Skip to main content

Remainders of the Self: Consciousness as a Problem for Neuroethics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Theories of the Self and Autonomy in Medical Ethics

Part of the book series: The International Library of Bioethics ((ILB,volume 83))

  • 524 Accesses

Abstract

Neuroscience has made great progress in recent years in detecting mental processes using electrophysiological and imaging techniques. One of the major breakthroughs in this regard has been the detection of residual consciousness in persons diagnosed with a vegetative state. However, this very success gives rise to a number of theoretically as well as ethically crucial follow-up questions. What neuroimaging can provide are highly artificial, mathematically processed images and not direct information about the patient’s mind. Therefore, it is far from clear whether and to what degree behaviourally unresponsive patients are indeed conscious. This is all the more so since we are confronted with a double mediation: one between the person’s mind and the image of the brain and the second between the image and something that we interpret as a meaningful answer of the patient to a question of the physician. For the patient in question it is of vital importance that his ability for consciousness is neither over- nor underrated since both can lead to significant suffering. Above that, residual consciousness or remainders of the person’s self—even if reduced and fragmented—have to be taken into account for treatment or end of life decisions. Unfortunately, there is no consensus in neuroscience about what “consciousness” and “being conscious” really means. To be sure, there is a long tradition regarding notions like these in philosophy. However, philosophical insight does not find its way into neuroscience easily. Against this background, the paper aims at connecting philosophical and neuroscientific understandings of consciousness in order to better understand what may go on inside an otherwise unresponsive patient. The notion of a “self” that might be preserved even if the person in question is not fully conscious or only has some basic form of consciousness will serve as a working concept for this problem. Neuroethics has to solve the conceptual problem of consciousness in order to be able to solve the clinical problem of consciousness and with it the ethical problem of autonomy and the self.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    It is obvious that this understanding of consciousness is too simplistic. However, that is not the fault of James, whose account is richer, but the fault of those present authors who leave it at that.

  2. 2.

    This is impressively shown by Płonka (2015).

  3. 3.

    If this seems silly to you, it would not be much better the other way around: It is difficult—to say the least—searching for something in the brain that you do not know. Searching for a wolf in the woods presupposes to know what a wolf is.

  4. 4.

    Coma is usually a transient state from which patients either decline to brain death or improve to at least a vegetative state.

  5. 5.

    Think of a multi-storey building: The basement represents coma, the first floor is the vegetative state, and so on up to the penthouse where the philosopher’s second order self-consciousness resides. The level-based account has recently been challenged, see below.

  6. 6.

    LIS does not belong to the DOC-family but it is nevertheless of utmost importance in the DOC-Context since a patient may be misdiagnosed with VS even though she is completely conscious (an impressive example give Vanhaudenhuyse et al. 2018).

  7. 7.

    Again, this must not be confused with LIS, where the patient is perfectly clear but cannot communicate.

  8. 8.

    I can only give some hints to research literature and methods here; see Cavaliere et al. (2016) for a concise overview.

  9. 9.

    It goes without saying, that things actually are much more complicated.

  10. 10.

    One could argue that an unconscious patient cannot be harmed because in this case “there is nobody” who could be harmed. However, harm can be more direct (e.g., pain) or more indirect (e.g., violation of interests). Moreover, one has probably to take into consideration various dimensions of consciousness and the self (for more on the concept of self see part 5 below).

  11. 11.

    Actually, consciousness corresponds to a single-storey building in this picture.

  12. 12.

    Think of a patient who is fully conscious of her pain, but of nothing else.

  13. 13.

    More potential fallacies have been described in regard of the broader ethical context, see for instance Johnson (2016), Northoff (2016).

  14. 14.

    A patient may be familiar with his mother’s voice or his father’s name without knowing much about his own and his parent’s biography.

  15. 15.

    This is not to say that consciousness is possible without brain activity.

  16. 16.

    In principle, we can never be completely sure whether someone really is conscious. See the zombie arguments in the philosophy of mind.

  17. 17.

    Sapience refers to Block’s access consciousness but seems to have a more comprehensive meaning. While Block’s concept can be used (locally) for the naked information, sapience alludes to the person’s (global) mental life.

  18. 18.

    That critical interests can persist in dementia, unconsciousness and even death need not be disputed here.

  19. 19.

    Remember that I assumed for the sake of clarity that the patient has no prospect of recovery.

  20. 20.

    Block himself argued for at least the conceptual possibility of phenomenal zombies, i.e. creatures with access—but no phenomenal consciousness (Block 1995).

  21. 21.

    Actually, he is not only a philosophical zombie, he is also a “philosophical twin”. This philosophical twin is your exact duplicate minus phenomenal consciousness.

  22. 22.

    Levy’s respective passage is worth citing at length: “But even if it is true that only a conscious being has a point of view, and that there can only be values if there are conscious acts of valuing, I see no reason at all to believe that the consciousness in question has to be phenomenal consciousness. My zombie twin has a point of view. He sees the world from a particular perspective, in an attitude-infused way. Indeed, his idiosyncratic take on things is identical to mine. He also values things. He believes that his life will go better if certain things happen, and therefore he desires that those things happen. He is motivated to do things that make it more likely that those things happen. There are states of affairs that he does not believe he can influence, but toward which he takes attitudes too (he hopes for peace in the Middle East, for instance). He is inclined to say that he values these things, and I am inclined to agree with him.” (Levy 2014, 133).

  23. 23.

    In the philosophical literature on consciousness is the “dreaming driver” a well-known example from everyday experience: Once you know the route from home to your office by heart, you will be able to make the ride “automatically” while dreaming of your lover. It may be the same with the zombie-systems giving the investigator the wrong impression that the patient is conscious.

  24. 24.

    For an instructive comparison of different accounts of consciousness and the self see Morin (2006).

  25. 25.

    The Theory of Mind (ToM) discussed in cognitive psychology probably builds upon this more basic and general “theory” of a mind.

References

  • Bayne, Tim, Jakob Hohwy, and Adrian M. Owen. 2016. Are There Levels of Consciousness? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 20 (6): 405–413. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2016.03.009.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bender, Andreas, Ralf J. Jox, Eva Grill, Andreas Straube, and Dorothée Lulé. 2015. Persistent Vegetative State and Minimally Conscious State: A Systematic Review and Meta-Analysis of Diagnostic Procedures. Deutsches Arzteblatt International 112 (14): 235–242. https://doi.org/10.3238/arztebl.2015.0235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, Ned. 1995. On a Confusion about a Function of Consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (02): 227–247. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00038188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruno, Marie-Aurélie., Audrey Vanhaudenhuyse, Aurore Thibaut, Gustave Moonen, and Steven Laureys. 2011. From Unresponsive Wakefulness to Minimally Conscious PLUS and Functional Locked-in Syndromes: Recent Advances in Our Understanding of Disorders of Consciousness. Journal of Neurology 258 (7): 1373–1384. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00415-011-6114-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cabrera, Laura Y., and Judy Illes. 2018. Balancing Ethics and Care in Disorders of Consciousness. The Lancet Neurology 17 (2): 112–113. https://doi.org/10.1016/S1474-4422(17)30402-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cavaliere, Carlo, Carol di Perri, Steven Laureys, and Andrea Soddu. 2016. Instrumental Assessment of Residual Consciousness in DOCs. In Neurotechnology and Direct Brain Communication: New Insights and Responsibilities Concerning Speechless but Communicative Subjects, ed. by Michele Farisco and Kathinka Evers, 70–84. Explorations in Cognitive Psychology Series. London; New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corbetta, Maurizio, and Gordon L. Shulman. 2002. Control of Goal-Directed and Stimulus-Driven Attention in the Brain. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3 (3): 201–215. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn755.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, Antonio R. 1999. The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness. Harcourt Brace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, Will, and Neil Levy. 2016. Persistent Vegetative State, Akinetic Mutism, and Consciousness. In Finding Consciousness: The Neuroscience, Ethics, and Law of Severe Brain Damage, ed. by Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, 122–34. Oxford Series in Neuroscience, Law, and Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel. 1992. The Self as a Center of Narrative Gravity. In Self and Consciousness: Multiple Perspectives, ed. Frank S. Kessel, Pamela M. Cole, and Dale L. Johnson, 103–115. Hillsdale, N.J: L. Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eickhoff, S.B., M. Dafotakis, C. Grefkes, T. Stöcker, N.J. Shah, A. Schnitzler, K. Zilles, and M. Siebler. 2008. FMRI Reveals Cognitive and Emotional Processing in a Long-Term Comatose Patient. Experimental Neurology 214 (2): 240–246. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.expneurol.2008.08.007.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farisco, Michele, and Kathinka Evers. 2017. The Ethical Relevance of the Unconscious. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine : PEHM 12 (December). https://doi.org/10.1186/s13010-017-0053-9.

  • Fazekas, Peter, and Morten Overgaard. 2018. A Multi-Factor Account of Degrees of Awareness. Cognitive Science 42: 1833–1859. https://doi.org/10.1111/cogs.12478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fernández-Espejo, Davinia, and Adrian M. Owen. 2013. Detecting Awareness after Severe Brain Injury. Nature Reviews. Neuroscience 14 (11): 801–809. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn3608.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fins, Joseph J. 2015. Rights Come to Mind. Brain Injury, Ethics, and the Struggle for Consciousness. 1st ed. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fins, Joseph J., and James L. Bernat. 2018. Ethical, Palliative, and Policy Considerations in Disorders of Consciousness. Archives of Physical Medicine and Rehabilitation 99 (9): 1927–1931. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.apmr.2018.07.003.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giacino, Joseph T., S. Ashwal, N. Childs, R. Cranford, B. Jennett, D.I. Katz, J.P. Kelly, et al. 2002. The Minimally Conscious State: Definition and Diagnostic Criteria. Neurology 58 (3): 349–353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giacino, Joseph T., M.A. Kezmarsky, J. DeLuca, and K.D. Cicerone. 1991. Monitoring Rate of Recovery to Predict Outcome in Minimally Responsive Patients. Archives of Physical Medicine and Rehabilitation 72 (11): 897–901.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glannon, Walter. 2016. The Value and Disvalue of Consciousness. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 25 (4): 600–612. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0963180116000335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg, D.L. 2007. Comment on “Detecting Awareness in the Vegetative State.” Science 315 (5816): 1221–1221. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1135284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jennett, B., and F. Plum. 1972. Persistent Vegetative State after Brain Damage. A Syndrome in Search of a Name. Lancet 1 (7753): 734–737.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, L. Syd M.. 2016. Inference and Inductive Risk in Disorders of Consciousness. AJOB Neuroscience 7 (1): 35–43. https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2016.1150908.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Jong, B.M., A.T. Willemsen, and A.M. Paans. 1997. Regional Cerebral Blood Flow Changes Related to Affective Speech Presentation in Persistent Vegetative State. Clinical Neurology and Neurosurgery 99 (3): 213–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jox, Ralf J., and Katja Kuehlmeyer. 2013. Introduction: Reconsidering Disorders of Consciousness in Light of Neuroscientific Evidence. Neuroethics 6 (1): 1–3. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-011-9138-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, Guy, and Julian Savulscu. 2009. Brain Damage and the Moral Significance of Consciousness. Journal of Medicine & Philosophy 34 (1): 6–26. https://doi.org/10.1093/jmp/jhn038.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1998. Critique of Pure Reason. The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. Cambridge ; New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laureys, Steven, Gastone G. Celesia, Francois Cohadon, Jan Lavrijsen, José León-Carrión, Walter G. Sannita, Leon Sazbon, et al. 2010. Unresponsive Wakefulness Syndrome: A New Name for the Vegetative State or Apallic Syndrome. BMC Medicine 8 (November): 68. https://doi.org/10.1186/1741-7015-8-68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laureys, Steven, and Nicholas D. Schiff. 2012. Coma and Consciousness: Paradigms (Re)Framed by Neuroimaging. NeuroImage 61 (2): 478–491. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuroimage.2011.12.041.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, Neil. 2014. The Value of Consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies: Controversies in Science & the Humanities 21 (1–2): 127–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, Neil, and Julian Savulescu. 2009. Moral Significance of Phenomenal Consciousness. In Coma Science: Clinical and Ethical Implications, ed. by Nicholas D. Schiff and Adrian M. Owen Steven Laureys, 177: 361–70. Progress in Brain Research. New York: Elsevier. https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0079612309177257.

  • Mäki-Marttunen, Verónica, Mariana Castro, Lisandro Olmos, Ramón Leiguarda, and Mirta Villarreal. 2016. Modulation of the Default-Mode Network and the Attentional Network by Self-Referential Processes in Patients with Disorder of Consciousness. Neuropsychologia 82 (February): 149–160. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2016.01.022.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menon, D.K., A.M. Owen, E.J. Williams, P.S. Minhas, C.M. Allen, S.J. Boniface, and J.D. Pickard. 1998. Cortical Processing in Persistent Vegetative State. Wolfson Brain Imaging Centre Team. Lancet (London, England) 352 (9123): 200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monti, Martin M. 2012. Cognition in the Vegetative State. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology 8 (1): 431–454. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-clinpsy-032511-143050.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monti, Martin M., Audrey Vanhaudenhuyse, Martin R. Coleman, Melanie Boly, John D. Pickard, Luaba Tshibanda, Adrian M. Owen, and Steven Laureys. 2010. Willful Modulation of Brain Activity in Disorders of Consciousness. New England Journal of Medicine 362 (7): 579–589. https://doi.org/10.1056/NEJMoa0905370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morin, Alain. 2006. Levels of Consciousness and Self-Awareness: A Comparison and Integration of Various Neurocognitive Views. Consciousness and Cognition 15 (2): 358–371. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2005.09.006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nachev, P., and M. Husain. 2007. Comment on “Detecting Awareness in the Vegetative State.” Science 315 (5816): 1221–1221. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1135096.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, Thomas. 1974. What Is It Like to Be a Bat? the Philosophical Review 83 (4): 435–450. https://doi.org/10.2307/2183914.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Naro, Antonino, Antonino Leo, Alfredo Manuli, Antonino Cannavò, Alessia Bramanti, Placido Bramanti, and Rocco Salvatore Calabrò. 2017. How Far Can We Go in Chronic Disorders of Consciousness Differential Diagnosis? The Use of Neuromodulation in Detecting Internal and External Awareness. Neuroscience 349 (May): 165–173. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuroscience.2017.02.053.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neisser, Ulric. 1988. Five Kinds of Self-Knowledge. Philosophical Psychology 1 (1): 35–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Northoff, Georg. 2016. Doaes Task-Evoked Activity Entail Consciousness in Vetetative State? In Neurotechnology and Direct Brain Communication: New Insights and Responsibilities Concerning Speechless but Communicative Subjects, ed. by Michele Farisco and Kathinka Evers, 104–16. London; New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Owen, Adrian M., Martin R. Coleman, Melanie Boly, Matthew H. Davis, Steven Laureys, and John D. Pickard. 2006. Detecting Awareness in the Vegetative State. Science 313 (5792): 1402–1402. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1130197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pistoia, Francesca, Simona Sacco, Janet Stewart, Marco Sarà, and Antonio Carolei. 2016. Disorders of Consciousness: Painless or Painful Conditions?-Evidence from Neuroimaging Studies. Brain Sciences 6 (4). https://doi.org/10.3390/brainsci6040047.

  • Płonka, Beata. 2015. Neurobiology of Consciousness: Current Research and Perspectives. Studia Humana 4 (December): 23–38. https://doi.org/10.1515/sh-2015-0023.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Posner, Jerome B., Clifford B. Saper, Nicholas Schiff, and Fred Plum. 1983. Plum and Posner’s Diagnosis of Stupor and Coma. Fourth Edition, 2007. Contemporary Neurology Series. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raichle, M.E., A.M. MacLeod, A.Z. Snyder, W.J. Powers, D.A. Gusnard, and G.L. Shulman. 2001. A Default Mode of Brain Function. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 98 (2): 676–682. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.98.2.676.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaefer, Michael, and Georg Northoff. 2017. Who Am I: The Conscious and the Unconscious Self. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 11: 126. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2017.00126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schechtman, Marya. 2011. The Narrative Self. In The Oxford Handbook of the Self, ed. by Shaun Gallagher. Oxford ; New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schnakers, Caroline, Audrey Vanhaudenhuyse, Joseph Giacino, Manfredi Ventura, Melanie Boly, Steve Majerus, Gustave Moonen, and Steven Laureys. 2009. Diagnostic Accuracy of the Vegetative and Minimally Conscious State: Clinical Consensus versus Standardized Neurobehavioral Assessment. BMC Neurology 9 (1). https://doi.org/10.1186/1471-2377-9-35.

  • Shepherd, Joshua. 2018. Consciousness and Moral Status. Routledge Focus on Philosophy. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Staffen, W., M. Kronbichler, M. Aichhorn, A. Mair, and G. Ladurner. 2006. Selective Brain Activity in Response to One’s Own Name in the Persistent Vegetative State. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry 77 (12): 1383–1384. https://doi.org/10.1136/jnnp.2006.095166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • The Multi-Society Task Force on PVS. 1994. Medical Aspects of the Persistent Vegetative State (1). New England Journal of Medicine 330 (21): 1499–1508. https://doi.org/10.1056/NEJM199405263302107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanhaudenhuyse, Audrey, Vanessa Charland-Verville, Aurore Thibaut, Camille Chatelle, Jean-Flory L. Tshibanda, Audrey Maudoux, Marie-Elisabeth. Faymonville, Steven Laureys, and Olivia Gosseries. 2018. Conscious While Being Considered in an Unresponsive Wakefulness Syndrome for 20 Years. Frontiers in Neurology 9: 671. https://doi.org/10.3389/fneur.2018.00671.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanhaudenhuyse, Audrey, Athena Demertzi, Manuel Schabus, Quentin Noirhomme, Serge Bredart, Melanie Boly, Christophe Phillips, et al. 2011. Two Distinct Neuronal Networks Mediate the Awareness of Environment and of Self. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 23 (3): 570–578. https://doi.org/10.1162/jocn.2010.21488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vogeley, Kai, and Shaun Gallagher. 2011. Self in the Brain. In The Oxford Handbook of the Self, ed. by Shaun Gallagher, 111–36. Oxford ; New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, Dominic, Guy Kahane, and Julian Savulescu. 2008. “Neglected Personhood” and Neglected Questions: Remarks on the Moral Significance of Consciousness. The American Journal of Bioethics 8 (9): 31–33. https://doi.org/10.1080/15265160802412486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marco Stier .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Stier, M. (2020). Remainders of the Self: Consciousness as a Problem for Neuroethics. In: Kühler, M., Mitrović, V.L. (eds) Theories of the Self and Autonomy in Medical Ethics. The International Library of Bioethics, vol 83. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-56703-3_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics