Skip to main content

Blushing with Shame: Toward a Hegelian Contribution on the Issue of the Positive Role of Negative Emotions

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Dark Side: Philosophical Reflections on the “Negative Emotions”

Part of the book series: Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind ((SHPM,volume 25))

Abstract

This essay examines the notion of shame in Hegel’s writings as a case study to show that an emotion that is generally considered ‘negative’ may nonetheless fulfil important functions in the life of the subject. In none of Hegel’s works the concept of shame is analysed systematically and thoroughly. Therefore, I will start by analysing the encyclopaedic Anthropology to show how feelings always presume, for Hegel, states of physiological arousal and include bodily manifestations. Subsequently, on the basis of the encyclopaedic Psychology, I will show not only that the philosopher attributes considerable importance to sensations and feelings in general but also considers the emotional dimension of the subject in continuity with rational thinking. Eventually, I will examine some relevant passages of the Encyclopaedia Logic and the Aesthetic and I will show how, for Hegel, shame plays a relevant role in the process of development of the human being. Indeed, shame is considered by the philosopher as the constitutive place of self-consciousness. Contextually, I will try to retrieve the relations, by way of comparison and contrast, between the Hegelian understanding of shame and the most recent psychological and neuroscientific findings.

The English version of this paper was revised by dr. Giorgia Falceri.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    With regard to Hegel’s works it is not correct to use the term ‘emotions’, because the term did not exist in the German language in Hegel’s time, as evidenced by the fact that the word does not appear in the brothers Grimm’s Deutsches Wörterbuch (1854–1917).

  2. 2.

    The Große Enzyklopädie published after Hegel’s death by his disciples is nothing but the text of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1830) enriched by substantial additions in which the editors collected Hegel’s autograph notes and notes taken by some of his students during lectures.

  3. 3.

    Some illustrious interpreters of Hegel’s philosophy, such as Bodammer (1969, 2), Peperzak (1987, 9) and Rometsch (2007, 9–16), are against the use of secondary sources. However, unpublished or non-autographed documents (although they should not be used uncritically as evidence) provide information both on how Hegel meditated on different topics and on his own writings, and on how students received his lectures. Moreover, since in the last few years a large amount of non-autographed and unpublished material has been published by the Hegel-Archiv of Bochum and included in the critical edition of the Gesammelte Werke, it is now possible to use the secondary tradition according to criteria that guarantee a remarkable reliability.

  4. 4.

    These considerations seem to precede the research of neuroscientist Antonio Damasio, according to whom body and mind constitute an integrated unity with respect to which every dualism turns out to be an abstraction that prevents from understanding our neurological and mental processes. Consequently, emotions cannot be reduced to the mental activity of the brain, but result from a combination of mental evaluative acts and somatic modifications (Damasio 1994).

  5. 5.

    In the Philosophy of Mind edited by Michael Inwood, which is cited in this study, ‘Affekte’ is in my opinion erroneously translated into ‘emotions’ (cf. footnote 1). ‘Affektion’, which derives from the Latin ‘afficere’, suggests the idea of being affected by something and it is a common word in Hegel’s time (see Kant 2006, 149–182), as it had entered the German vocabulary in 1500. Michael J. Petry – who in his edition of Hegel’s Philosophy of Subjective Spirit translates ’Affekte’ with ’affections’ (Petry 1978, Vol. 2, 163) – explains: “Hegel, like many of his contemporaries, regarded affections as being closely associated with sensations (§ 401), an as therefore differing from passions […] (§§ 473/4), in that they are intense and ephemeral, and not the outcome of a slowly developing or persistent desire. If an affection’s effect upon a person’s disposition remained confined to the soul, it was a feeling; if it influenced his body, it was an ‘Affekt’” (Petry 1978, Vol. 1, cxxiv).

  6. 6.

    On the difference between ‘basic’ or ‘primary’ emotions and ‘complex’ or ‘secondary’ emotions see infra, 11.3.

  7. 7.

    Schachter and Singer critique William James who, in his famous What is an Emotion?, defines the emotion as a feeling of the bodily changes that occur following a stimulus. Consequently, says James, we do not cry, strike or tremble because we are sad, angry or afraid, but “we feel sorry because we cry, angry because we strike, afraid because we tremble” (James 1884, 190). According to James, the feeling of arousal that the subject has is therefore fundamental to define an emotion.

  8. 8.

    A link between cognition and feeling was already suggested by Aristotle in his Rhetoric. It is indeed the judgment of something like an insult that we deem undeserved, that triggers the passion of anger (Aristotle 1909, 68–69).

  9. 9.

    Most contemporary theories maintain that there is only a small number of basic emotions and that all the others result from a mixture of these, as it happens with complex colours – to use a metaphor of Robert Plutchik (1962) – which all derive from the three primary colours. However, there is no unanimity on what and how many the basic emotions are: Plutchik postulates eight, Carroll Izard (2007) six, while Silvan Tomkins (1963) claims they are also eight, but different from those listed by Plutchik.

  10. 10.

    In his interpretation of the Genesis myth of the fall, Hegel, who calls himself a Lutheran (Hegel 1984b, 520), most likely draws upon the Protestant literature (see Almond 1999; Crowther 2010), which he has known in his time as a student in Tübingen.

  11. 11.

    In The Conjectural Beginning of Human History (1786), Kant rereads the myth of the fall having in mind Rousseau’s Discourse on the Origin and Foundations of Inequality Among Men (1755), and states that the knowledge acquired by Adam and Eve consists in the fact that human beings, unlike animals, can say no to instinct, which means they are capable of freedom (Kant 2007, 169).

  12. 12.

    Lloyd-Jones (1971) subsequently extended his interpretation of Greek society as based on the sense of shame to the entire classical period. Scholars such as Adkins (1960) and Carter (1986) worked in the same framework. Instead, Williams (1993) – in counterposition to Snell (1948) – criticised this hermeneutic approach, developing his own arguments from the implications that the antithesis under scrutiny has with regard to personal identity and the existence of the Self.

  13. 13.

    “But if it is simply identical with the actuality of individuals, the ethical, as their general mode of behaviour, appears as custom; and the habit of the ethical appears as a second nature” (Hegel 1991a, 195).

References

  • Adkins, A. W. H. (1960). Merit and responsibility. A study in Greek values. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Almond, P. C. (1999). Adam and Eve in seventeenth-century thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1909). The Rhetoric of Aristotle (Vol. 2) (R. Claverhouse Jebb, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (2000). Nicomachean Ethics (R. Crisp, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arndt, A. (2017). Zur Rolle des Gefühls in Hegels Theorie des subjektiven Geistes. In A. Arndt & J. Zovko (Eds.), Hegels Anthropologie (pp. 75–88). Berlin/Boston: de Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Arnold, M. B. (1960). Emotion and personality (Vol. 1–2). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Averill, J. R. (1976). Emotion and anxiety: Sociocultural, biological, and psychological determinants. In M. Zuckerman & C. D. Spielberger (Eds.), Emotions and anxiety: New concepts, methods, and applications (pp. 87–130). Oxford: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benedict, R. (1946). The chrysanthemum and the sword: Patterns of Japanese culture. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bodammer, T. (1969). Hegels Deutung der Sprache. Interpretationen zu Hegels Äusserungen über die Sprache. Hamburg: Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, L. B. (1986). The quiet Athenian. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charland, L. C. (2005). Emotion experience and the indeterminacy of valence. In L. Feldman Barrett, P. M. Niedenthal, & P. Winkielman (Eds.), Emotion and consciousness (pp. 231–254). New York: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2005). Appraising valence. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 12(8–10), 103–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowther, K. M. (2010). Adam and Eve in the protestant reformation. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason and the human brain. New York: Grosset/Putnam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1998). The expression of emotions in man and animals (3rd ed.). Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, R. J., & Fox, N. A. (1982). Asymmetrical brain activity discriminates between positive versus negative affective stimuli in human infants. Science, 218(4578), 1235–1237. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.7146906.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Sousa, R. (1987). The rationality of emotions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Deonna, J. A., Rodogno, R., & Teroni, F. (2012). In defense of shame. The faces of an emotion. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dodds, E. R. (1951). The Greeks and the irrational. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ekman, P. (1984). Expression and the nature of emotion. In K. R. Scherer & P. Ekman (Eds.), Approaches to emotion (pp. 319–344). Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ekman, P. (1999). Basic emotions. In T. Dalgleish & M. Power (Eds.), Handbook of cognition and emotions (pp. 45–60). Chichester: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ekman, P., & Cordaro, D. (2011). What is meant by calling emotions basic. Emotions Review, 3(4), 364–370. https://doi.org/10.1177/1754073911410740.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ekman, P., Friesen, W. V., & Ellsworth, P. (1972). Emotion in the human face: Guidelines for research and an integration of findings. New York: Pergamon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman Barrett, L. (2006). Are emotions natural kinds? Perspectives on Psychological Sciences, 1(1), 28–58. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00003.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flügel, J. C. (1966). The psychology of clothes (4th ed.). London: The Hogarth Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frijda, N. (1986). The emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2003). The moral emotions. In R. J. Davidson, K. R. Scherer, & H. H. Goldsmith (Eds.), Handbook of affective sciences (pp. 852–870). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1975). Aesthetics. Lectures on fine art (Vol. 2) (T. M. Knox, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1984a). Lectures on the philosophy of religion: Vol. 1. Introduction and the concept of religion (R. F. Brown, P. C. Hodgson, & J. M. Stewart, Trans.). Berkeley/Los Angeles/London: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1984b). Hegel: The letters (C. Butler & C. Seiler, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1991a). Elements of the philosophy of right (H. B. Nisbet, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1991b). The encyclopaedia logic (with the Zusätze) (T. F. Geraets, W. A. Suchting, & H. S. Harris, Trans.). Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Pub. Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1995). Lectures on the philosophy of religion: Vol. 2. Determinate religion (R. F. Brown, P. C. Hodgson, & J. M. Stewart, Trans.). Berkeley/Los Angeles/London: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (2004). Philosophy of nature (A. V. Miller, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (2007a). Lectures on the philosophy of spirit 1827–28 (R. R. Williams, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (2007b). Philosophy of mind (W. Wallace & A. V. Miller, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (2018). The phenomenology of spirit (M. Inwood, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, J. J. (2013). Hegel on emotions. Coordinating form and content. In D. S. Stern (Ed.), Essay on Hegel’s philosophy of subjective spirit (pp. 71–86). Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Izard, C. E. (1977). Human emotions. New York: Plenum Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Izard, C. E. (2007). Basic emotions, natural kinds, emotion schemas, and a new paradigm. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 2(3), 260–280. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1745-6916.2007.00044.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1884). What is an emotion? Mind, 9(34), 188–205. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/os-IX.34.188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2006). Anthropology from a pragmatic point of view (R. B. Louden, Trans.). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2007). Conjectural beginning of human history (A. W. Wood, Trans.). In G. Zöller & R. B. Louden (Eds.), Anthropology, history, and education (pp. 163–175). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaufman, G. (1989). The psychology of shame. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ketelaar, T. (2015). Evolutionary psychology and emotion: A brief history. In V. Zeigler-Hill, L. L. M. Welling, & T. K. Shackelford (Eds.), Evolutionary perspectives on social psychology (pp. 51–68). Cham: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-28099-8_516-1.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kilborne, B. (2002). Disappearing persons: Shame and appearance. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kinston, W. (1983). A theoretical context for shame. International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 64(2), 213–226.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laing, R. D. (1959). The divided self. London: Tavistock.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lansky, M. (1987). Shame and domestic violence. In D. Nathanson (Ed.), The many faces of shame (pp. 335–362). New York: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • LeDoux, J. (1996). The emotional brain. The mysterious underpinnings of emotional life. New York/London/Toronto/Sydney: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, H. B. (1971). Shame and guilt in neurosis. New York: International Universities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, M. (1992). Shame: The exposed self. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, M. (2016). Self-conscious emotions: Embarassment, pride, shame, guilt, and hubris. In L. Feldman Barrett, M. Lewis, & J. M. Haviland-Jones (Eds.), Handbook of emotions (4th ed., pp. 792–814). New York/London: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd-Jones, H. (1971). The justice of Zeus. Berkeley/Los Angeles/London: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynd, H. (1985). On shame and the search for identity. New York: Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, W. (1980). Emotion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maurer, C. (2017). La Theorie des Gefühls hegeliana in dialogo con le recenti teorie sulle emozioni. Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia, 8(1), 30–46. https://doi.org/10.4453/rifp.2017.0003.

  • Mead, M. (1937). Cooperation and competition among primitive peoples. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mendes, W. B., & Park, J. (2014). Neurobiological concomitants of motivation states. In A. J. Elliot (Ed.), Advances in motivation science (pp. 233–270). Waltham: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moll, J., de Oliveira-Souza, R., Zahn, R., & Grafman, J. (2008). The cognitive neuroscience of moral emotions. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology: Vol. 3. The neuroscience of morality: Emotion, brain disorders, and development (pp. 1–17). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (2001). Upheavals of thought: The intelligence of emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (2004). Hiding from humanity. Disgust, shame, and the law. Princeton/Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parrott, W. G. (Ed.). (2014). The positive side of negative emotions. New York/London: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peperzak, A. (1987). Selbsterkenntnis des Absoluten. Grundlinien der Hegelschen Philosophie des Geistes. Stuttgart/Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pessoa, L. (2012). Beyond brain regions: Network perspective of cognition-emotion interaction. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 35(3), 158–159. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X11001567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petry, M. J. (1978). Hegel’s philosophy of subjective spirit (Vol. 1–2). Dordrecht/Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Piers, G., & Singer, M. (1953). Shame and guilt. Springfield: Thomas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plutchik, R. (1962). The emotions: Facts, theories, and a new model. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roeser, S. (2011). Moral emotions and intuitions. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rometsch, J. (2007). Hegels Theorie des erkennenden Subjekts. Systematische Untersuchungen zur enzyklopädischen Philosophie des subjektiven Geistes. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, A. O. (Ed.). (1980). Explaining emotions. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russon, J. (2009). Emotional subjects: Mood and articulation in Hegel’s philosophy of mind. International Philosophical Quarterly, 49(1), 41–52. https://doi.org/10.5840/ipq20094914.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schachter, S., & Singer, J. (1962). Cognitive, social and physiological determinants of emotional state. Psychological Review, 69(5), 379–399.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schimmenti, A. (2012). Unveiling the hidden self: Developmental trauma and pathological shame. Psychodynamic Practice, 18(2), 195–211. https://doi.org/10.1080/14753634.2012.664873.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sheff, T. J. (1987). The shame-rage spiral: A case study of an interminable quarrel. In H. B. Lewis (Ed.), The role of shame in symptom formation (pp. 109–149). Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheff, T. J., & Retzinger, S. M. (1991). Emotions and violence: Shame and rage in destructive conflicts. Lexington: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skeat, W. W. (2005). An etymological dictionary of the English language. Mineola: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, R. L., Webster, J. M., Parrott, G. W., & Eyre, H. L. (2002). The role of public exposure in moral and nonmoral shame and guilt. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 83(1), 138–159. https://doi.org/10.1037//0022-3514.83.1.138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snell, B. (1948). Die Entdeckung des Geistes. Studien zur Entstehung des europäischen Denkens bei den Griechen. Hamburg: Claassen & Goverts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. C. (1976). The passions: Emotions and the meaning of life. Garden City: Anchor Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. C., & Stone, L. D. (2002). On “positive” and “negative” emotions. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 32(4), 417–435. https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-5914.00196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, M. J. (1998). Breaking the chain of low self-esteem. Shorewood: Wolf Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, N., & Oatley, K. (1992). Basic emotions: Theory and measurement. Cognition and Emotion, 6(3–4), 161–168. https://doi.org/10.1080/02699939208411067.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tangney, J. P., & Dearing, R. L. (2002). Shame and guilt. New York/London: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tangney, J. P., & Fischer, K. W. (1995). Self-conscious emotions. The psychology of shame, guilt, embarrassment, and pride. New York/London: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tangney, J. P., & Tracy, J. L. (2012). Self-conscious emotions. In M. R. Leary & J. P. Tangney (Eds.), Handbook of self and identity (2nd ed., pp. 446–480). New York/London: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tangney, J. P., Stuewig, J., & Mashek, D. J. (2007). Moral emotions and moral behaviour. Annual Review of Psychology, 58, 345–373. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.psych.56.091103.070145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tappolet, C., Teroni, F., & Konzelmann Ziv, A. (Eds.). (2018). Shadows of the soul: Philosophical perspectives on negative emotions (pp. 105–112). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, G. (1985). Pride, shame and guilt: Emotions of self-assessment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomkins, S. S. (1962). Affect, imagery, and consciousness: Vol. 1. The positive affects. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomkins, S. S. (1963). Affect, imagery, and consciousness: Vol. 2. The negative affects. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tracy, J. L., Robins, R. W., & Tangney, J. P. (Eds.). (2007). The self-conscious emotions. Theory and research. New York/London: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1993). Shame and necessity. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wurmser, L. (1981). The mask of shame. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaborowski, R. (2013). On so-called negative emotions. Organon, 45, 137–152.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Maurer, C. (2021). Blushing with Shame: Toward a Hegelian Contribution on the Issue of the Positive Role of Negative Emotions. In: Giacomoni, P., Valentini, N., Dellantonio, S. (eds) The Dark Side: Philosophical Reflections on the “Negative Emotions”. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind, vol 25. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-55123-0_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics