Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Nordic Wittgenstein Studies ((volume 6))

  • 173 Accesses

Abstract

In his political philosophy, Peter Winch was pursuing two themes, one of which is more explicit and more conventional than the other. His first theme was the critique of classical social contract theory. His second theme is best characterised as the primacy of agency over spectatorship. This long-term philosophical commitment is distinct from another central theme for Winch, his emphasis on particular cases. In ethics and politics, the perspective of agency implies understanding how an individual may be ‘called to agency’ by some course of events.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    On Rawls, see Winch (1989, 184–185, 187). Today certain applications of game theory to political philosophy would look like an obvious target of Winch’s criticism. This is, however, not a theme that Winch discussed.

  2. 2.

    In his notes for ‘Intercollegiate Lectures on Political Philosophy’ (1969–70, 3) Winch includes a mention of ‘the craving for particularity’. Lynette Reid informs me that Winch is repeating a joke that Gerald Cohen (who participated in the lectures) made about him.

  3. 3.

    As Winch’s discussion (1992b, Lecture 9) brings out, this paradox is particularly pressing for Hobbes because of his specific view on human motivation: his determinism, his causalist view on action and his logical hedonism.

  4. 4.

    Winch’s main criticism of Locke’s subsequent development of contract theory is that, rather than solving the problem, he brushes it under the carpet.

  5. 5.

    One conclusion from Wittgenstein would be that, in a sense, it is easier to refute the statement that the world is less than five million years old than that it is less than 150 years old. Engaging with the first statement mobilises all the resources of geology and genetics, while the latter statement implies utter scepticism about those very resources.

  6. 6.

    As pointed out by Reid (2017).

  7. 7.

    For a related discussion, see Lagerspetz 2015, 145–146.

  8. 8.

    Reid 2017, 11. Italicisation added.

  9. 9.

    Elsewhere in his work, Wittgenstein frequently offers mechanical training as a model for teaching language or specific rule following activities – admittedly always in stylized illustrations of specific activities and not as a general model for learning. See, for instance, Wittgenstein 1960, p. 77; Wittgenstein 1953, §§ 5–6, 157.

  10. 10.

    Winch avoids the term ‘re-enactment’, partly because he goes along with the then (1958) usual misconception of re-enactment as psychological Einfühlung and not, as Collingwood would have it, a critical reconstruction of past reasoning along with the historically contingent conditions of its meaningfulness (see Winch 1958/1990, 132). That view is no longer held among Collingwood scholars (D’Oro and Connelly 2015).

  11. 11.

    ‘Man and Society in Hobbes and Rousseau’, included in (Winch 1972a, 90–109).

  12. 12.

    The conclusion Winch draws here is, firstly, that any moral agent is committed, by pain of inconsistency, to treating all similar cases (including his own) in the same way – unless of course he has changed his mind in the meanwhile. This view is widely shared among moral philosophers. His second conclusion is not so. He argues that the moral agent is not similarly committed to thinking that other moral agents, looking at the same cases, would have to arrive at the same judgments as he has.

  13. 13.

    E.g. Winch (1972a, 62; 108; 1987, 162–163)

  14. 14.

    The temporal reading of his argument would face the obvious objection that it might be empirically refuted. Is it obvious, for instance, that we need first-hand experience of a murder case before we can judge that murder is wrong?

  15. 15.

    See also Winch 1989 and Winch’s translation of Weil 1987.

  16. 16.

    See my paper Lagerspetz 2019.

  17. 17.

    Winch (1972a), 3, 68; Winch ([1958] 1990), 123; Winch 1957.

  18. 18.

    Cf. Winch 1969–70, 3: ‘It would be dangerous to assume that there is any one problem which all political philosophers have been concerned with. Even if one uses a formula which could be thought to cover the enquiries and difficulties of many different philosophers, there is the real possibility that different men have been troubled about the problem in different ways and hence have different kinds of requirement about what would constitute a satisfactory solution. This being said I am going to ignore the danger for the time being and talk about what I do think is in a way the fundamental problem in political philosophy’ (italicization added).

  19. 19.

    Parts of this paper were presented at the Centre of Ethics at the University of Pardubice, 4 May 2018 and at the conference Keeping it Honest. Vulnerable Writing, 22–23 August 2019, Uppsala University (conference hosted by Engaging Vulnerability and organized in collaboration with the Nordic Wittgenstein Society). The paper was presented again at Philosophy Research Seminar, Åbo Akademi University, 9 September 2019. Thanks to the participants and others for comments and discussions – especially, but not exclusively, to Jonas Ahlskog, Michael Campbell, Martin Gustafsson, Lars Hertzberg, Markus Kortesmäki, Camilla Kronqvist, Lynette Reid and Björn Vikström.

References

  • Beran, O. (2018). “Give me an example”: Peter Winch and learning from the particular. Nordic Wittgenstein Review, 7, 49–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collingwood, R. G. (1939). An autobiography. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Oro, G., & Connelly, J. (2015). Robin George Collingwood. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/collingwood/

  • Hardt, M., & Negri, A. (2001). Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hardwig, J. (1991). The role of trust in knowledge. The Journal of Philosophy, 88, 693–708.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Havel, V. (1990). The power of the powerless. In J. Vladislav (Ed.), Living in Truth (pp. 36–122). London: Faber & Faber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, T. (1651/1981). Leviathan. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1970). Of the original contract. In A. MacIntyre (Ed.), Hume’s Ethical Writings (pp. 255–273). London: Collier-Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagerspetz, O. (2015). Trust, Ethics and Human Reason. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagerspetz, O. (2019). Peter Winch on “Aristotelian” and “Socratic” reasoning. Philosophical Investigations, 42, 146–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reid, L. (2017). Peter Winch on political and epistemic authority, Manuscript draft, presented at Philosophy research seminar at Åbo Akademi University, 4 September 2017 and at Peter Winch conference – truth in politics and metaphysics at King’s College London, 30 June to 2 July 2017.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, C. (2009). Wittgenstein and Political Theory. The View from Somewhere. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weil, S. (1987). The legitimacy of the provisional government (P. Winch, Trans.). Philosophical Investigations, 53, 87–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1957). The universities and the state. Higher Education Quarterly, XII, 14–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1958/1990). The Idea of a Social Science and its Relation to Philosophy. 2nd ed. London: Routledge/Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1969–1970). Intercollegiate lectures in political philosophy. [Typescript; lecture notes; 16 pp]. Peter Winch Archives (GB 0100 KCLCA K/PP171, Box 14). King’s College London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1972a). Ethics and Action. London: Routledge/Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1972b). Authority and rationality. The Human World, 8, 11–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1987). Trying to Make Sense. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1989). Simone Weil: The Just Balance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P., ed. Lagerspetz, O. (1990). Seminars on authority, The University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign. Notes by O. Lagerspetz, MS, 39 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1990). Introduction. In I. Maclean, A. Montefiore, & P. Winch (Eds.), The Political Responsibility of Intellectuals (pp. 1–16). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1991a). Certainty and authority. In A. P. Griffiths (Ed.), Wittgenstein Centenary Essays (pp. 223–238). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1991b). Persuasion and reason. [Typescript of a lecture delivered at Brooklyn College; 20 pp.] Peter Winch Archives (GB 0100 KCLCA K/PP171, Box 28), Kings College, London. (Shared with students at Illinois and Abo.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1992a). Persuasion. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 17, 123–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1992b). Philosophy of law and the state [Computer printout; lecture notes; 61 pp.]. Peter Winch Archives (GB 0100 KCLCA K/PP171, Box 16). King’s College London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1993). Political authority. [Computer printout; seminar notes; 24 pp.]. Peter Winch Archives (GB 0100 KCLCA K/PP171, Box 16). King’s College London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1997). Can We Understand Ourselves? Philosophical Investigations, 20, 193–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (2002). How is political authority possible? D. Z. Phillips (Ed.). Philosophical Investigations, 25, 20–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (n.d. [mid-1990s]). Authority, consent, and practical reason [Computer print-out outline for a book]. Peter Winch Archives (GB 0100 KCLCA K/PP171, Box 16), Kings College, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1960). The Blue and Brown Books (Second ed.). New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1972). On Certainty. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Olli Lagerspetz .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Lagerspetz, O. (2020). Political Philosophy and the Primacy of Agency. In: Campbell, M., Reid, L. (eds) Ethics, Society and Politics: Themes from the Philosophy of Peter Winch. Nordic Wittgenstein Studies, vol 6. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-40742-1_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics