Skip to main content

Language, Truth and Logic and the Anglophone Reception of the Vienna Circle

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Historical and Philosophical Significance of Ayer’s Language, Truth and Logic

Part of the book series: History of Analytic Philosophy ((History of Analytic Philosophy))

Abstract

A.J. Ayer’s Language, Truth, and Logic had been responsible for introducing the Vienna Circle’s ideas, developed within a Germanophone framework, to an Anglophone readership. Inevitably, this migration from one context to another resulted in the alteration of some of the concepts being transmitted. Such alterations have served to facilitate a number of false impressions of Logical Empiricism from which recent scholarship still tries to recover. In this paper, I will attempt to point to the ways in which LTL has helped to foster the various mistaken stereotypes about Logical Empiricism which were combined into the received view. I will begin by examining Ayer’s all too brief presentation of an Anglocentric lineage for his ideas. This lineage, as we shall see, simply omits the major nineteenth century Germanophone influences on the rise of analytic philosophy. The Germanophone ideas he presents are selectively introduced into an Anglophone context and directed toward various concerns that arose within that context. I will focus on the differences between Carnap’s version of the overcoming of metaphysics, and Ayer’s reconfiguration into what he calls the elimination of metaphysics. Having discussed the above, I will very briefly outline the consequences that Ayer’s radicalization of the Vienna Circle’s doctrines had on the subsequent Anglophone reception of Logical Empiricism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This paper was first presented in 2018 at the conference on “The Historical and Philosophical Significance of Ayer’s Language, Truth and Logic” at the University of Pécs, organized by the MTA “Lendület Morals and Science” and the “Empiricism and atomism in twentieth-century Anglo-Saxon philosophy” Research Group. I owe many thanks to all those present, as well as to the anonymous reviewers, for many helpful questions and suggestions. I am particularly grateful to Adam Tamas Tuboly for inviting me to contribute to the conference and book, and for his many insightful comments and suggestions. All page references to Language, Truth and Logic below are to the second edition of 1946; see Ayer (1936/1946), noted in the text as “LTL.

  2. 2.

    For a detailed discussion of weaker versions of verificationism see Hans-Johann Glock’s chapter in this volume.

  3. 3.

    Susan Stebbing was also largely responsible for introducing the Vienna Circle’s ideas to British philosophers in her 1933 British Academy address; see Stebbing (1933); see also Siobhan Chapman’s discussion of Stebbing in her chapter of this volume.

  4. 4.

    In an interview from 1989, Ayer says that he “didn’t speak much German” at the time, and that “I couldn’t really take much part in their debates, but I understood what was going on” (Ayer and Honderich 1991, 209). This may at least partly account for his ignorance of the Germanophone context in which the Vienna Circle’s ideas were developed (see e.g. Carnap et al. 1929/1973). Nonetheless, in that same interview, more than 50 years after LTL was published, Ayer still discusses the obscurity of nonsensical German (and French) philosophy, as opposed to the clarity of English-speaking philosophy in the tradition of British Empiricism (Ayer and Honderich 1991, 212–213 and 225).

  5. 5.

    This may be compared with the acknowledgment section of his “Demonstration of the impossibility of metaphysics” from 1934, where he simply says that his views are not original, but clearer versions of those developed by Schlick et al. (Ayer 1934a, 335).

  6. 6.

    According to Ayer, Ryle instructed him to spend his honeymoon in Vienna in 1933 (rather than go to Cambridge to attend Wittgenstein’s lectures); see Ayer and Honderich (1991, 209).

  7. 7.

    Ayer (1936) also presented a British lineage for Logical Empiricism at the International Congress for Scientific Philosophy in Paris in 1935. (Here, he carefully distinguishes between two directions in British philosophy, the Moorean account of directive analysis which Stebbing (1933) employs in her criticism of the Vienna Circle, and his own Russellian defense of their position.)

  8. 8.

    By 1936, a number of Vienna and Berlin Circle members had already started publishing articles in English, for example Kurt Grelling (1928), Otto Neurath (1931/1983), Moritz Schlick (1931/1979, 1932/1979, 1935/1979), Blumberg and Feigl (1931), Rudolf Carnap (1934a, b, 1936–7), Herbert Feigl (1934), Carl G. Hempel (1934), and Juhos (1935) Furthermore, a number of Anglophone discussions of logical positivism had already been available, for example, Susan K. Langer (1930), Sidney Hook (1930), Helen Knight (1931) (which surveys, apart from new works of Neo-Scholasticism and Phenomenology, the first issue of Erkenntnis, and summarizes three articles by Schlick, Carnap, Reichenbach, and Waismann); E.B. Ginsburg (1932), Ernest Nagel (1932, 1934), Stebbing (1933), Walter S. Gamertsfelder (1933), Victor F. Lenzen (1933), John Dewey (1934), and W.V.O. Quine (1935).

  9. 9.

    An overview of the contemporary Anglophone presentations of Logical Empiricism, including, apart from Ayer, Stebbing, and Nagel, the work of Charles Morris, is given in Pincock (forthcoming). (Of these, I will not consider Morris’ book since it was published after Ayer’s.) An even earlier stage in the Anglophone reception of Logical Empiricism is described in Verhaegh (2020).

  10. 10.

    Weinberg (1936) also covers a lot of the material that Ayer omitted, but was only published, after LTL.

  11. 11.

    Of course there are continuities between early modern and Logical Empiricism; see for example Krisztián Pete’s chapter on the connections between Ayer and Berkley’s non-cognitivism.

  12. 12.

    In 1931 Reichenbach offers a similar presentation of his stance as a “triumph” of both Rationalism and Empiricism; see Reichenbach (1931/1978).

  13. 13.

    See also Tuboly (2017, 46–53) where he argues that the Vienna Circle’s members themselves also underplayed Frege’s influence.

  14. 14.

    Stebbing’s (1930) A Modern Introduction to Logic was an attempt to rectify this; she acknowledges Frege’s significance (40, 129, 132, 181, 213, 442, 459, 486–487), but places Russell’s work center-stage.

  15. 15.

    Frege is discussed by Linke (1926), Grelling (1928, 100), and by Black (1933).

  16. 16.

    He does note that Tarski, who is vaguely in the line of influence of Brentano, “developed a deductive theory of syntax or metalogic several years before Carnap’s publications on this topic” (Nagel 1936b, 50).

  17. 17.

    The French conventionalists had a significant influence on the Vienna Circle, especially Neurath; see for example Haller (1979/1991) and Uebel (1997). Anglophone sources available to Ayer that mention at least the name of Poincare as an influence on Logical Empiricism include Neurath (1931/1983, 48) and Gamertsfelder (1933, 108).

  18. 18.

    See Ayer et al. (1936); see also Giannoni (1971, 75–76), Ben-Menahem (2006, 13–14). In the first edition of LTL he argues that analytic propositions “simply record our determination to use words in a certain fashion” (LTL, 84), but he differentiates this in the second edition of LTL (17).

  19. 19.

    Though Kant is not directly referenced, his treatment of metaphysics may be what Carnap has in mind when he talks of metaphysics as “uncertain, on the ground that its problems transcend the limits of human knowledge” (Carnap 1932/1959, 60).

  20. 20.

    See the chapter of László Kocsis in this volume.

  21. 21.

    See also Uebel (2007, 334). For more detail on some of the ways in which Ayer is involved in ongoing debates within the Vienna Circle, see Thomas Uebel’s chapter in the volume.

  22. 22.

    Ayer elsewhere (“Demonstration of the impossibility of metaphysics”) addresses this distinction by explaining that, like Carnap, he considers that “questions about the meaning of a concept reduce themselves to questions about the meanings of […] the simplest proposition in which it can significantly occur” (1934a, 337). The absence of such an account in LTL could simply be an omission on Ayer’s behalf or it could signal Ayer’s distancing himself from Carnap’s account (though resolving this question would require going beyond the bounds of this inquiry).

  23. 23.

    Ayer (1934a, 338, 342) also sees that there may be an attempt to convey emotion behind some nonsensical sequence of words.

  24. 24.

    While later in LTL Ayer resists this conclusion, Ayer (1934a, 342) had briefly restated Carnap’s point about metaphysics being the result of a “desire also to express their feelings about the world. Literature and the arts afford the most satisfactory medium for such expression.”

  25. 25.

    The dialogue begins as a response to Richards (1924) in Mace (1934a). Ayer replied in Ayer (1934b), to which Mace responded in Mace (1934b).

  26. 26.

    As noted above, Ayer’s “Demonstration of the impossibility of metaphysics,” published a month later in July 1934, also cites Carnap’s article, as well as Schlick, as the sources of its arguments.

  27. 27.

    Furthermore, Ayer had different targets and motivations than the Vienna Circle; see Vrahimis (2013a).

  28. 28.

    The list of continental philosophers to whom he responded includes not only Heidegger but also, among others, Husserl, Sartre, and Merleau-Ponty; see Vrahimis (2013a, b).

References

  • Ayer, Alfred J. 1934a. Demonstration of the Impossibility of Metaphysics. Mind 43 (171): 335–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1934b. The Genesis of Metaphysics. Analysis 1 (4): 55–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1936. The Analytic Movement in Contemporary British Philosophy. In Actes du Congrès international de philosophie scientifique, facs. VIII, Historie de la logique et de la philosophie scientifique, 53–59. Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1936/1946. Language, Truth and Logic. 2nd ed. London: Victor Gollancz.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1987. Reflections on Language, Truth, and Logic. In Logical Positivism in Perspective: Essays on Language, Truth, and Logic, ed. Barry Gower, 23–34. London/Sydney: Groom Helm.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, Alfred J., and Ted Honderich. 1991. An Interview with A.J. Ayer. In A.J. Ayer: Memorial Essays, ed. Phillips Griffiths, 209–226. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, Alfred J., C.H. Whiteley, and Max Black. 1936. Truth by Convention: A Symposium. Analysis 4 (2/3): 17–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Menahem, Yemima. 2006. Conventionalism: From Poincare to Quine. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Black, Max. 1933. The Nature of Mathematics: A Critical Survey. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, and Trubner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumberg, Albert E., and Herbert Feigl. 1931. Logical Positivism: A New Movement in European Philosophy. The Journal of Philosophy 17: 281–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, Rudolf. 1932/1959. The Elimination of Metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of Language. In Logical Positivism, ed. A.J. Ayer, 60–81. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1934a. Meaning, Assertion and Proposal. Philosophy of Science 1 (3): 359–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1934b. The Unity of Science. Trans. Max Black. London: K. Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co. Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1936–7. Testability and Meaning. Philosophy of Science 3 (4): 419–471 & 4 (1): 1–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, Rudolf, Hans Hahn, and Otto Neurath. 1929/1973. The Scientific Conception of the World: The Vienna Circle. In Empiricism and Sociology, ed. Marie Neurath and Robert S. Cohen, 299–318. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahms, Hans-Joachim. 1994. Positivismusstreit, Die Auseinandersetzung der Frankfurter Schule mit dem logischen Positivismus, dem amerikanischen Pragmatismus und dem kritischen Rationalismus. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Neue Sachlichkeit in the Architecture and Philosophy of the 1920s. In Carnap Brought Home: The View from Jena, ed. Steve Awodey and Carsten Klein, 357–376. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damböck, Christian. 2020, forthcoming. (Dis-)Similarities: Remarks on ‘Austrian’ and ‘German’ Philosophy in the 19th Century. In Franz Brentano and Austrian Philosophy, ed. Denis Fisette, Guillaume Fréchette, and Friedrich Stadler. Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, John. 1934. Meaning, Assertion and Proposal. Philosophy of Science 1 (2): 237–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, Herbert. 1934. Logical Analysis of the Psychophysical Problem: A Contribution of the New Positivism. Philosophy of Science 1 (4): 420–445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Michael. 2000. A Parting of Ways: Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger. La Salle/Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gamertsfelder, Walter S. 1933. Current Skepticism of Metaphysics. The Monist 43 (1): 105–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giannoni, Carlo Borromeo. 1971. Conventionalism in Logic: A Study in the Linguistic Foundation of Logical Reasoning. The Hague: Mouton.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ginsburg, E.B. 1932. On the Logical Positivism of the Viennese Circle. The Journal of Philosophy 29 (5): 121–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grelling, Kurt. 1928. Philosophy of the Exact Sciences: Its Present Status in Germany. The Monist 38 (1): 97–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haller, Rudolf. 1979/1991. On Otto Neurath. In Rediscovering the Forgotten Vienna Circle. Austrian Studies on Otto Neurath and the Vienna Circle, ed. Thomas Uebel, 25–32. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1986/1991. On the Historiography of Austrian Philosophy. In Rediscovering the Forgotten Vienna Circle. Austrian Studies on Otto Neurath and the Vienna Circle, ed. Thomas Uebel, 41–50. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl G. 1934. On the Logical Positivists’ Theory of Truth. Analysis 2 (4): 49–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hook, Sidney. 1930. A Personal Impression of Contemporary German Philosophy. The Journal of Philosophy 27 (6): 141–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horkheimer, Max. 1982. The Latest Attack on Metaphysics. In Critical Theory: Selected Essays, 132–187. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Juhos, Béla. 1935. Empiricism and Physicalism. Analysis 2 (6): 81–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knight, Helen. 1931. Philosophy in Germany. Journal of Philosophical Studies 5 (17): 105–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langer, Susan K. 1930. Review: Reichenbach’s Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre. The Journal of Philosophy 27 (22): 609–611.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lenzen, Victor F. 1933. Review: Atom and Cosmos by Hans Reichenbach. The Journal of Philosophy 30 (14): 390–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Linke, Paul F. 1926. The Present Status of Logic and Epistemology in Germany. The Monist 36 (2): 222–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loeb, Louis. 1981. From Descartes to Hume: Continental Metaphysics and the Development of Modern Philosophy. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longworth, Guy. 2009. Rationalism and Empiricism. In Key Ideas in Linguistics and the Philosophy of Language, ed. Siobhan Chapman and C. Routledge, 67–74. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mace, C.A. 1934a. Representation and Expression. Analysis 1 (3): 33–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1934b. Metaphysics and Emotive Language. Analysis 2 (1/2): 6–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, Ernest. 1932. Review: Das Unendliche in der Mathematik und seine Ausschaltung by F. Kaufmann. The Journal of Philosophy 29 (15): 401–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1934. Verifiability, Truth, and Verification. The Journal of Philosophy 31 (6): 141–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1936a. Impressions and Appraisals of Analytic Philosophy in Europe, I. The Journal of Philosophy 33 (1): 5–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1936b. Impressions and Appraisals of Analytic Philosophy in Europe, II. The Journal of Philosophy 33 (2): 29–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, Otto. 1931/1983. Physicalism: The Philosophy of the Viennese Circle. In Otto Neurath: Philosophical Papers, 1913–1946, ed. Marie Neurath and Robert Cohen, 48–51. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, D.F. 1981. The Myth of British Empiricism. History of European Ideas 1: 331–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neil, John, and Thomas Uebel. 2004. Horkheimer and Neurath: Restarting a Disrupted Debate. European Journal of Philosophy 12 (1): 75–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, Christopher. forthcoming. Logical Empiricism in the Anglophone World. In Routledge Handbook of Logical Empiricism, ed. Thomas Uebel and Christoph Limbeck-Lilienau. New York/London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. 1935. Review of Logische Syntax der Sprache by Rudolf Carnap. Philosophical Review 44 (4): 394–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, Hans. 1931/1978. Aims and Methods of Modern Philosophy of Nature. In Hans Reichenbach: Selected Writings 1909–1953, ed. Maria Reichenbach and Robert S. Cohen, vol. 1, 359–388. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, I.A. 1924. Principles of Literary Criticism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, Alan. 1990. How Not to Russell Carnap’s Aufbau. PSA 1990: Proceedings of the 1990 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1: 3–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rock, Tina. 2017. Brentano’s Methodology as a Path Through the Divide: On Combining Phenomenological Descriptions and Logical Analysis. Axiomathes 27 (5): 475–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand. 1903. The Principles of Mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sachs, Carl B. 2011. What Is to Be Overcome? Nietzsche, Carnap, and Modernism as the Overcoming of Metaphysics. History of Philosophy Quarterly 28 (3): 303–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, Moritz. 1931/1979. The Future of Philosophy. In Moritz Schlick: Philosophical Papers Volume II (1925–1936), ed. Henk Mulder and Barbara F.B. van de Velde-Schlick, 210–224. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1932/1979. A New Philosophy of Experience. In Moritz Schlick: Philosophical Papers Volume II (1925–1936), ed. Henk Mulder and Barbara F.B. van de Velde-Schlick, 225–237. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1935/1979. Facts and Propositions. In Moritz Schlick: Philosophical Papers Volume II (1925–1936), ed. Henk Mulder and Barbara F.B. van de Velde-Schlick, 400–404. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Barry. 1997. The Neurath-Haller Thesis: Austria and the Rise of Scientific Philosophy. In Austrian Philosophy Past and Present, ed. Keith Lehrer and Johann Christian Marek, 1–20. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stebbing, L. Susan. 1930. A Modern Introduction to Logic. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1933. Logical Positivism and Analysis. Proceedings of the British Academy 19: 53–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuboly, Adam Tamas. 2017. The Limits and Basis of Logical Tolerance: Carnap’s Combination of Russell and Wittgenstein. In Bertrand Russell’s Life and Legacy, ed. Peter Stone, 45–72. Wilmington: Vernon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, Thomas. 1997. From the Duhem Thesis to the Neurath Principle. In Austrian Philosophy Past and Present, ed. Keith Lehrer and Johann Christian Marek, 87–100. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Empiricism at the Crossroads: The Vienna Circle’s Protocol-Sentence Debate Revisited. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verhaegh, Sander. 2020. The American Reception of Logical Positivism: First Encounters (1929–1932). HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 10 (1): 106–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vrahimis, Andreas. 2013a. “Was There a Sun Before Men Existed?”: A.J. Ayer and French Philosophy in the Fifties. Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 1 (9).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013b. Encounters Between Analytic and Continental Philosophy. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2018. The Brentano School and the History of Analytic Philosophy: Reply to Röck. Axiomathes 28 (3): 363–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020. Scientism, Social Praxis, and Overcoming Metaphysics: A Debate Between Logical Empiricism and the Frankfurt School. HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 10 (2).

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, Julius R. 1936. An Examination of Logical Positivism. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wisdom, John. 1931. Interpretation and Analysis in Relation to Bentham’s Theory of Definition. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Vrahimis, A. (2021). Language, Truth and Logic and the Anglophone Reception of the Vienna Circle. In: Tuboly, A.T. (eds) The Historical and Philosophical Significance of Ayer’s Language, Truth and Logic. History of Analytic Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-50884-5_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics