Skip to main content

Life and Time: Bergson and the Life Sciences

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Time, Life & Memory

Part of the book series: Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy ((LOET,volume 38))

  • 288 Accesses

Abstract

In Creative Evolution (1911 [1907]) Henri Bergson discusses the distinction between the living, biotic, and the non-living, abiotic world. The study touched directly upon several of the key developments of his age in biology. Notably evolution theory played a crucial role in his philosophy. In the historical context of the turn of the century, the debate between religious readings of the origin of life and evolution theory had far from quieted down. Evolution theory continued to be seen as controversial due to its negation of the story of the origin of species as it was laid down in Genesis. Biological vitalism appeared to safeguarded the notion of the sanctity of life. Bergson’s vitalism is however of a different nature, preluding views that emerged only decades later, in complex systems theory. This chapter discusses the relevance of Bergson's ideas for the life sciences.

Life does not proceed by the association and addition of elements, but by dissociation and division. We must get beyond both points of view, both mechanism and finalism being, at bottom, only standpoints to which the human mind has been led by considering the work of man.

- Henri Bergson, Creative Evolution (1911 [1907])

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In discussions with an expert on thermodynamics, he defined a solution to this: the processes expressed in living beings were triggered by and are kept in motion through the energy of the sun. In this regard, the earth is not a closed system. As such, life on earth is merely a side-phenomenon of the heat generated by the sun. The total net calculus of entropy still carries along an increase in the entropy in the universe.

  2. 2.

    The physicist Richard Feynman wrote down the dictum with chalk on blackboard just before his death. Although he meant it to refer to the (re)creation of the argumentative steps towards a theoretical result, it has often been used to refer to the literal recreation of something in nature, to be able to understand it.

  3. 3.

    Feynman is actually quite a bit older. Its historical roots can be traced to statements by Giambattisto Vico and Immanuel Kant (van den Belt 2009) in their focus on mathematical construction (Broeks and Zwart 2021).

  4. 4.

    Personal communication with Prof. Vitor Martins Martins dos Santos (2017). Wageningen University and Research.

  5. 5.

    In early 1943, by invitation of the Dublin Institute for Advanced Studies at Trinity College, Schrödinger gave a view on biology in a series of lectures he later published under the title “What Is Life?: The Physical Aspect of the Living Cell”. These were bundled in a small book with an enormous impact. It indirectly inspired the definition of the double helix (Schrödinger 1944).

  6. 6.

    Bergson already criticised evolution theorists of his time for taking this position since to his mind they did not fundamentally rethink time in evolution theory, and thus still subsumed evolution under a Newtonian mechanistic principle (Bergson, Creative Evolution).

  7. 7.

    The aim here is not to dispense with symbols, but rather to explain how the (symbolic) conventions within given fields of knowledge may lead to overstretched conclusions, and thus create openings for further theory and research.

  8. 8.

    Creationism departs from the view that all species were, at one point in time, at the beginning of the history of the cosmos, created, and remained unchanged in the ensuing centuries.

  9. 9.

    At the time also with ‘specimens’ that remain a horrific witness to humanity’s talent for cruelty in the name of science and truth.

  10. 10.

    He objected to Immanuel Kant’s epistemological conception of time (Critic of Pure Reason (Kritik der reinen Vernunft (1781/1787)) since Kant, as mentioned previously, seemed to interpret time as a spatial dimension. There is reason to draw this assertion into question, since for Kant, time is very much constituted by our ability to recognize a thing as the same thing over time. This is amongst others captured in Kant’s ‘modality of recognition’: our ability to recognize something as something relates time to experiential memory rather than to space: Kant thus reconstructs time as an aspect of memory, not of space, a strategy quite similar to Bergson’s in ‘Matter and Memory’.

  11. 11.

    Something that is illustrated by the average, and often parodied, picture of the evolution of homo sapiens, from left to right, as a sequenced linear development from crawling dark-haired apes to increasingly tall, evermore upright (and, whilst disliking certain forms of overenthusiastic political correctness: indeed often also more blonde haired and lighter skinned) bipedal specimens.

  12. 12.

    For an example, please see the use of the concept of a safe ‘chassis’, a standardised GM organism that has multiple safeguards built into its DNA.

  13. 13.

    And admittedly, by adhering to a position that, although articulated by a contemporary of Bergson, was not picked up by him in spite of its crucial importance to his position.

  14. 14.

    Since much of Bergson’s personal archive was destroyed at his own request, we cannot know whether he might have reflected upon the potential of Metchnikoff’s theories more elaborately.

Literature

  • Bensaude-Vincent, B. (2009). Biomimetic chemistry and synthetic biology: A two-way traffic across the Borders. International Journal for Philosophy of Chemistry, 15(1), 31–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1912 [1903]). An introduction to metaphysics (trans; Hulme, T.E.). Hackett Publishing Company 1999. Also included in: Bergson, H. (2007 (1923)). The creative mind: An introduction to metaphysics 1923. Dover Publications: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1911 [1907]). Creative evolution. New York: Henry Holt and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, D. (1980). Wholeness and the implicate order. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brillouin, L. ([1956, 1962] 2004). Science and information theory. Mineola, NY: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broeks, D., & Zwart, H. (2021, forthcoming). Understanding life by engineering it: An epistemological assessment of the Feynman-dictum in synthetic biology. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cath, A. G. (2018). Solace in complexity: A fundamental empirical thought experiment. Vianen: Uitgeverij ProefschriftMaken.

    Google Scholar 

  • Church, G., & Regis E. (2012). Regenesis. How synthetic biology will reinvent nature and ourselves. Philadelphia: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, K. B. (2010). Origins of learned reciprocity in solitary ciliates searching grouped courting assurances at quantum efficiencies. Biosystems, 99, 27–41. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biosystems.2009.08.005.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F. H., & Orgel, L. E. (1973). Directed panspermia. Icarus, 19(3), 341–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crow, J. F. (1992). Erwin Schrödinger and the hornless cattle problem. Genetics, 130, 237–239.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, F. C. (1951). Ecology and urban areal research. Scientific Monthly, 73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gharud, R., Simpson, B., Langley, A., & Tsoukas, H. (2015). The emergence of novelty in organisations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1995). What is life? The next fifty years: Speculations on the future of biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1781). Kritik der reinen Vernunft (A). Riga: Hartknoch.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miquel, P. (2007). Bergson and Darwin: From an Immanentist to an Emergentist approach to evolution. SubStance, 36(3), 42–56. Issue 114: Henri Bergson’s creative evolution 100 years later (2007). Published by: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morin, E. (1990). Introduction a la pensee complexe. Paris: ESF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mutsaers, I. (2016). Immunological discourse in political philosophy: Immunisation and its discontents. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nature. (2007). Nature editorial: Meanings of life: Synthetic biology provides a welcome antidote to chronic vitalism. Nature, 447, 1031–1032.

    Google Scholar 

  • Onffray de Lamettrie, J. (2003 [1748]). Machine man and other writings (ed: Thomson, A.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger, E. (1944). What is life – The physical aspect of the living cell. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, H. (1854). Essays: Scientific, political and speculative (Vol. 2). London: Williams and Norgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spier, R. E. (2003). History of animal cell technology. In R. E. Spier (Ed.), Encyclopedia of cell technology (Vol. 2, pp. 853–872). New York: Wiley.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stambler I. (2014). A history of life-extensionism in the twentieth century. Longevity History, Rishon Lezion. http://www.longevityhistory.com. Last accessed: 10-07-2019.

  • van den Belt, H. (2009). Playing god in Frankenstein’s footsteps: Synthetic biology and the meaning of life. NanoEthics, 3(3), 257–268. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11569-009-0079-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Venter, C. (2013). Life at the speed of light: From the double Helix to the Dawn of digital life. New York: Viking Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vikhanski, L. (2016). Immunity: How Elie Metchnikoff changed the course of modern medicine. Chicago: Chicago Review Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Bertalanffy, L. (1934). Untersuchungen über die Gesetzlichkeit des Wachstums I: Allgemeine Grundlagen der Theorie; mathematische und physiologische Gesetzlichkeiten des Wachstums bei Wassertieren. Arch. Entwicklungsmech, 131, 613–652.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Westerhoff, H. V., Brooks, A. N., Simeonidis, E., García-Contreras, R., He, F., Boogerd, F. C., et al. (2014). Macromolecular networks and intelligence in microorganisms. Frontiers in Microbiology, 5(379).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wickramasinghe, C. (2011). Bacterial morphologies supporting cometary panspermia: A reappraisal. International Journal of Astrobiology, 10(1), 25–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zwart, H. (2010). De waarheid op de wand: psychoanalyse van het weten. Nijmegen: Vantilt. ISBN 9789460040481.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zwart, H. (2012). On decoding and rewriting genomes: A psychoanalytical reading of a scientific revolution. Medicine, Healthcare and Philosophy: A European Journal, 15(3), 337–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zwart, H. (2018). In the beginning was the genome: Genomics and the bi-textuality of human existence. The New Bioethics: A Multidisciplinary Journal of Biotechnology and the Body. https://doi.org/10.1080/20502877.2018.1438776.

  • Zwart, H. (2019). What is mimicked by biomimicry? Synthetic cells as exemplifications of the three-fold biomimicry paradox. Environmental Values, 27(special issue).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Landeweerd, L. (2021). Life and Time: Bergson and the Life Sciences. In: Time, Life & Memory. Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy, vol 38. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-56853-5_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics