Skip to main content

Researching Education: Perspectives from Winch’s Approach to the Social Sciences

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Ethics, Society and Politics: Themes from the Philosophy of Peter Winch

Part of the book series: Nordic Wittgenstein Studies ((volume 6))

  • 168 Accesses

Abstract

Peter Winch’s claim that the province of social science is one of philosophical as well as empirical enquiry is examined using education as an extended example. On Winch’s view, understanding a social institution or practice involves a grasp of its conceptual structure and this itself should be the subject of empirical investigation. Winch’s own criticism of his earlier position is compared with Rush Rhees’s critique of the Builders example in Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations (1958/1967). Language games are not to be considered in isolation but as part of a society consisting of interconnected practices that taken together make sense. Education as a family of preparatory human practices is considered as an integral part of a society and, drawing on Vico, the complexity of education’s role in society is considered. The implications of this complexity for a conceptual investigation of education is outlined and a distinction is drawn between the concept of education and various operative conceptions which are the province of the empirical as well as the normative researcher. This approach to the study of education is illustrated through an extended example and the possibilities for an empirical investigation of education are considered.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    As is well-known, the English term ‘science’ has connotations of experimental enquiries concerning natural phenomena, whereas the German ‘Wissenschaft’ is a more hold-all term encompassing all kinds of systematic enquiry aiming at knowledge. The term ‘Wissenschaft’, when substituted for ‘science’ already makes Winch’s claim sound much less controversial.

  2. 2.

    Adam Smith makes this crucial move in Bk 1 of the Wealth of Nations (1776/1981). Moving from the relatively uncontroversial suggestion that we always act from our (perceived) interests in matters economic, he equates this with the more controversial claim that we thus act out of self-love in such matters (pp. 26–27), despite his friend David Hume cautioning against such an interpretation ‘Of the Dignity and Meanness of Human Nature’ (Hume 1741/2008).

  3. 3.

    The dispute between Walther von Stolzing and Hans Sachs in Act 3 of Wagner’s ‘Die Meistersingers’, expresses this conflict, and Wagner gives due weight to both sides.

  4. 4.

    See the discussion in (Reid 1987)

  5. 5.

    Space does not allow me to develop this example further. It concerns the assessment of the quality of the writing of young children. In this case we have a genuinely contested concept, and perhaps a considerable degree of confusion as to how to resolve it. It is difficult to frame an investigation into a practice if the investigators cannot determine their own framing concepts for the investigation because of radical disagreements within their own culture about what the practice involves. The interested reader should look at the references to Barrow and Woods (1974), Howe (1990), Best (1992), Gingell (2001) and Reid (1987) in the bibliography to follow this issue up.

  6. 6.

    This could be considered as a ‘hinge’ proposition and one might wonder about its universal scope (Dromm 2018). I am not here concerned about its status as a putative hinge proposition and merely suggest that it is hard to make sense of any human society without taking account of biological parameters. This does not imply that it is straightforward to just ‘read off’ the non-categorial contingent manifestations of categorial concepts simply by treating them as a kind of deduction from those concepts or by covertly importing non-categorial content into the categorial concepts.

  7. 7.

    The role of conflict receives explicit recognition in the 1990 Introduction to ISS.

  8. 8.

    One rarely remarked on consequence of such perspectivalism is that what one group may regard as a worthwhile life for another is not recognised as a worthwhile life for them. Vico was aware of such conflicts of perception.

  9. 9.

    This is not to imply that all children are inculcated into every societal practice, which would be absurd. But it does imply that they are inculcated into those practices that make a human life possible, even if, for some, that life is more restricted than that of others.

  10. 10.

    See Everett (2008) on the child-rearing practices of the Piraha. When we come across examples like this, we can better understand what Winch meant when he said that any worthwhile philosophy involves the study of society. We are alerted to different ways of living and gain a better understanding of such concepts as initiation, trust, obedience and understanding as a result.

  11. 11.

    See Rousseau’s comments in Emile on the need for Emile to have a life partner, Sophie (Rousseau 1762/1968, 465).

  12. 12.

    We can add here that the Germanophone Bildungsroman literary tradition takes seriously the idea that self-knowledge is not available to one just because one is an adult, but must be painfully acquired through experiences, often of occupational engagement and romantic attachment. See for example the novels of Keller, Goethe, Lenz, and many others, in particular Goethe (1790/1980).

  13. 13.

    Plato (2016) ‘The Laws’ Bk 1, 644 onwards for a very strong statement of a moral view of education as opposed to training. I do not mean to exclude of course that members of a particular group can disagree amongst themselves about what form of education is appropriate for their own children.

  14. 14.

    If we cannot do this then it is difficult to make sense of those who reject a certain educational practice. If one fails to take account of what unwilling participants in an educational practice think about what is an adequate preparation for them and fail to relate it to what they consider to be important, for example their local labour market and its associated form of life, then one is unlikely to see that their behaviour has any point. (see Willis 1977) Learning to Labour for an example. If one thinks of fiction as a form of telling lies, then one is unlikely to see the point of storytelling for children (see Ways with Words, Brice-Heath 1983). Needless to say, such examples illustrate how it is possible for educators to misunderstand the beliefs and practices of those with whom they deal within their own society.

  15. 15.

    Arguably, the earlier work of Basil Bernstein (1973) on social class and language use tried to do this. It failed to gather the data that would validate the thesis however, and subsequent work has not supported Bernstein’s empirical claims.

  16. 16.

    As Winch points out, our own confusions may lie deep and may need to be brought to the surface, perhaps by a process of dialectic, as he demonstrates how Socrates attempts to show Polus what his opinion really is (Winch 1990, pp. 98–100 – the discussion is of the dialogue between Socrates and Polus in the Republic).

  17. 17.

    Some might say that it is about job rather than occupational preparation, but I will not deal with that complication now as it is not particularly relevant to the discussion.

  18. 18.

    See Glick (2015) for an outline of some of the complications of this position and Pavese (2015) for an attempt to resolve them.

  19. 19.

    It should, however, be noted how rich and complex Ryle’s examples often are, ranging over fishing, chess playing, surgery, archery and courtroom oratory. Stanley and Williamson focus on riding a bicycle. Later work deals with games like basketball (Stanley and Williamson 2017).

  20. 20.

    This does not imply that problem solving is some kind of generic ability.

  21. 21.

    And also, to an extent in Austria and Germanophone Switzerland.

  22. 22.

    Contested because some (especially on the trade union side of social partnership arrangements) would insist on a reflective element in this broad capacity, while others might see it as of little or no importance.

  23. 23.

    Cf. Kerschensteiner (1906/1968) for an articulation of this concept of work, which bears some resemblance to Marx’s non-alienated labour.

  24. 24.

    I owe this example to my colleague, Dr. Bernadette O’Neill.

  25. 25.

    See the prevalence of talk in Germany about ‘soft skills’.

  26. 26.

    Sometimes this is difficult, even in practices with which we are superficially familiar as Winch (1997) argued. We sometimes cannot find our feet with these practices. Winch does not elaborate, but it is reasonable to suggest that the spontaneous and affective reactions that demonstrate their importance for their participants may elude us. But can we gain some inkling of this importance? A football fan (to use Winch’s example) identifies, not just with the team, but with what the team represents, a community united in a common endeavour. And that is something that (it is to be hoped) we should all be able to understand.

  27. 27.

    As in the case of the Germanic conception of know-how discussed above.

References

  • Barrow, R., & Woods, R. (1974). An Introduction to Philosophy of Education. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G. (1993/1964). Human Capital: A Theoretical and Empirical analysis, with Special Reference to Education (3rd ed.). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benner, D. (2003). Wilhelm von Humboldt’s Bildungstheorie. Weinheim and Munich: Juventa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Best, D. (1992). The Rationality of Feeling. Understanding the Arts in Education. Brighton: Falmer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, B. (1973). Class, Codes and Control (Vol. 1). London: Paladin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brice-Heath, S. (1983). Ways with Words. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dromm, K. (2018). The difficulties with groundlessness. Philosophical Investigations, 41(4), 418–435.

    Google Scholar 

  • Everett, D. (2008). Don’t Sleep, there are Snakes. London: Profile Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallie, W. B. (1955-6). Essentially contested concepts. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56, 167–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gingell, J. G. (2001). Against creativity. Irish Educational Studies, 20(1), 33–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glick, E. (2015). Practical modes of presentation. Nous, 49(3), 538–559.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goethe, J. (1796/1980). Wilhelm Meister’s Lehrjahre. Frankfurt am Main: Fischer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haldane, J. (1989). Metaphysics in the philosophy of education. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 23(2), 171–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanf, G. (2010). The changing relevance of the Beruf. In M. Brockmann, L. Clarke, G. Hanf, P. Mehaut, A. Westerhuis, & C. Winch (Eds.), Knowledge, Skills and Competence in the European Labour Market. What’s in a Qualification? (pp. 50–67). Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howe, M. J. (1990). The Origins of Exceptional Abilities. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1741/2008). Of the dignity and meanness of human nature. In S. Copley & A. Edgar (Eds.), Selected Essays of David Hume (pp. 43–48). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kerschensteiner, G. (1906/1968). Produktiver Arbeit und ihr Erziehungswert. In T. Rutt (Ed.), Ausgewählte Pädagogische Texte (Band 2) (pp. 6–25). Paderborn: Ferdinand Schöningh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, G. (2018). Meaning for radical contextualists: Travis and Gadamer on why words matter. Philosophical Investigations, 41(1), 22–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orchard, L., & Stretton, H. (1994). Public Good, Public Choice and Public Enterprise. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2015). Practical senses. Philosopher’s Imprint, 15(29), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, R. S. (1981). Democratic values and educational aims. In Essays on Educators (pp. 32–52). London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (2016). The Laws. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reid, I. (Ed.). (1987). The Place of Genre in Learning: Current debates. Geelong: Typereader Press, Deakin University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rhees, R. (1959-60). Wittgenstein’s builders. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 60, 171–186.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richter, D. (2018). Winch on understanding other people. Philosophical Investigations, 41(4), 399–417.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, J.-J. (1762/1968). Émile ou de l’Education. Paris: Flammarion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1946/1971). Knowing how and knowing that. In Collected Papers (Vol. 2, pp. 212–225). New York: Barnes and Nobles.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1979). On Thinking. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (1776/1981). The Wealth of Nations. Indianapolis: Liberty Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. Journal of Philosophy, 48(8), 411–444.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2017). Skill. Nous, 51(4), 713–726.

    Google Scholar 

  • Streeck, W. (1992). Social Institutions and Economic Performance. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Streeck, W. (2011). Skills and Politics: General and Specific. Cologne: Max Planck Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vico, G. (1744/1968). The New Science of Giambattista Vico (revised translation of 3rd ed., T. G. Bergin & M. H. Fisch Trans.). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Willis, P. (1977). Learning to Labour. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1958/1990). The Idea of a Social Science (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1964/1972). Understanding a primitive society. In Ethics and Action (pp. 8–48). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1972). Ethics and Action. London: Routledge Kegan Paul

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1990). Einheit: Voraussetzung oder Forderung? In O. Marquard (Ed.), Einheit und Vielheit: Proceedings of the XIV German Congress of Philosophy – Giessen, 21–26 September, 1987 (pp. 94–100). Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1997). Can we understand ourselves? Philosophical Investigations, 20(3), 193–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958/1967). Philosophical Investigations (3rd ed. G. E. M. Anscombe & G. H. Von Wright Eds., G. E. M. Anscombe Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On Certainty (G. E. M. Anscombe & G. H. Von Wright Eds., D. Paul & G. E. M. Anscombe Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christopher Winch .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Winch, C. (2020). Researching Education: Perspectives from Winch’s Approach to the Social Sciences. In: Campbell, M., Reid, L. (eds) Ethics, Society and Politics: Themes from the Philosophy of Peter Winch. Nordic Wittgenstein Studies, vol 6. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-40742-1_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics