Skip to main content

Between Life and Existence. Heidegger’s Aristotelianism and the Question of Animality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Heidegger and Contemporary Philosophy

Part of the book series: Contributions to Hermeneutics ((CONT HERMEN,volume 8))

  • 375 Accesses

Abstract

This paper starts by investigating the Aristotelian roots of Heidegger’s stance toward animal life from 1924 lecture course “Basic concepts of Aristotelian philosophy” to 1929/30 lecture course “The fundamental concepts of Metaphysics”. In following Aristotle, Heidegger displays the ontological transition from life to existence as grounded to the peculiar linguistic ability of human beings. In doing that, both Heidegger and Aristotle seem to establish a connection between an existential faculty (logos) and the apparently dominant position occupied by our species. On the other side, though, to be endowed with logos means for human beings to be able to de-centre themselves in recognizing the essential connection to other beings in the whole of life. This insight will concur in leading Heidegger after the 20’s to the rethinking of the role played by man in the new structure of Ereignis and to crucial notions as Lichtung, Open and Quaternity. But this peculiar function seems also to specify Aristotle’s system of human (anthroposcopic) knowledge as pointing to the idea of a general continuity of life, from simplest living beings via the sublunar world to the perfect life of stars and Deity. So apparently maintaining, despite Heidegger’s claim of going beyond metaphysics, the connection with Aristotle strong even in the later stages of his thought.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Derrida (2006).

  2. 2.

    Agamben (2004).

  3. 3.

    On the debate concerning Aristotle’s anthropocentrism, see Sedley (1991).

  4. 4.

    See Sorabji (1993).

  5. 5.

    E. g. De Fontenay (1998).

  6. 6.

    See Labarrière (2005).

  7. 7.

    See Singer (1975) and Regan (1983).

  8. 8.

    As an introduction to animality studies, see Lundblad (2009).

  9. 9.

    See on this Shepard (1996).

  10. 10.

    See Cimatti (2015, 2016).

  11. 11.

    See Calarco (2008).

  12. 12.

    Heidegger (2009).

  13. 13.

    Heidegger (1995).

  14. 14.

    See on this McNeill (1999).

  15. 15.

    Heidegger (2009, 14).

  16. 16.

    As distinctively pointed out by Bailey (2011).

  17. 17.

    Heidegger (2009, 14).

  18. 18.

    Kisiel (1995, 295).

  19. 19.

    Heidegger (2009, 39).

  20. 20.

    Heidegger (2009, 39).

  21. 21.

    Heidegger (2009, 37).

  22. 22.

    See Heidegger (2009, 39): “Aristotle supplies the reference to phone and zoa as theria at the outset, in order to give the correct background for the further being-characteristic of human beings in the world, for the logos-investigation.”

  23. 23.

    Cf. Heidegger (2009, 39).

  24. 24.

    Reference is to Aristotle, Pol. A 2, 1253 a 14–16 ff.

  25. 25.

    Heidegger (2009, 41).

  26. 26.

    Heidegger (2009, 42–43).

  27. 27.

    Heidegger (2009, 37–38).

  28. 28.

    Heidegger (2009, 220).

  29. 29.

    Cf. Heidegger (1995, 177).

  30. 30.

    Heidegger (1995, 248). On the theories of Jakob von Uexküll as a source for this Heideggerian principle, see Agamben (2002), 42: “Uexküll affirms - and thus formulates a principle that would have some success - that “no animal can enter into relation with an object as such,” but only with its own carriers of significance”. For a general overview of Uexküll’s influence in the philosophy of twentieth century (Heidegger included) see Kull (2001).

  31. 31.

    Derrida (2006, 89).

  32. 32.

    Among the various (and constantly increasing in number) tendencies that could be briefly quoted as paradigmatic of the current scenario: Animality Studies: an emerging interdisciplinary academic field focused on the cultural study of animals and animality. It can be distinguished from animal studies and critical animal studies by its resistance to animal rights or animal welfare as an explicit justification for work in this field (Lundblaud, 2002); Zoography: a perspective developed by Calarco (2008), who is opposed to Heidegger and Derrida’s notion of difference: the idea of a radical indistinction which rules over any form of animal life, insofar as what specifies life in general is bodily and fleshy constitution; Philosophy of animality: a perspective recently developed among the others by F. Cimatti (2015, 2016).

  33. 33.

    Cimatti (2015, 42).

  34. 34.

    This idea is variously connected to the efforts by Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari to give sense to the post-nietzschean notion of “becoming animal”. Also see on this, Deleuze and Guattari (1987, 238) and Cimatti (2015).

  35. 35.

    Cimatti (2015, 50).

  36. 36.

    Cimatti (2015, 52).

  37. 37.

    Agamben (2004, 39).

  38. 38.

    Agamben (2004, 13–14). The reference is to Aristotle, De Anima 413 a 20 ff.: “It is through life that what has soul in it differs from what has not.1 Now this term “to live” has more than one sense, and provided any one alone of these is found in a thing we say that the thing is living—viz. thinking, sensation, local movement and rest, or movement in the sense of nutrition, decay and growth. Hence we think of all species of plants also as living, for they are observed to possess in themselves a principle and potentiality through which they grow and decay in opposite directions... This principle can be separated from the others, but not they from it—in mortal beings at least. The fact is obvious in plants; for it is the only psychic potentiality they possess. Thus, it is through this principle that life belongs to living things... By nutritive power (threptikon) we mean that part of the soul which is common also to plants.”. Quoted in Agamben (2004, 13–14).

  39. 39.

    Agamben (2004, 14).

  40. 40.

    Agamben (2004, 15–16).

  41. 41.

    Agamben (2004, 16).

  42. 42.

    Dombrowski (1994) and Glendinning (1996) versus Schalow (2006) can be considered representative of the opposition between anthropocentric and anti-anthropocentric reading of Heidegger.

  43. 43.

    E. g. the case of the De Motu Animalium, in which the eminent case of movement, according to the premises of the work, could be considered the perfect living being, i.e. the divine. On the possibility of a “multicentric” approach of Aristotle, according to the various domains of his investigations, see Nussbaum (1986, xv).

  44. 44.

    Heidegger (2009, 69).

  45. 45.

    On this, see the chapter «Who speaks for the Animals?» in (2006, 103).

References

  • G. Agamben, The Open: Man and Animal (or. ed. 2002), tr. by K. Attell, Stanford University Press, Stanford (CA) 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • C. Bailey, Animal Dasein. The Genesis of Existentials in the Early Heideggers Interpretations of Aristoteles, «Heidegger Circle Proceedings» 1 (2011), pp. 199-212.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Calarco, Zoographies: The Question of the Animal from Heidegger to Derrida, Columbia University Press, New York 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • F. Cimatti, Ten Theses on Animality, “Lo Sguardo”, 18(2), 2015, pp. 41-59.

    Google Scholar 

  • F. Cimatti, Beyond the human/non-human dichotomy: the philosophical problem of human animality, in “Humanimalia” 7/2016, pp. 35-55.

    Google Scholar 

  • É de Fontenay, Le silence des bétes. La philosophie à l’èpreuve de l’animalitè, Fayard, Paris 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Deleuze and F. Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus. Capitalism and Schizophrenia, trans. by B. Massumi, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Derrida, The Animal That Therefore I am (or. ed. 2006), ed. by M.-L. Mallet, trans. by D. Wills, Fordham University Press, New York 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • D. Dombrowski, Heidegger’s anti-Anthropocentrism, in «Between the Species» 10/1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • S. Glendinning, Heidegger and the Question of Animality, «International Journal of Philosophical Studies» 4/1 (1996), pp. 75-82.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Heidegger, The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude, transl. by. W. McNeill and N. Walker, Indiana University Press, Bloomington & Indianapolis 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Heidegger, Basic Concepts of Aristotelian Philosophy, transl. by R. D. Metcalf and M. B. Tanzer, Indiana University Press, Bloomington & Indianapolis 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Th. Kisiel, The Genesis of Heidegger’s Being and Time, University of California Press, London 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • K. Kull, Jakob von Uexküll: An Introduction, in “Semiotica” 134 (2001), pp. 1-59.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.-L. Labarrière, La condition animale. Études sur Aristote et les Stoïciens, Peeters, Louvain/Paris/Dudley (MA) 2005.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Lundlblad, From Animal to Animality Studies, in “PMLA” 124/2009, pp. 496-502.

    Google Scholar 

  • W. McNeill, The Glance of the Eye. Heidegger, Aristotle and the Ends of Theory, SUNY Press, Albany 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. C. Nussbaum, Introduction in Aristotle’s De Motu Animalium, ed. by M. C. Nussbaum, Princeton University Press, Princeton 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  • T. Regan, The Case for Animal Rights, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London 1983.

    Google Scholar 

  • F. Schalow, The Incarnality of Being. The Earth, Animals and the Body in Heidegger’s Thought, SUNY Press, Albany 2006,

    Google Scholar 

  • D. Sedley, Is Aristotle’s Biology anthropocentric?, in “Phronesis”, 36/1991, pp. 179-196.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Shepard, The others. How animals made us human, Island Press, Washington 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Sorabji, Animal Minds and Human Morals. The Origin of the Western Debate, Duckworth, London 1993.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrea Le Moli .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Le Moli, A. (2021). Between Life and Existence. Heidegger’s Aristotelianism and the Question of Animality. In: Di Martino, C. (eds) Heidegger and Contemporary Philosophy. Contributions to Hermeneutics, vol 8. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-56566-4_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics