Skip to main content

Narratives in Flux. Why Patients’ Life Stories Do Not Provide Decisive Instructions in Cases of Surrogate Decision-Making

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Theories of the Self and Autonomy in Medical Ethics

Part of the book series: The International Library of Bioethics ((ILB,volume 83))

Abstract

This paper critically discusses the role narrative accounts of the self might play in surrogate decision-making. Medical cases in which patients are not or no longer able to express their interests and also have not given a prior account of them present us with the question of how to respect their autonomy, i.e. how the patient would probably want to be treated, were he or she able to decide for him- or herself. In such situations it seems natural to refer to a notion of the person’s identity or self, for based on this we might extrapolate how the person would decide in an authentic manner. In this regard, narrative theories of the self seem to be able to provide a reasonable answer. Knowing a person’s life story seems to suggest a simple and convincing way to determine her authentic interests based on how her story, i.e. her narrative identity, would continue in a plausible and coherent way. However, I claim that narrative accounts of the self inherently fail to provide a simple and convincing answer in such cases. After distinguishing between mere expressive narrative accounts and constitutive narrative accounts, I argue that expressive narrative accounts do not present an independent analysis of the constitution of the self to begin with and are at best a helpful epistemic tool to find out what the patient’s autonomous preference likely would be. Yet, even this only holds under the contestable assumption that the patient’s self remains stable. Constitutive narrative accounts, on the other hand, while indeed presenting an independent account of the constitution of the self, either revert back to an expressive narrative account if the idea of one’s free authorship of one’s life story is rejected, or they fail to provide any reason for why one should choose a certain version of the patient’s life story as the newly to be constructed one. Instead, I conclude that a person’s life story remains in a constant state of flux, which is why also constitutive narrative accounts are unable to provide surrogate decision-makers with a well-justified answer which treatment option to choose in order to respect the patient’s autonomy based on who he or she is.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    For ethics as well as political philosophy in general, see the overview in Christman 2015, and for medical ethics in particular, see most prominently Beauchamp and Childress 2013, esp. ch. 4.

  2. 2.

    With the only exception of cases of hard paternalism if one concedes that such acts can ever be ethically justified. See in this regard, for instance, Beauchamp and Childress 2013, 221–23.

  3. 3.

    For an overview, see Jaworska 2017.

  4. 4.

    Throughout my paper I use the term ‘self’ interchangeably with a person’s ‘identity’ (as this term is usually understood in the social sciences), ‘personality,’ or ‘character,’ i.e. in general in terms of an answer to the everyday question who a person is and to spell out the criterion of authenticity within the notion of personal autonomy.

  5. 5.

    Cp. MacIntyre 1981, ch. 15; Ricœur 1987, 1991, 1995, ch. 6; Schechtman 1996; DeGrazia 2005, ch. 3; Henning 2009; and Davenport 2012. For a concise overview, see Shoemaker 2016, Sects. 2.3 and 6.2. For seminal criticisms of narrative approaches to the self, see Strawson 2004; and Lamarque 2004.

  6. 6.

    To avoid a possible misunderstanding, I do not argue against either expressive or constitutive narrative accounts per se, i.e. in terms of such accounts being implausible analyses of the (constitution of) the self. I merely argue that neither of these accounts, convincing as they may be per se, is able to provide us with a solution to surrogate decision-making in medical ethics.

  7. 7.

    See Kuczewski 1994, 1999; and Blustein 1999. See also Rich 1997; Lindemann Nelson 1997; McCarthy 2003; DeGrazia 2005, esp. ch. 3; Torke, Alexander, and Lantos 2008; and Witt 2018.

  8. 8.

    Blustein 1999, 21.

  9. 9.

    Kuczewski 1999, 33.

  10. 10.

    Schechtman 1996, 93f. Cp. also DeGrazia 2005, 80–88, who roughly agrees with Schechtman’s account.

  11. 11.

    Cp. Schechtman 1996, 114–30; and Blustein 1999, 23 and 28.

  12. 12.

    Blustein 1999, 22.

  13. 13.

    Blustein 1999, 22, cp. also 24. Kuczewski agrees (cp. Kuczewski 1999, 33f.).

  14. 14.

    Blustein 1999, 23. Kuczewski argues along the same lines (cp. Kuczewski 1999, 34).

  15. 15.

    Cp. Blustein 1999, 25; and Kuczewski 1999, 33f. Given the possibility that the patient may have told multiple and more or less different versions of his or her life story, it remains an open question which of these versions should be seen as authoritative.

  16. 16.

    Although Schechtman’s term for her view is obviously straightforward enough in claiming that a person’s narrative is constitutive of her identity or self, the constraints she introduces seem to indicate that one’s narrative may very well be conceived of as merely an adequate expression of an underlying content (cp. again Schechtman 1996, 114–30). Cp. also Kuczewski 1994, 43f., 1999, 33; Blustein 1999, 24–26; and DeGrazia 2005, 80.

  17. 17.

    For a concise overview of general approaches to the constitution of the self, see Kühler and Jelinek 2013; and Shoemaker 2016.

  18. 18.

    This problem essentially mirrors the similar problem with referring to a patient’s advance directives, as one can never be sure that the patient’s expressed preference in it may still be considered valid and has not changed since then.

  19. 19.

    Blustein actually admits this presupposition of stability explicitly (cp. Blustein 1999, 22).

  20. 20.

    Cp. MacIntyre 1981, 217f.; Ricœur 1995, 140f.; and Schechtman 1996, 94.

  21. 21.

    Cp. Blustein 1999, 20f.; and Kuczewski 1999, 33.

  22. 22.

    See Ricœur 1987, 1991, 1995, esp. ch. 6.

  23. 23.

    On a critical note, Galen Strawson has prominently pointed out that putting aspects and situations of a person’s life in a meaningful order does not necessarily mean telling a canonized form of story (cp. Strawson 2004, 439–43). Weaker versions of constitutive narrative accounts, thus, only comprise the claim that some form of meaningful order has to be established with regard to the aspects and situations in question. While this may be done in form of a canonized story, it does not have to be. In contrast, stronger versions of constitutive narrative accounts, like Ricœur’s, claim just that. We need canonized forms of storytelling in order to construe a meaningful self. Moreover, we also need an adequate social context in which this may be done and from which the canonized forms of storytelling stem. Be that as it may, the crucial point for my discussion here is that both weaker and stronger versions of constitutive narrative accounts include the claim that at least some form of meaningful order needs to be construed in order to render single events or decisions intelligible within a coherent frame of reference.

  24. 24.

    Cp. Ricœur 1987, 59–61, and 1995, 141–43.

  25. 25.

    Cp. Ricœur 1987, 61–63, and 1995, 143–47.

  26. 26.

    Cp. Ricœur 1987, 63–67, and 1995, 148–51.

  27. 27.

    Cp. Blustein 1999, 25; and Kuczewski 1999, 33f.

  28. 28.

    While Blustein explicitly denies this (cp. Blustein 1999, 26f.), I take it that, given Ricœur’s elaboration on constitutive narrative accounts and even Blustein’s own partial admittance (cp. Blustein 1999, 27), his claim to the contrary remains unconvincing.

  29. 29.

    This holds at least partially if the impact of social conditions on what may count as successful storytelling and which versions of a story a person comes to think of in the first place is taken into account.

  30. 30.

    DeGrazia 2005, 107.

  31. 31.

    Cf. Frankfurt 1993, 109f.; and Taylor 1977, 31–33.

  32. 32.

    Of course, much more needs to be said about whether an existentialist approach to the constitution of the self is really untenable. For a concise overview of existentialism in general, see Crowell 2017, and for an existentialist approach to the constitution of the self in particular, see Kühler and Jelinek 2013, xif. and xviii–xx. For the purpose of my paper, however, I can leave this question open.

  33. 33.

    Schechtman’s discussion of the articulation constraint and reality constraint remains rather vague in this regard. If there are, indeed, any decisive criteria upon which one’s self-narrative can be judged as being adequate or not, this would imply that one’s life story has to track underlying and given content of one’s life and character. However, if there are no such decisive criteria, this would imply that the constraints Schechtman advocates cannot plausibly go beyond simple descriptive coherence with reality, e.g. one’s whereabouts at a certain time. Cp. Schechtman 1996, 115–19 and 125–30.

References

  • Beauchamp, Tom L., and James F. Childress. 2013. Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 7th ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blustein, Jeffrey. 1999. Choosing for Others as Continuing a Life Story: The Problem of Personal Identity Revisited. Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 27 (1): 20–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christman, John. 2015. Autonomy in Moral and Political Philosophy. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. by Edward N. Zalta. Spring 2015. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/autonomy-moral/.

  • Crowell, Steven. 2017. Existentialism. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. by Edward N. Zalta, Winter 2017. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/existentialism/.

  • Davenport, John J. 2012. Narrative Identity, Autonomy, and Mortality. From Frankfurt and MacIntyre to Kierkegaard. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia, David. 2005. Human Identity and Bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, Harry G. 1993. On the Necessity of Ideals. In Necessity, Volition, and Love, by Harry G. Frankfurt, 108–16. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henning, Tim. 2009. Person sein und Geschichten erzählen: Eine Studie über personale Autonomie und narrative Gründe. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaworska, Agnieszka. 2017. Advance Directives and Substitute Decision-Making. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. by Edward N. Zalta, Summer 2017. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/advance-directives/.

  • Kuczewski, Mark G. 1994. Whose Will Is It, Anyway? A Discussion of Advance Directives, Personal Identity, and Consensus in Medical Ethics. Bioethics 8 (1): 27–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuczewski, Mark G. 1999. Commentary: Narrative Views of Personal Identity and Substituted Judgment in Surrogate Decision-making. Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 27 (1): 32–36. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1748-720X.1999.tb01433.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kühler, Michael, and Nadja Jelinek. 2013. Introduction. In Autonomy and the Self, ed. by Michael Kühler and Nadja Jelinek, ix–xxxvi. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamarque, Peter. 2004. On Not Expecting Too Much from Narrative. Mind & Language 19 (4): 393–408. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0268-1064.2004.00265.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindemann Nelson, Hilde, ed. 1997. Stories and Their Limits: Narrative Approaches to Bioethics. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1981. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, Joan. 2003. Principlism or Narrative Ethics: Must We Choose Between Them? Medical Humanities 29 (2): 65–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rich, Ben A. 1997. Prospective Autonomy and Critical Interests: A Narrative Defense of the Moral Authority of Advance Directives. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 6 (2): 138–147. https://doi.org/10.1017/s0963180100007763.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ricœur, Paul. 1987. Narrative Identität. Heidelberger Jahrbücher 3: 57–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ricœur, Paul. 1991. Narrative Identity. Philosophy Today 35 (1): 73–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ricœur, Paul. 1995. Oneself as Another. Trans. by Kathleen Blamey. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schechtman, Marya. 1996. The Constitution of Selves. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, David. 2016. Personal Identity and Ethics. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. by Edward N. Zalta, Winter 2016. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/identity-ethics/.

  • Strawson, Galen. 2004. Against Narrativity. Ratio (New Series) 17: 428–452.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1977. What Is Human Agency? In Philosophical Papers 1. Human Agency and Language, by Charles Taylor, 15–44. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  • Torke, Alexia M., G. Caleb Alexander, and John Lantos. 2008. Substituted Judgment: The Limitations of Autonomy in Surrogate Decision Making. Journal of General Internal Medicine 23 (9): 1514–1517. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11606-008-0688-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt, Karsten. 2018. ‘Narrative and Characterization’. Erkenntnis, 1–19. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0017-5.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Kühler .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Kühler, M. (2020). Narratives in Flux. Why Patients’ Life Stories Do Not Provide Decisive Instructions in Cases of Surrogate Decision-Making. In: Kühler, M., Mitrović, V.L. (eds) Theories of the Self and Autonomy in Medical Ethics. The International Library of Bioethics, vol 83. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-56703-3_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics