Abstract
Opponents of the new mechanistic account of scientific explanation argue that the new mechanists are committed to a ‘More Details Are Better’ claim: adding details about the mechanism always improves an explanation. Due to this commitment, the mechanistic account cannot be descriptively adequate as actual scientific explanations usually leave out details about the mechanism. In reply to this objection, defenders of the new mechanistic account have highlighted that only adding relevant mechanistic details improves an explanation and that relevance is to be determined relative to the phenomenon-to-be-explained. Craver and Kaplan (B J Philos Sci 71:287–319, 2020) provide a thorough reply along these lines specifying that the phenomena at issue are contrasts. In this paper, we will discuss Craver and Kaplan’s reply. We will argue that it needs to be modified in order to avoid three problems, i.e., what we will call the Odd Ontology Problem, the Multiplication of Mechanisms Problem, and the Ontic Completeness Problem. However, even this modification is confronted with two challenges: First, it remains unclear how explanatory relevance is to be determined for contrastive explananda within the mechanistic framework. Second, it remains to be shown as to how the new mechanistic account can avoid what we will call the ‘Vertical More Details are Better’ objection. We will provide answers to both challenges.
Access this chapter
Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout
Purchases are for personal use only
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
- 1.
- 2.
Craver and Kaplan use the label ‘MDB_r’ (with an index). For our purposes, it is more convenient to use the label ‘MRDB’.
- 3.
Note that the mutual manipulability account is not a description about what should be a component of a mechanism for a given phenomenon but rather a recipe for determining what is a component of a mechanism for a given phenomenon.
- 4.
‘dogged’ → ‘fdogged’ → ‘frogged’ → ‘froggyd’ → ‘froggy’
- 5.
This criterion is equivalent to the one on p. 21 above. The edit distance from M to M* is 0 iff M and M* have the same constituents.
- 6.
Note that the question we are interested in differs from the question that Woodward answers with his account of conditional irrelevance. Our question is ‘When is an explanation improved by going down the mechanistic hierarchy?’ Woodward’s question is ‘When is a higher-level explanation better than or as good as a fundamental level explanation?’ Woodward’s perspective differs from ours in the sense that in his context it is commonly assumed that (i) there are different explanations at different levels (whereas we assume that there is one explanation that can extend over multiple levels), and (ii) that lowest-level explanations are by default the preferred ones (due to considerations of causal closure and exclusion). Based on these considerations, the question arises whether higher-level explanations can at least sometimes be better or at least as good as lowest-level explanations. Here, Woodward provides a convincing answer: a given higher-level explanation is at least as good as the lowest-level explanation if the lowest-level explanation is irrelevant for the explanandum conditional on the higher-level explanation. In the mechanistic picture, however, explanation is a top-down matter: while the first lower-level is clearly explanatorily relevant for the phenomenon (say, the activity of the hippocampus is clearly explanatorily relevant for spatial memory), the lowest level is clearly not (say, the interactions between quarks is clearly irrelevant for the explanation of spatial memory). The question, then, is where in the mechanistic hierarchy explanatory relevance stops.
References
Baetu, T. M. (2015). The completeness of mechanistic explanations. Philosophy of Science, 82, 775–786. https://doi.org/10.1086/683279.
Batterman, R. W., & Rice, C. C. (2014). Minimal model explanations. Philosophy of Science, 81, 349–376. https://doi.org/10.1086/676677.
Baumgartner, M., & Casini, L. (2017). An abductive theory of constitution. Philosophy of Science, 84, 214–233. https://doi.org/10.1086/690716.
Baumgartner, M., & Gebharter, A. (2016). Constitutive relevance, mutual manipulability, and fat-handedness. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 67, 731–756. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axv003.
Baumgartner, M., Casini, L., & Krickel, B. (2018). Horizontal Surgicality and mechanistic constitution. Erkenntnis. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0033-5.
Boone, W., & Piccinini, G. (2016). Mechanistic abstraction. Philosophy of Science, 83, 686–697. https://doi.org/10.1086/687855.
Bunke, H., & Shearer, K. (1998). A graph distance metric based on the maximal common subgraph. Pattern Recognition Letters, 19, 255–259. North-Holland. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0167-8655(97)00179-7.
Chirimuuta, M. (2014). Minimal models and canonical neural computations: The distinctness of computational explanation in neuroscience. Synthese, 191, 127–153. Springer Netherlands. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0369-y.
Cohen, W. W., Ravikumar, P., & Fienberg, S. E. (2003). A comparison of string metrics for matching names and records. In ACM international conference on Knowledge Discovery and Data Mining (KDD), Workshop on data cleaning, record linkage, and object consolidation, 2003, 3:73–78.
Craver, C. F. (2007a). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic Unity of neuroscience. New York: Oxford University Press.
Craver, C. F. (2007b). Constitutive explanatory relevance. Journal of Philosophical Research, 32, 1–20. https://doi.org/10.5840/jpr_2007_4.
Craver, C. F. (2016). The explanatory power of network models. Philosophy of Science, 83, 698–709. https://doi.org/10.1086/687856.
Craver, C. F., & Bechtel, W. (2007). Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biology and Philosophy, 22, 547–563. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-006-9028-8.
Craver, C. F., & Kaplan, D. M. (2020). Are more details better? On the norms of completeness for mechanistic explanations. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 71, 287–319. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axy015.
Damerau, F. J. (1964). A technique for computer detection and correction of spelling errors. Communications of the ACM, 7, 171–176. ACM. https://doi.org/10.1145/363958.363994.
Dretske, F. I. (1972). Contrastive statements. The Philosophical Review, 81, 411. https://doi.org/10.2307/2183886.
Glennan, S. (2017). The new mechanical philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Illari, P. M. K., & Williamson, J. (2011). Mechanisms are real and local. In In Causality in the Sciences (pp. 818–844). Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199574131.003.0038.
Illari, P. M. K., & Williamson, J. (2012). What is a mechanism? Thinking about mechanisms across the sciences. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2, 119–135. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-011-0038-2.
Kaiser, M. I., & Krickel, B. (2017). The metaphysics of constitutive mechanistic phenomena. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 68, 745–747. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axv058.
Kästner, L. (2017). Philosophy of cognitive neuroscience: Causal explanations, mechanisms and empirical manipulations. Berlin/Boston: De Gruyter.
Krickel, B. (2018a). The mechanical world (Studies in brain and mind) (Vol. 13). Cham: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-03629-4.
Krickel, B. (2018b). Saving the mutual manipulability account of constitutive relevance. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 68, 58–67. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2018.01.003.
Levenshtein, V. I. (1966). Binary codes capable of correcting deletions, insertions, and reversals. Soviet Physics Doklady, 10, 707–710. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1022689900470.
Levy, A. (2014). What was Hodgkin and Huxley’s achievement? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, 469–492. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axs043.
Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.
Miłkowski, M. (2016). Explanatory completeness and idealization in large brain simulations: A mechanistic perspective. Synthese, 193, 1457–1478. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0731-3.
Monge, A., & Elkan, C. (1997). An efficient domain-independent algorithm for detecting approximately duplicate database records. In The proceedings of the SIGMOD 1997 workshop on data mining and knowledge discovery.
Railton, P. A. (1980). Explaining explanation: A realist account of scientific explanation and understanding. Princeton University.
Rice, C. (2015). Moving beyond causes: Optimality models and scientific explanation. Nous, 49, 589–615. John Wiley & Sons, Ltd (10.1111). https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12042.
Romero, F. (2015). Why there isn’t inter-level causation in mechanisms. Synthese, 192, 3731–3755. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0718-0.
Wagner, R. A., & Fischer, M. J. (1974). The string-to-string correction problem. Journal of the ACM, 21, 168–173. https://doi.org/10.1145/321796.321811.
Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.
Woodward, J. (2013). Mechanistic explanation: Its scope and limits. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 87, 39–65. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8349.2013.00219.x.
Woodward, J. (2018). Explanatory autonomy: The role of proportionality, stability, and conditionalirrelevance. Synthese. Springer Netherlands: 1–29. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01998-6.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Editor information
Editors and Affiliations
Rights and permissions
Copyright information
© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG
About this chapter
Cite this chapter
Kohár, M., Krickel, B. (2021). Compare and Contrast: How to Assess the Completeness of Mechanistic Explanation. In: Calzavarini, F., Viola, M. (eds) Neural Mechanisms. Studies in Brain and Mind, vol 17. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-54092-0_17
Download citation
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-54092-0_17
Published:
Publisher Name: Springer, Cham
Print ISBN: 978-3-030-54091-3
Online ISBN: 978-3-030-54092-0
eBook Packages: Religion and PhilosophyPhilosophy and Religion (R0)