Skip to main content

Between the Logic of Life and the Anti-logic of Death: Reflections on Suicidality in the Wake of Jean Améry

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Jean Améry
  • 524 Accesses

Abstract

Over the last century, suicidal thoughts have usually been examined under the magnifying glass of psychologists, psychiatrists, and moralists, as a pathological phenomenon of misjudgment or failure of judgment abilities. This approach, according to Jean Améry (1912–1978), is subordinate to the logic of life, while the suicidal mind is altered by the anti-logic of death. What is the anti-logic of death? Is it a logic at all? What is its relation to death and to voluntary death? This chapter aims to investigate the meaning of the anti-logic of death and its role in Améry’s line of reasoning. I argue that a proper understanding of the role of anti-logic uncovers the way in which Améry’s reasoning is aimed to expose the absurd rebellion embodied by voluntary death.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    All references refer to the above text unless otherwise stated.

  2. 2.

    The book form of On Suicide, based on a series of radio broadcasts which was delivered by Améry in 1976, after an unsuccessful suicide attempt two years earlier (1974). Two years later (1978), Améry succeeded to accomplish his Voluntary death.

  3. 3.

    As much as my offered exegetic might indicate the need for a re-examination of some liberal beliefs in regard to freedom, autonomy, and rationality, I will not address these issues directly here, for my aim in this chapter is to clarify Améry’s anti-logic of death and indicate its applicability to the current philosophical study of suicidality.

  4. 4.

    As Gallagher points out, “one does not have to know or be aware of this brain processes and an ecologically embedded body, in order to have an experience that still counts as a self-experience” (2000, p. 15). I am aware of the fact that I am using Gallagher’s terms (minimal and narrative self) quite tolerantly, yet I think it could be useful for the sake of the argument that I am attempting to posit. As far as it might turn out to be a valuable question later on, I am not getting to the question of whether the minimal self is bound (still implicitly perhaps) in the most basic sense with interpersonal relations or not (see for example: Zahavi, D. 2007, 2017; Brinck, I., Reddy, V., & Zahavi, D. 2017), for it seems that Améry himself is undecided on the matter (e.g., pp. 59–122 regarding the question of undeniable belonging vs. existential loneliness).

  5. 5.

    By Ontological Vulnerability, I refer namely to the first of the three sources in the taxonomy developed by Mackenzie et al. (2014): inherent vulnerability, which is ‘intrinsic to the human condition’; situational vulnerability, which is ‘context specific’; and finally, pathogenic vulnerability, which stems from abuse, oppression, and injustice. These sources may appear according to Mackenzie et al. in two states: dispositional vulnerability and occurrent vulnerability (pp. 7–9).

  6. 6.

    See Baier (1991, 1995), Ratcliffe, M., (2009, 2013) and Bernstein (2011).

  7. 7.

    By using the word Construct, I refer to the sense of agency as a conceptual entity, an explanatory variable, which is not directly observable and whose existence depends upon the subject’s mind. In other words, it is a psycho-subjective (personal as well as collective) interpretation of physical objects in the world.

  8. 8.

    This superficial definition will suffice at the moment for the sake of my argument, but it is important to note that there is a rich field of writing that seeks to philosophically analyze and define death. For further reading, see Bradley, Feldman, and Johansson (eds., 2013) and Luper (2009). It is also needless to say that there are of course philosophical traditions that undermine this assumption (for example, Buddhist reincarnation, or to a certain extent, the religious concept of paradise).

  9. 9.

    Death as such, in its inaccessibility, is an anonymous death and, therefore, it opposes the Heideggerian concept of death as one’s own possibility or as Dasein’s authentic existence. To some extent, it mirrors Maurice Blanchot’s conception of death as it appears in The Space of Literature (1982).

  10. 10.

    See: Baier (1991) and Bernstein (2011).

  11. 11.

    Although there are different definitions and interpretations of the absurd, I will refer here the to the absurd mostly as it characterized by Camus (1955) and Nagel (1971)—a kind of necessary relationship between people and the world resulting from the ‘act of attention’ (Camus 1955, p. 43) or intentionality.

  12. 12.

    See Wittgenstein, L. (1958 Part II, §xi).

  13. 13.

    That is why ‘reality’, for Améry, is always a human reality that is dynamic and influenced by the relationship of interdependence between the subject and the other. It follows that any self-determination regarding ‘being’ is impossible: ‘It is what it is not and is not what it is’ (Sartre 1992, p. 112).

  14. 14.

    However, there are two reservations that should be noted in this context: (1) the vast majority of Pessimists aim to eventually find reasons to oppose suicide. Some, like Schopenhauer and Rousseau, come to a solution of celibacy and reduction, while others like Camus offer more involved solutions, sometimes even political (see Dienstag 2009, p. 103); and (2) for the most part, Améry’s own voluntary death is attributable more to his notion of human freedom and less to pessimism. Nonetheless, as my analysis suggests, it seems plausible that it is the latter that produces the former.

  15. 15.

    Échec is the French equivalent of “check” in the game of Chess. That is the declaration of a defeat that can put an end to the game. However, in the context that Améry uses it, this is a declaration of self-defeat. Therefore, Améry’s emphasis of Échec is decided upon by the subject and not by society, although it is the second authority that may ‘Define the condition under which person’s vital situation can be designated as Échec’ (p. 45).

  16. 16.

    As Améry himself was well aware, Échec is a more common and conspicuous threat than death (p. 42), whether as a failure in life (e.g., bankruptcy, dismissal, or divorce), or whether as a failure of life (because eventually all lives are submissions to death, or because fundamental loneliness is irrefutable [pp. 114–115]). Thus, For the most part, the Échec does not lead to extreme conclusions such as voluntary death , and even if it does, it is usually a momentary, fleeting notion. It is only the ‘affected person [who] experiences in its full inexorability’ (ibid.). What then does ‘affected’ refer to here? My guess is that Améry refers here to the affect of the anti-logic of death which was activated by the ‘first blow’.

  17. 17.

    Ratcliffe refers to a traumatic experience, which was certainly present in Améry’s life (although Améry refuses to refer to himself as ‘traumatized’, but rather as having experienced a ‘spiritual and psychic condition [which] corresponds completely to reality’ (Améry, 1980, p. 99)), as well as to victims of all kinds of abuse, which according to many studies on the subject, constitute a large percentage of suicides. However, the criterion for traumatic experience can be as broad as it can be narrow and limited. Here, I am applying it broadly. Further exploration should address Ratcliffe’s notion that modification occurs at the pre-intentioned structure as well. Clarifying this issue can potentially support the thesis that death inclination is deeply involved in life instincts.

  18. 18.

    Plutchik R (2001). To be honest, for Plutchik and his successors, Eros does not constitute an ‘emotion’. However, for the sake of my argument, the distinction is not important.

  19. 19.

    As with Eros, words fail to fully capture it, yet, it is interesting to note though that the functions of both Eros and Disgust are to preserve life; nonetheless, in extreme cases, they act against the organism itself in a kind of autoimmune attack. Should we conclude that such cases indicate pathology? I would like to argue that they do not, and the explanation for this is closely related to how one might think of death inclinations.

  20. 20.

    Self-disgust is a fairly common matter in Western society, and, to a certain extent, everyone is likely to have experienced some level of it (whether from binge eating, from an unnecessary cigarette, or from the image staring at us from the mirror).

  21. 21.

    Inclination toward death [Todesneigung] is the term that Améry uses to distinguish his exegetics from Freud`s Todestrieb. Nevertheless, it seems to me that the analysis suggested by Améry is somewhat problematic and insufficient. First, because although Améry quotes Freud using the term Todestrieb as ‘Death instinct’ (pp. 73–75), it is important to notice that Freud himself insists that it is a drive [der Trieb], and not an instinct [der Instinkt]. The second reason is that, to some extent, his interpretive proposal seems to already exist in Freud scripts.

  22. 22.

    See Bernstein (2011, pp. 398–399). It is worth noticing here that through an analysis of psychosis and interpersonally induced trauma, Ratcliffe conceives a disruption of the pre-reflective ‘trust’ that guides everyday perceptions. If interpersonal relations affect the integrity of intentionality (i.e., the basic experience of being in one kind of intentional state rather than in another), then it is not only significance that undergoes a change, but also the affective bodily and interpersonal expectations that tacitly guide our own encounters of others and the world. Therefore, the experiential precondition itself is claimed to be relational.

  23. 23.

    See Dienstag (2009).

  24. 24.

    I find Windt’s definition for suicidality very useful here: suicidality as an ‘open texture’ event with a ‘weak’ family-resemblance criterion (1981, p. 40).

  25. 25.

    For example, ‘It is not Being that oppresses me, or Nothingness, or God, or the Absence of God, only society. For it and only it caused the disturbance in my existential balance, which I am trying to oppose with an upright gait. It and only it robbed me of my trust in the world’ (Améry 1980, p. 100).

  26. 26.

    In this sense, Wittgenstein’s distinction seems accurate—indeed, ‘the world of the happy man is a different one from that of the unhappy man’ (2018, §6.43).

  27. 27.

    For an updated comprehensive and clear review of psychological and sociological approaches to suicide and suicidality, see Gunn III JF and Lester D (2014).

  28. 28.

    This difference is more than a difference between two language games, to use Wittgenstein’s notion (1958), because the anti-logic of death opposes any common practices, regulation and rules altogether, and as a result it denies the possibility of a game, let alone participation in it. Therefore, to quote Clements, ‘In a real sense, an individual who does not value existence does not value anything at all, and to apply tools of cognitive values to this primary effect is to deny him his validity in a totally arbitrary fashion’ (1980, p. 107).

  29. 29.

    ‘Epistemic Ignorance’ is not a lack of knowledge but a lack of utilizing it. Yet, it is not a wholly conscious choice or a ‘not caring’, but rather, it is closer to denial than exclusion or repression. The more it is used, the more it becomes deeper and comprehensive. This is because ignorance as a substantive epistemic practice is not only a ‘defect’ on the part of the ‘knower’ but a structural problem. (For further reading: Tuana 2004; Gilson 2011, 2014).

  30. 30.

    It is important to clarify that the structure of an act/thought in no way implies that it is impulsive. There are, of course, suicides that can be characterized as impulsive (usually among teenagers), but these are not at the heart of the analysis proposed here.

  31. 31.

    Be that as it may, I will not get into the rich, complex discussion over the question of free will that Améry refers to, nor shall I try to explain his position and defend it. I will just mention that, for Améry, freedom is not existential (p. 125). That is, freedom is not a state of pure objective being (as opposed to truth or reason) but an individual, endless process of constant change that is ‘subject to a multi causality that is almost infinite’ (p. 137). That is, one is conditioned (by the logic of life, whether you call it biologics, physics, or neurochemistry facts, or as ‘unity of consciousness and the categories’, or as speaking animal), and yet one experiences one’s self as free (p. 137).

  32. 32.

    Hegel, G.W.F. (1977) Phenomenology of Spirit.

  33. 33.

    To some extent, Améry’s anti-logic of death can be analogous to Blanchot’s Other Night (1982, pp. 162–163), as it refuses any possibility of positive conceptualization. This movement, as Blanchot points out, ‘makes us sense not only its discretion and its essential intimacy but also its profound unreality: death as abyss, not that which founds but the absence and the loss of all foundation’ (1982, p. 153). The endless reflections that reverberate the absolute reveal the non-exclusivity of the logic of life; yet, at the same time, it resists dialectical negation by shattering any possibility of meaning. This superficial comparison to Blanchot raises an important question in regard to Améry’s positive reversal that is embodied in voluntary death .

  34. 34.

    This point, used and articulated by the ‘Two States View’ advocates, as Cowley argued, contends that the concept of rationality is essentially future-oriented; since the suicidal subject has no future after suicide, it makes no sense to call suicide rational or irrational (2006, p. 497) or, as Devine claimed: ‘We are dealing, that is, not with a situation concerning which rational men will exhibit a range of estimates, but with a situation in which one man’s estimate is as good as another, because what is being done is a comparison with an unknown quality’ (1980, p. 139).

  35. 35.

    It is more likely that facing the anti-logic of death may lead one to ‘feel no impulse to oppose or stand for anything at all’ (Kulp 2014, p. 126), not even to die. Therefore, Kulp’s own conclusion according to which ‘the ultimate outcome of this logic of death is the lack of the need to do or be anything, is suicide’ (ibid.) seem to be a contradiction. For further discussion on the issue of temporality, narrative and intention in Améry’s writing see: Ben-Shai (2010, 2011).

  36. 36.

    Or ‘The production and maintenance of a compulsory ontology of pathology’ (Marsh 2013, p. 747). See also Marsh (2010).

References

  • Améry, J. (1980). At the Mind’s Limits (Translated from German by S. Rosenfeld and S. P. Rosenfeld). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Améry, J. (1984). Radical Humanism: Selected Essays (Translated from German by S. Rosenfeld and S. P. Rosenfeld). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Améry, J. (1999). On Suicide: A Discourse on Voluntary Death (Translated from German by J. D. Barlow). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baechler, J. (1979). Suicides. New York: Basic Books, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baier, A. C. (1991). “Trust and Its Vulnerabilities” and “Sustaining Trust”. In Tanner Lectures on Human Values (Vol. 13). Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baier, A. C. (1995). Moral Prejudices: Essays on Ethics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, A. T., Kovacs, M., & Weissman, A. (1979). Assessment of Suicidal Ideation: The Scale for Suicidal Ideation. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 47(2), 343–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Shai, R. (2010). To Reverse the Irreversible: On Time Disorder in the Work of Jean Améry. In J. R. Watson (Ed.), Metacide (pp. 73–92). Leiden, The Netherlands: Brill | Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Shai, R. (2011). Imposition, or Writing from the Void: Pathos and Pathology in Améry. In M. Zolkos (Ed.), On Jean Améry: Philosophy of the Catastrophe (pp. 109–134). Lanham: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, J. M. (2011). Trust: On the Real But Almost Always Unnoticed, Ever-Changing Foundation of Ethical Life. Metaphilosophy, 42(4), 395–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blanchot, M. (1982). The Space of Literature (Translated from [language] by A. Smock). London: University of Nebraska Press Lincoln.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, B., Feldman, F., & Johansson, J. (2013). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Death. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brinck, I., Reddy, V., & Zahavi, D. (2017). The Primacy of the We? In C. Durt, T. Fuchs, & C. Tewes (Eds.), Embodiment, Enaction, and Culture (pp. 131–148). Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camus, A. (1955). The Myth of Sisyphus, and Other Essays. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camus, A. (1991). The Rebel an Essay on Man in Revolt (With a Foreword by Sir Herbert Read A Revised and Complete Translation from French by Anthony Bower). New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clements, C. (1980). The Ethics of Not-Being. In M. Pabst Battin & D. Mayo (Eds.), Suicide: The Philosophical Issues (pp. 104–114). New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cowley, C. (2006). Suicide is Neither Rational nor Irrational. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 9(5), 495–504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Critchley, S. (2004). Very Little – Almost Nothing: Death, Philosophy, Literature. London and New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Devine, P. E. (1980). On Choosing Death. In M. Pabst Battin & D. Mayo (Eds.), Suicide: The Philosophical Issues (pp. 138–142). New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dienstag, J. F. (2009). Pessimism: Philosophy, Ethic, Spirit. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Epicurus. (1966). Principal Doctrines. In J. Saunders (Ed.), Greek and Roman Philosophy After Aristotle. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2000). Philosophical Conceptions of the Self: Implications for Cognitive Science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4(1), 14–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilson, E. (2011). Vulnerability, Ignorance, and Oppression. Hypatia, 26(2), 308–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilson, E. (2014). The Ethics of Vulnerability: A Feminist Analysis of Social Life and Practice. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunn, J. F., III, & Lester, D. (2014). Theories of Suicide: Past, Present and Future. Springfield, IL: Charles C Thomas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1977). Phenomenology of Spirit (Translated from German by A. V. Miller with Analysis of the Text and Foreword by J. N. Findlay). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidelberger-Leonard, I. (2010). The Philosopher of Auschwitz: Jean Améry and Living with the Holocaust. London and New York: I. B. Tauris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kulp, M. J. (2014). The Limits of Rationality: Suicidality, Affectivity, and the Rational. PhD. Dissertations. Retrieved from http://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/1277.

  • Liddell, H. G., & Scott, R. (1889). ‘Logos’. An Intermediate Greek–English Lexicon. Retrieved from http://www.perseus.tufts.edu.

  • Luper, S. (2009). Philosophy of Death. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Macintyre, A. (1985). After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (2nd ed.). London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, C., Rogers, W., & Doods, S. (Eds.). (2014). Vulnerability: New Essays in Ethics and Feminist Philosophy. New York: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marsh, I. (2010). Suicide: Foucault, History and Truth. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marsh, I. (2013). The Uses of History in the Unmaking of Modern Suicide. Journal of Social History, 46(3), 744–756.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1971). The Absurd. The Journal of Philosophy, 68(20), 716–727.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plutchik, R. (2001). The Nature of Emotions. American Scientist; Research Triangle Park, 89(4), 344–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2009). Existential Feeling and Psychopathology. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 16(2), 179–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2013). What Is It to Lose Hope? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 12(4), 597–614.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1985). Time and Narrative (Translated from French by K. McLaughlin & D. Pellauer). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ringel, E. (1976). The Presuicidal Syndrome. Suicide and Life-Threatening Behaviour, 6(3), 131–149.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J. P. (1992). Being and Nothingness (Translated from French by H. Barnes). New York: Washington Square Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlimme, J. E. (2013). Sense of Self-Determination and the Suicidal Experience. A Phenomenological Approach. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 16(2), 211–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shneidman, E. S. (2001). Comprehending Suicide: Landmarks in 20th-Century Suicidology. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tuana, N. (2004). Coming to Understand: Orgasm and the Epistemology of Ignorance. Hypatia, 19(1), 194–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Windt, P. (1981). The Concept of Suicide. In M. Pabst Battin & D. J. Mayo (Eds.), Suicide: The Philosophical Issues. London: Peter Owen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958) Philosophical Investigations (Translated from German by Anscombe GEM) (2nd ed.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (2018). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus Logisch-Philosophische Side by Side Edition v. 0.53. Retrieved from http://people.umass.edu/klement/tlp/.

  • Zahavi, D. (2007). Self and Other: The Limits of Narrative Understanding. In D. Hutto (Ed.), Narrative and Understanding Persons (pp. 179–201). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2017). Thin, Thinner, Thinnest: Defining the Minimal Self. In D. Christoph, T. Fuchs, & C. Tewes (Eds.), Embodiment, Enaction, and Culture: Investigating the Constitution of the Shared World (pp. 193–199). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Lavi, Y. (2019). Between the Logic of Life and the Anti-logic of Death: Reflections on Suicidality in the Wake of Jean Améry. In: Ataria, Y., Kravitz, A., Pitcovski, E. (eds) Jean Améry. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-28095-6_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics