Skip to main content

Our Emotional Cores

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Emotions as Original Existences
  • 227 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter I advance the idea that emotion lies at the core of self, by which I mean that emotions are those properties of ours that characterize our intrinsic properties or what we are like in and of ourselves, that is, when considered apart from the different ways we are disposed to behave. I begin by saying something about why the search for an object’s intrinsic nature is an important one. I then outline and motivate five criteria for something to count as an intrinsic property, as well as make some general observations regarding these five criteria. Next I consider a number of psychological states or properties, including beliefs, desires, and emotions, with a view to seeing which might be most suited to serve as intrinsic properties of ours. I will argue that only emotions, conceived of as non-intentional feeling states, meet the five criteria in question.

Ah, Dorian, how happy you are! What an exquisite life you have had! You have drunk deeply of everything. You have crushed the grapes against your palate. Nothing has been hidden from you. And it has all been to you no more than the sound of music. It has not marred you. You are still the same.

I am not the same, Henry.

—Oscar Wilde (1986, 245)

We are not necessarily thinking machines. We are feeling machines that think.

—Antonio Damasio (1994, 16)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Of course modern physics doesn’t characterize such things in terms of how they tend to appear to us, as such entities are too small to be perceptible to normal senses.

  2. 2.

    It is also of the nature of a disposition to relate its bearer to the triggering conditions (see Chap. 4). Thus, a vase is not merely disposed to shatter, but is disposed to shatter in the event of being struck with force.

  3. 3.

    Bertrand Russell writes: “The physical world is only as regards certain abstract features of its space-time structure—features which, because of their abstractness, do not suffice to show whether the physical world is, or is not, different in intrinsic character from the world of mind” (1948, 240).

  4. 4.

    William Seager writes: “One of the core intuitions about intrinsic properties is that they are the properties that things have ‘in themselves’, the properties that something would retain even if it was the only thing in the universe. If we add the premise that things can exist as the sole denizen of a world (in some appropriately weak modal form—that fact that I need oxygen to survive will not prevent me from having intrinsic properties) we have an argument against relationalism. Individuals can, on this view, be ‘pulled out’ of the relations they may find themselves in and exist entirely apart from them.” (2006, 11)

  5. 5.

    For similar reasons I disagree with Langton and Lewis’s definition of intrinsic property, according to which an intrinsic property is one that an object can possess independent of whether it is lonely or accompanied (Langton and Lewis 1998). An object bearing dispositional properties is independent of the object being lonely or accompanied (thus, an object can possess dispositional properties regardless of whether it is accompanied or lonely), but again such properties are not intrinsic properties.

  6. 6.

    One might query whether dispositions (or causal powers more generally) are relational only as they are represented by us (see e.g. Langton 2006). I think the way dispositions are to be defined rules that idea out. That it is of the nature of a disposition to relate an object to something external to the object is a fact about what dispositions are, and not merely a fact about how we think about dispositions.

  7. 7.

    See, for instance, the views expressed by some dementia carers who were interviewed by Julian Baggini (2011). Of one carer named Jill, Baggini writes: “Dementia took the lid of darker aspects of her mother’s personality. The balance was shifted within her existing personality; she did not acquire a completely new one. The evil looks and snide remarks were simply no longer repressed. Although her memory went along with her ability to recognise her daughter, in Jill’s view she was very much ‘still there’. Jill had no sense of a reduction or diminution of the self” (2011, 53–54). The view that dementia need not change people is one often held by people with dementia also (see e.g. MacRae 2010; Caddell and Clare 2012).

  8. 8.

    As Simon Blackburn writes of Gage and similar cases: “The reason for the inability to function normally…seems to be that these patients have lost any normal association between representing aspects of the situation, and the stable onset of the affect or emotion. Scenes which would excite positive or negative emotions in normal people may leave such patients entirely cold. They do not become excited at the prospect of gain, or fearful at the prospect of loss. In these emotional lives, everything has either disappeared, or at least become unstable.” (1998, 126)

References

  • Adams, R. (2007). Idealism Vindicated. In P. V. Inwagen & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Persons: Human and Divine (pp. 35–54). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baggini, J. (2011). The Ego Trick. What Does it Mean to be You? London: Granta Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S. (1998). Ruling Passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caddell, L., & Clare, L. (2012). Identity, Mood, and Quality of Life in People with Early-Stage Dementia. International Psychogeriatrics, 24, 1306–1315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2016). Panpsychism and Panprotopsychism. In G. Bruntrup & L. Jaskolla (Eds.), Pansychism: Contemporary Perspectives (pp. 19–47). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ Error. New York: Quill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, M. (1990). Relevant Predication 2: Intrinsic Properties and Internal Relations. Philosophical Studies, 60, 177–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Francescotti, R. (2014). Editor’s Introduction. In R. Francescotti (Ed.), Companion to Intrinsic Properties (pp. 1–16). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goff, P. (2017). Consciousness and Fundamental Reality. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harlow, J. (1868). Recovery from the Passage of an Iron Bar Through the Head. Publications of the Massachusetts Medical Society, 2, 320–347.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1982). Psychophysical Supervenience. Philosophical Studies, 41, 51–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kistler, M. (2011). Powerful Properties and the Causal Basis of Dispositions. In A. Bird, B. Ellis, & H. Sankey (Eds.), Properties, Powers and Structures. Issues in the Metaphysics of Realism (pp. 119–137). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R. (2006). Kant’s Phenomena: Extrinsic or Relational Properties? A Reply to Allais. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 73, 170–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R., & Lewis, D. (1998). Defining ‘Intrinsic’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58, 333–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacRae, H. (2010). Managing Identity While Living with Alzheimer’s Disease. Qualitative Health Research, 20, 293–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1948). Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W. (1995). Consciousness, Information, and Panpsychism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2, 272–288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W. (2006). The Intrinsic Nature Argument for Panpsychsim. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13, 129–145.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sprigge, T. (1999). Panpsychism. In The Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (1994). Mental Reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2003). Real Materialism. In L. Antony & N. Hornstein (Eds.), Chomsky and His Critics (pp. 49–88). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2006). Realistic Materialism: Why Physicalism Entails Panpsychism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13, 3–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Cleve, J. (2016). Problems from Reid. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilde, O. (1986). A Picture of Dorian Gray. London: Marshall Cavendish.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (1987). Sanity and the Metaphysics of Responsibility. In F. Schoeman (Ed.), Responsibility, Character, and the Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Demian Whiting .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Whiting, D. (2020). Our Emotional Cores. In: Emotions as Original Existences. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-54682-3_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics