de la lengua española, eds. Ignacio Bosque, and Violeta Demonte, 1429–1517. Madrid: Espasa-Calpe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pesetsky, David. 1995. Zero Syntax: Experiencers and Cascades. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porroche, Margarita. 1990. Aspectos de la atribucion en español. Zaragoza: Portico.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylkkänen, Liina. 2000. On Stativity and Causation. In Events as Grammatical Objects: The Converging Perspectives of Lexical Semantics and Syntax, eds. Carol Tenny, and James Pustejovsky. Standford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylkkänen, Liina. 2002. Introducing Arguments. PhD dissertation, Massachussets Institute of Technology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramchand, Gillian C. 2008. Verb Meaning and the Lexicon: A First Phase Syntax. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rothmayr, Antonia. 2009. The Structure of Stative Verbs. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schäfer, Florian. 2008. The Syntax of (Anti-)causatives. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sichel, Ivy. 2010. Event structure constraints in nominalization. In The Syntax of Nominalizations Across Languages and Frameworks, eds. Artemis Alexiadou, and Monika Rathert, 159–197. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Vivanco, Margot. 2020. Spanish anticausative se and its relation to scales. In Unraveling the Complexity of SE. Cham: Springer International Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to the audiences of the Workshop on Romance se-si, where a previous version of this work was presented, for their constructive feedback. I also thank two anonymous reviewers and María Luisa Zubizarreta for the extensive discussions I had with her on this topic. Last but not least, thank you to Grant Armstrong and Jon MacDonald for organizing the workshop and for the relentless effort they have put in making this volume a reality. Errors are my own.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alfredo García-Pardo .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

García-Pardo, A. (2021). Light Verbs and the Syntactic Configurations of se. In: Armstrong, G., MacDonald, J.E. (eds) Unraveling the complexity of SE. Studies in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, vol 99. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-57004-0_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics