Skip to main content

Phenomenological Approaches to Physics: Mapping the Field

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Phenomenological Approaches to Physics

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 429))

Abstract

Much ink has been spilled over the interrelations between philosophy and physics in the late nineteenth and early twentieth century as well as over the emergence of philosophy of science as an autonomous philosophical sub-discipline. Although our understanding of these issues is certainly more nuanced today than it was only a couple of years ago, more work needs to be done in order to arrive at an adequate picture of the intricate relations between philosophy and physics on the one hand and of how philosophical reflections on the physical sciences evolved during the last century on the other. This volume addresses one of the remaining blind spots, namely the role of phenomenology in the development of twentieth century (philosophy of) physics. In this introductory chapter, we shed light on the characteristics and historical development of phenomenological approaches to physics, indicate how current debates in philosophy of physics could benefit from phenomenological approaches, and provide summaries of the individual chapters.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Cf., for more detailed introductions to phenomenological philosophy, e.g. Smith (2007), Luft and Overgaard (2012) or Zahavi (2012). The relations between phenomenology and (philosophy of) science are discussed in Kockelmans and Kisiel (1970), Feist (2004), Gutting (2005) or Hyder and Rheinberger (2010).

  2. 2.

    For more details on Husserl’s epistemology and his conception of experiential justification, cf. Berghofer (2018a, 2019). For how Husserl’s approach can enrich current debates in epistemology, cf. Berghofer (2018c).

  3. 3.

    It should be mentioned, however, that such an apparently clear distinction between the empirical sciences and phenomenology would be blurred if the first-person perspective were incorporated to the natural sciences. For instance, there are trends in current experimental psychology that explicitly argue for incorporating the first-person perspective into science, emphasizing the significance of Husserlian phenomenology. One such proposal is Liliana Albertazzi’s “experimental phenomenology” (cf. Albertazzi, 2013). As we will see, some phenomenologists, such as Merleau-Ponty, believe that the incorporation of subjectivity is even possible in physics.

  4. 4.

    Cf., for detailed information concerning the personal relationship between Husserl and Weyl, Ryckman (2005b, chapter 5).

  5. 5.

    Although there have been critical voices as well (Ihde 2011), Husserl’s interpretation of Galilean science had a strong impact on several Galileo scholars, especially on the French historian of science Alexandre Koyré. Cf., for a discussion of the relationship between Husserl and Koyré, Parker (2017).

  6. 6.

    For an excellent analysis of the historical origins of gauge theory as well as an overview of its role in string theory, cf. O’Raifeartaigh and Straumann (2000).

  7. 7.

    Cf., for discussions of Merleau-Ponty’s views on the exact sciences, e.g. Kisiel (1970), Rouse (1986), Matherne (2018), and Romdenh-Romluc (2018).

  8. 8.

    Merleau-Ponty adopts this terminology from the French physicist and logician Paulette Destouches-Février. Below we see in more detail how strongly Merleau-Ponty was influenced by Destouches-Février. For a portrayal and further development of the approaches of Destouches-Février and her husband Jean-Louis Destouches, cf. Bitbol (1998, 2001).

  9. 9.

    Unfortunately, the fact that Merleau-Ponty is quoting Destouches-Février here is easily overlooked in the English translation because the quotation marks are missing (Merleau-Ponty 2003, 98).

  10. 10.

    For instance, readers familiar with Husserl’s oeuvre will not fail to notice Weyl’s allusion to section 49 of Ideas I: The notion of the “coordinate system as the necessary residue of the ego-extinction” is, of course, a reference to Husserl’s thought experiment of the “absolute consciousness as the residue of the annihilation of the world” (Husserl 1983, section 49). Moreover, it interesting to note that the trained mathematician Husserl also explicitly refers to the “origin of the coordinate system” (Husserl, 1973c, 116; our translation) in order to elucidate the role of the embodied subject in our cognitive engagements with the world.

References

  • Albertazzi, L. (2013). Experimental phenomenology: An introduction. In L. Albertazzi (Ed.), Handbook of experimental phenomenology. Visual perception of shape, space and appearance (pp. 1–36). Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Babich, B. (2016). Hermeneutic philosophy of science: Interpreting nature, reading laboratory science. In N. Keane & C. Lawn (Eds.), The Blackwell companion to hermeneutics (pp. 492–504). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, O. (1973). Beiträge zur phänomenologischen Begründung der Geometrie und ihrer physikalischen Anwendung. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belousek, D. W. (1998). Husserl on scientific method and conceptual change: A realist appraisal. Synthese, 115, 71–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berghofer, P. (2017). Transcendental phenomenology and unobservable entities. Perspectives, 7(1), 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berghofer, P. (2018a). Husserl’s conception of experiential justification: What it is and why it matters. Husserl Studies, 34(2), 145–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berghofer, P. (2018b). Ontic structural realism and quantum field theory: Are there intrinsic properties at the most fundamental level of reality? Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 62, 176–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berghofer, P. (2018c). Towards a phenomenological conception of experiential justfication. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1744-5.

  • Berghofer, P. (2018d). Why Husserl’s universal empiricism is a moderate rationalism. Axiomathes, 28, 539–563.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berghofer, P. (2019). On the nature and systematic role of evidence: Husserl as a proponent of metalist evidentialism? European Journal of Philosophy, 27(1), 8–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berghofer, P., & Wiltsche, H. (2019). Phänomenologie. In M. Grajner & G. Melchior (Eds.), Handbuch Erkenntnistheorie (pp. 35–42). J.B. Stuttgart: Metzler.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bitbol, M. (1998). Some steps towards a transcendental deduction of quantum mechanics. Philosophia Naturalis, 35, 253–280.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bitbol, M. (2001). Jean-Louis destouches: théories de le prévision et individualité. Philosophia Scientiae, 5(1), 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1998). In defense of pure reason. A rationalist account of a priori justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (2002). The logical syntax of language. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. (1999). The paradox of subjectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowell, S. (2001). Husserl, Heidegger, and the space of meaning. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • da Silva, J. J. (Ed.) (2017). Mathematics and its applications. A transcendental-idealist perspective. Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feist, R. (Ed.) (2004). Husserl and the sciences. Ottawa: University of Ottawa Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (2002). A phenomenological solution to the measurement problem? Husserl and foundations of quantum mechanics. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 33, 467–491.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, C. (2017). On participatory realism. In I. Durham & D. Rickels (Eds.), Information and interaction (pp. 113–134). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gavroglu, K. (1995). Fritz London: A scientific biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glazebrook, T. (2000). Heidegger’s philosophy of science. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glazebrook, T. (Ed.) (2012). Heidegger on science. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glock, H.-J. (2015). Neo-Kantianism and analytic philosophy. In N. D. Warren & A. Staiti (Eds.), New approaches to Neo-Kantianism (pp. 59–81). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gutting, G. (1978). Husserl and scientific realism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 39(1), 42–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gutting, G. (Ed.) (2005). Continental philosophy of science. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardy, L. (2013). Nature’s suit. Husserl’s phenomenological philosophy and the physical sciences. Athens: Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartimo, M. (2018). Husserl’s scientific context 1917–1938, a look into Husserl’s private library. The new yearbook for phenomenology and phenomenological philosophy, 16 (pp. 335–355).

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, C. W. (1986). Husserl and the problem of theoretical entities. Synthese, 66, 291–309.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, C. W. (1989). Husserl’s phenomenology and the foundations of natural science. Athens: Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heelan, P. (1983). Space-perception and the philosophy of science. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1967). What is a thing? South Bend: Gateway Editions.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1968). What is called thinking? New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1971). Poetry, language, thought. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1978). Frühe Schriften. Gesamtausgabe Band 1. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1997). Plato’s sophist. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2002). Off the beaten track. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1960). Cartesian meditations. An introduction to phenomenology. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1969). Formal and transcendental logic. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1970). The crisis of the European sciences and transcendental phenomenology. An introduction to phenomenological philosophy. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1971). “Phenomenology”, Edmund Husserl’s article for the encyclopedia Brittanica (1927): New complete translation by Richard E. Palmer. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 2, 77–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1973a). Experience and judgment. Investigations in a genealogy of logic. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1973b). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Dritter Teil: 1925–1935. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1973c). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Erster Teil: 1905–1920. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1973d). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Zweiter Teil: 1921–1928. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1983). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy. First book: General introduction to a pure phenomenology. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1989). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy. Second book: Studies in the phenomenology of constitution. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1997). Thing and space: Lectures of 1907. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2000). Londoner Vorträge. Husserl Studies, 16, 183–254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001a). Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis: Lectures on transcendental logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001b). Logical investigations. Volume 1. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001c). Logical investigations. Volume 2. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2002). Einleitung in die Philosophie. Vorlesungen 1922/23. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2008). Introduction to logic and theory of knowledge. Lectures 1906/07. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyder, D., & Rheinberger, H. (Eds.) (2010). Science and the life-world. Essays on Husserl’s crisis of the European sciences. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihde, D. (1991). Instrumental realism. The interface between philosophy of science and philosophy of technology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihde, D. (2011). Husserl’s Galileo needed a telescope! Philosophy of Technology, 24, 69–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jammer, M. (1974). The philosophy of quantum mechanics. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kisiel, T. J. (1970). Merelau-Ponty on philosophy and science. In J. J. Kockelmans & T. J. Kisiel (Eds.), Phenomenology and the natural sciences (pp. 251–273). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kockelmans, J. J. (1966). Phenomenology of the physical sciences. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kockelmans, J. J. (1970a). The era of the world-as-picture. In J. J. Kockelmans & T. J. Kisiel (Eds.), Phenomenology and the natural sciences (pp. 184–201). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kockelmans, J. J. (1970b). Heidegger on the essential difference and necessary relationship between philosophy and science. In J. J. Kockelmans & T. J. Kisiel (Eds.), Phenomenology and the natural sciences (pp. 147–166). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kockelmans, J. J. (1985). Heidegger and science. Washington: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kockelmans, J. J., & Kisiel, T. J. (Eds.) (1970). Phenomenology and the natural sciences. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2016). Structural realism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, winter 2016 ed.

    Google Scholar 

  • London, F., & Bauer, E. (1983). The theory of observation in quantum mechanics. In J. A. Wheeler & W. H. Zurek (Eds.), Quantum theory and measurement (pp. 217–259). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luft, S., & Overgaard, S. (Eds.) (2012). The Routledge companion to phenomenology. New York/London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matherne, S. (2018). Merleau-Ponty on abstract thought in mathematics and natural science. European Journal of Philosophy, 26(2), 780–797.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meixner, U. (2010). Husserls transzendentaler Idealismus als Supervenienzthese. Ein interner Realismus. In M. Frank & N. Weidtmann (Eds.), Husserl und die Philosophie des Geistes (pp. 178–208). Frankfurt am Main: Surhkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968). The visible and the invisible. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2003). Nature. Course notes from the Collège de France. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran, D. (2012). Husserl’s crisis of the European sciences and transcendental phenomenology: An introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mormann, T. (1991). Husserl’s philosophy of science and the semantic approach. Philosophy of Science, 58(1), 61–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Raifeartaigh, L. (1997). The dawning of Gauge theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Raifeartaigh, L., & Straumann, N. (2000). Gauge theory: Historical origins and some modern developments. Review of Modern Physics, 72(1), 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parker, R. K. B. (2017). The history between Koyré and Husserl. In R. Pisano, J. Agassi, & D. Drozdova (Eds.), Hypotheses and perspectives in the history and philosophy of science (pp. 243–276). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietersma, H. (2000). Phenomenological epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (2002). The logic of scientific discovery. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds, J. (2018). Phenomenology, naturalism and science: A hybrid and heretical proposal. New York/London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, A. (2006). “The Fact of Science” and critique of knowledge: Exact science as problem and resource in Marburg Neo-Kantianism. In M. Friedman & A. Nordmann (Eds.), The Kantian legacy in nineteenth-century science (pp. 211–226). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romdenh-Romluc, K. (2018). Science in Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology. In D. Zahavi (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the history of phenomenology (pp. 340–359). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. (1986). Merleau-Ponty and the existential conception of science. Synthese, 66(2), 249–272.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. (1987). Husserlian phenomenology and scientific realism. Philosophy of Science, 54, 222–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. (2005). Heidegger on science and naturalism. In G. Gutting (Ed.), Continental philosophy of science (pp. 123–141). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryckman, T. (2005a). Recovering first philosophy in philosophy of physics. Philosophy Today, 49, 13–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryckman, T. (2005b). The reign of relativity. Philosophy in physics 1915–1925. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1991). Philosophy and the scientific image of man. In Science, perception and reality (pp. 1–37). Ridgeview: Alascadero.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B. (1994). Austrian philosophy. The legacy of Franz Brentano. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. D. (2003). Husserl and the cartesian meditations. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, D. W. (2007). Husserl. New York/London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soffer, G. (1990). Phenomenology and scientific realism: Husserl’s critique of Galileo. Review of Metaphysics, 44, 67–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ströker, E. (1997). The Husserlian foundations of science. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vallor, S. (2009). The pregnancy of the real: A phenomenological defense of experimental realism. Inquiry, 52(1), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Webb, D. (2009). Heidegger, ethics, and the practice of ontology. London/New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. (1923). Gravitation and electricity. In A. Einstein, H. A. Lorentz, H. Weyl, & H. Minkowski (Eds.), The principle of relativity (pp. 199–216). New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. (1949). Philosophy of mathematics and natural science. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiltsche, H. A. (2012). What is wrong With Husserl’s scientific anti-realism? Inquiry, 55(2), 105–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiltsche, H. A. (2016). Mechanics lost: Husserl’s Galileo and Ihde’s telescope. Husserl Studies, 32(2), 149–173.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiltsche, H. A. (2017). Science, realism, and correlationism. A phenomenological critique of Meillassoux’ argument from ancestrality. European Journal for Philosophy, 25(3), 808–832.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiltsche, H. A. (2019). Models, science, and intersubjectivity. In F. Kjosavik, C. Beyer, & C. Fricke (Eds.), Husserl’s phenomenology of intersubjectivity. Historical interpretations and contemporary applications (pp. 339–358). New York/London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winther, R. G. (2016). The structure of scientific theories. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, winter 2016 edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2001). Husserl and transcendental intersubjectivity. A response to the linguistic-pragmatic critique. Athens: Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2003). Phenomenology and metaphysics. In D. Zahavi, S. Heinämaa, & H. Ruin (Eds.), Metaphysics, facticity, interpretation (pp. 3–22). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2010). Husserl and the “Absolute”. In C. Ierna, H. Jacobs, & F. Mattens (Eds.), Metaphysics, facticity, interpretation (pp. 71–92). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (Ed.) (2012). The Oxford handbook of contemporary phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The majority of the chapters in this volume were initially presented at the conference “Phenomenological Approaches to Physics,” which we organized at the University of Graz in June 2018. We would like to thank the participants who made the conference a truly memorable event. Special thanks are also due to Otávio Bueno, the editor of the Synthese Library series, to Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl, the head of the working unit “Phenomenology” at the University of Graz, and to Springer’s project coordinator Palani Murugesan. Finally, we would like to thank our families for emotional support, and the Austrian Research Fund (FWF) for a generous grant to carry out a research project on Hermann Weyl’s phenomenological philosophy of physics (project number: P31758).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Harald A. Wiltsche .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Berghofer, P., Wiltsche, H.A. (2020). Phenomenological Approaches to Physics: Mapping the Field. In: Wiltsche, H.A., Berghofer, P. (eds) Phenomenological Approaches to Physics. Synthese Library, vol 429. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-46973-3_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics