Skip to main content

Devitt and the Case for Narrow Meaning

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Language and Reality from a Naturalistic Perspective

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 142))

  • 227 Accesses

Abstract

In the late 1970s, Jerry Fodor, Hilary Putnam and Stephen Stich argued that the intentional content of most mental states is “wide,” i.e., does not supervene on the physical makeup of the subject’s head at a time. But many (including Fodor himself) have since argued that underlying the ordinary wide contents there must also be distinct, narrow ones. In “A Narrow Representational Theory of the Mind,” Michael Devitt defends the claim that the laws of mental processes as investigated by cognitive psychology should advert only to the narrow properties of representations, though some of those properties will be meaning properties specified by conceptual role, and that the scientifically appropriate boundary for explaining the behavior of an organism is its skin. But in Coming to Our Senses he repudiates that doctrine, because he has come to accept that widely characterized behavior is a more appropriate explanandum for psychology than behavior narrowly characterized.

This paper argues that there are narrow meanings, on the model of Kaplan’s notion of “character,” but (agreeing with Devitt) we have seen no reason to believe that there are narrow contents underlying ordinary wide ones.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    As we shall see, Devitt (1996) starts with a general concept of “semantic role,” and develops a notion of mental “meaning” from it. “Narrow meaning,” as he will prefer to call it, is rightly broader than narrow content as just defined.

  2. 2.

    Coming: “Psychological laws should advert to properties of tokens that are only syntactic” (1996: 264).

  3. 3.

    And he does not contest the argument up till that point. In Coming he will.

  4. 4.

    Notice that two different notions are expressed in these last two sentences, that do not necessarily coincide: internal functional roles, of the sort that would be codified in a Lewisian (1972) Ramsey sentence, and mathematical functions from external causes to wide referential meanings. “Function” as between those two is a pun, not that Devitt is confused as between the two meanings of the word.

  5. 5.

    Devitt does not consider Fodor’s (1980) argument from opacity. To expound and criticize that elusive argument would have taken a separate paper.

  6. 6.

    Coming: “Psychological laws should advert to properties of tokens that are only narrow semantic” (1996: 275). Devitt adds, “This should be read as a commitment to laws that advert to properties that are not syntactic, for example, to narrow word meanings.”

  7. 7.

    Fodor (1987) went on to repair the defect by arguing independently that for scientific purposes, states and events must be individuated by their causal powers. Devitt addresses this in a footnote (1989: 395–396 n. 29), but here again he is not convinced; he glimpses the objection that he will address at the end of the paper (see below), and that in Coming will disabuse him of the argument entirely. Wilson (1995: ch. 2) demolishes the argument from causal powers on its own terms.

    Still another version of the argument is the plain appeal to Twin Earth: If I and Twin Bill are molecular duplicates and so exactly alike in our heads, then necessarily (ignoring quantum randomness) we will behave in exactly the same way. That version too will succumb to the later objection just mentioned.

  8. 8.

    Of course no two human beings are ever functionally identical in reality, but Devitt points out (391) that all we need is functional similarity in the respects relevant to the situation in question.

  9. 9.

    Notoriously, in episode 22 (1970) of “Monty Python’s Flying Circus,” the Pythons scabrously lampooned Australian philosophers, and in that sketch pretended (very humorously, I admit) that every Ozzie philosopher is named Bruce. When I first arrived at Sydney University I had looked forward to learning what motivated that particular trope, but to my disappointment the real Australian philosophers did not know either, as ‘Bruce’ was not a conspicuously common name. It must be remembered, though, that in the sketch, the new member of the department at the University of Woolloomooloo, “a chap from pommie land,” was named Michael, though with a made-up surname.

    • Fourth Bruce: Michael Baldwin – this is Bruce. Michael Baldwin – this is Bruce. Michael Baldwin – this is Bruce.

    • First Bruce: Is your name not Bruce, then?

    • Michael: No, it’s Michael.

    • Second Bruce: That’s going to cause a little confusion .

    • Third Bruce: Mind if we call you ‘Bruce’ to keep it clear?

  10. 10.

    Which belief, I’m bound to say, would be ludicrously false.

  11. 11.

    This can lead to confusion, as it does on, e.g., p. 288.

    On pp. 157–158 he notes a few assumptions he makes regarding the relation between thought content and linguistic meaning: (1) thoughts as specified by “that”-clauses and the corresponding verbal utterances have the same meanings. (2) Thought meanings should be given “a certain explanatory priority” (italics original). (3) À la Grice, a linguistic utterance’s conventional meaning “is explained in terms of regularities in speaker meanings.” [Very strong disagreement from me on that one.] Nonetheless (4) conventional linguistic meanings play a role in the determination of particular thought meanings.

  12. 12.

    Just how complicated is brilliantly illustrated by the main examples in Rosenberg (1994), particular that of Gracie and “Barbara Cartwright” (135ff). Rosenberg intends some of his cases as counterexamples to Devitt’s (1981) analysis.

  13. 13.

    Block (1986), a functional-role theorist, acknowledges this as a significant problem.

  14. 14.

    What of a proper functionalism instead of a pallid causal theory? There are teleosemantics all ready to work, such as Millikan’s (1984, 1989). But teleological properties are wide. At least, the most promising theories of teleology are either backward-looking or forward-looking in time.

  15. 15.

    Devitt also suggests (1996: 295–296) that if a narrow property were to predict proper intentional objects of behavior, it would be as near as matters to a Kaplanian character, and so return us to our first view of narrow meanings.

  16. 16.

    And put to evil uses, but let us draw a veil.

  17. 17.

    Subsequently, Jackson and Chalmers themselves (2001) backed off the idea that A-intensions correspond to public linguistic meanings or types of meaning analogous to Kaplanian characters. They did kick A-intensions upstairs and diffusely so, into individual minds at particular times.

  18. 18.

    Pautz (2013) offers a good critical survey of the “Research Program.”

    Nicholas Georgalis (2006, 2015) similarly defends a notion, “minimal content,” that is available only from the first-person perspective and is more fundamental than (indeed an absolute prerequisite for) ordinary wide content. It is determined by the subject’s conceptions and intentions, and differs from Horgan’s phenomenal intentionality (Georgalis says) by not individuating contents according to phenomenology in the “what it’s like” sense. My problem with Georgalis’ view is that according to it, only mental states of which the subject is aware can be intentional at all; states of which the subject is unaware do not have even derived intentionality. Georgalis not only accepts that consequence but insists that it is an important truth. But if, like me, you think that being aware of a mental state you’re in and being unaware of it is typically just a superficial matter of attention, you will not be persuaded that that difference creates such an ontological gulf.

References

  • Baker, L.R. 1986. Just what do we have in mind? In Midwest studies in philosophy, 10: Studies in the philosophy of mind, ed. P.A. French, T.E. Uehling, and H.K. Wettstein, 25–48. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1995. Explaining attitudes: A practical approach to the mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N.J. 1986. Advertisement for a semantics for psychology. In Midwest studies in philosophy, 10: Studies in the philosophy of mind, ed. P.A. French, T.E. Uehling, and H.K. Wettstein, 615–678. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990. Inverted earth. In Philosophical perspectives, 4: Action theory and philosophy of mind, ed. J.E. Tomberlin, 53–79. Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Mental paint and mental latex. In Philosophical issues, 7: Perception, ed. E. Villanueva, 19–49. Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. 1986. Individualism and psychology. Philosophical Review 95: 3–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. 1996. The conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M., and L. Humberstone. 1980. Two notions of necessity. Philosophical Studies 38: 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. 1981. Designation. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. A narrow representational theory of the mind. In Representation: Readings in the philosophy of psychological representation, ed. S. Silvers, 369–402. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Reprinted in Mind and cognition, ed. W.G. Lycan, 371–398. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1991. Page references are to this edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1991. Why Fodor can’t have it both ways. In Meaning in mind: Fodor and his critics, ed. B. Loewer and G. Rey. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Coming to our senses. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Referred to in the text as Coming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M., and K. Sterelny. 1987. Language and reality: An introduction to the philosophy of language. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. 1973. The causal theory of names. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 47: 187–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.A. 1980. Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: 63–73. Reprinted in J.A. Fodor, Representations: Philosophical essays on the foundations of cognitive science, 225–253 and 330–331. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press, 1981. Page references are to this edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1987. Psychosemantics. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Georgalis, N. 2006. The primacy of the subjective: Foundations for a unified theory of mind and language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Mind, language, and subjectivity: Minimal content and the theory of thought. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. 2000, June. Narrow content and the phenomenology of intentionality. Presidential Address to the Society for Philosophy and Psychology. New York City.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., and G. Graham. 2012. Phenomenal intentionality and content determinacy. In Prospects for meaning, ed. R. Schantz, 321–344. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., and J. Tienson. 2002. The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality. In Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings, ed. D. Chalmers, 520–533. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. 1994. Armchair metaphysics. In Philosophy in mind, ed. J. O’Leary-Hawthorne and M. Michael, 23–42. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishing.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. From metaphysics to ethics: A defence of conceptual analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F., and D. Chalmers. 2001. Conceptual analysis and reductive explanation. Philosophical Review 110: 315–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. 1979. On the logic of demonstratives. In Contemporary perspectives in the philosophy of language, ed. P.A. French, T.E. Uehling, and H.K. Wettstein, 401–412. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. 2007. Intentional inexistence and phenomenal intentionality. In Philosophical perspectives, 21: Philosophy of mind, ed. J. Hawthorne, vol. 21, 307–340. Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———., ed. 2013a. Phenomenal intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013b. The phenomenal intentionality research program. In Phenomenal intentionality, ed. U. Kriegel, 1–26. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D.K. 1972. Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50: 249–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loar, B. 1987. Subjective intentionality. Philosophical Topics 15: 89–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Phenomenal intentionality as the basis of mental content. In Reflections and replies: Essays on the philosophy of Tyler Burge, ed. M. Hahn and B. Ramberg, 229–257. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W.G. 1996. Consciousness and experience. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. The case for phenomenal externalism. In Philosophical perspectives, 15: Metaphysics, ed. J.E. Tomberlin, 17–35. Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006a, December. Consumer semantics to the rescue. Presented in a symposium in honor of Distinguished Woman Philosopher Award recipient Ruth Garrett Millikan, Society of Women Philosophers.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006b. The meaning of ‘water’: An unsolved problem. In Philosophical issues, 16: Philosophy of language, ed. E. Sosa and E. Villanueva, 184–199. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Phenomenal intentionalities. American Philosophical Quarterly 45: 233–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R.G. 1984. Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. Biosemantics. Journal of Philosophy 86: 281–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pautz, A. 2013. Does phenomenology ground mental content? In Phenomenal intentionality, ed. U. Kriegel, 194–234. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1975. The meaning of “meaning”. In Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, 7: Language, mind and knowledge, ed. K. Gunderson, 131–193. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, J.F. 1994. Beyond formalism: Naming and necessity for human beings. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S.P. 1978. Autonomous psychology and the belief-desire thesis. The Monist 61: 573–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1980. Paying the price for methodological solipsism. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: 97–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, S. 1982. Partial character and the language of thought. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 63: 347–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R.A. 1995. Cartesian psychology and physical minds. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to William G. Lycan .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Lycan, W.G. (2020). Devitt and the Case for Narrow Meaning. In: Bianchi, A. (eds) Language and Reality from a Naturalistic Perspective. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 142. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-47641-0_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics