Skip to main content

Dialetheic Conditional Modal Logic

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Graham Priest on Dialetheism and Paraconsistency

Part of the book series: Outstanding Contributions to Logic ((OCTR,volume 18))

  • 479 Accesses

Abstract

Standard modal logic for alethic modalities analyses modalities as ranging over all possible worlds (the Leibnizian universe). This leaves very little room in the space of worlds to entertain impossible things. My proposal is to liberate the Leibnizian universe and reinforce the relative aspect of possibility; worlds are possible with respect to some worlds, and impossible for others. The central idea is to isolate relative possibility (Kripke) from conditionality (Lewis/Stalnaker). To accommodate counterpossibles, I provide a dialetheic conditional modal logic, a theory that is dialetheic at every level, in the logic as well as in the set theory behindĀ it.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    If youā€™re not familiar with bisimulation, think of the picture as showing that any formula that can be invalidated at \(\texttt {w}\) can also be invalidated at \(\texttt {w}'\) (see Priest 2008, Sect. 3.7.5); anything impossible at \(\texttt {w}\) is also impossible at \(\texttt {w}'\), because \(\texttt {w}\) doesnā€™t see any more worlds than \(\texttt {w}'\).

  2. 2.

    I follow Stalnaker (1968) and talk about conditionals instead of counterfactuals like Lewis (1973). I take ā€˜conditionalsā€™ to be a more general notion, counterfactuals being the special case of conditionals with false antecedents.

  3. 3.

    Repetition intended, to stress that dialetheic logic is used in the object and meta levels.

  4. 4.

    I continue to represent models with equivalence classes for \(\texttt {R}\) and Lewisā€™ systems of spheres \(\texttt {S}\), as I find them more convivial, with apologies if you donā€™t agree.

  5. 5.

    The proof of soundness and completeness is entirely standard, and I wonā€™t bother you with the details.

  6. 6.

    Williamson formulates pos as the logically equivalent , but this formulation will be better for us.

  7. 7.

    For a thorough criticism of Williamson on counterpossibles, see Berto et al. (2017), who also propose a conditional modal logic similar to mine, but using a distinction between possible and impossible worlds instead of my more general notion of relative possibility. I donā€™t like the twentieth-century distinction between possible and impossible worlds, or between good and bad worlds in general, as discussed in Girard and Weber (2015).

  8. 8.

    For a counterexample to nec, take a model with two worlds \(\texttt {w}\) and \(\mathtt {v}\) such that \(\mathtt {v}\not \in \texttt {R}(w)\), \(\mathtt {V}(p) =\{\mathtt {v}\}\), \(\mathtt {v}\in \texttt {S}(\texttt {w}, \llbracket p \rrbracket )\) but \(\mathtt {v}\not \in \mathtt {V}(q)\). Then \(\Box (p \rightarrow q)\) is vacuously true at \(\texttt {w}\) whereas is false. For a counterexample to pos, take a model with three worlds \(\texttt {w}, \mathtt {u}\) and \(\mathtt {v}\) such that \(\mathtt {V}(p) = \{\mathtt {u}, \mathtt {v}\}\), \(\mathtt {V}(q) = \{\mathtt {v}\}\), \(\mathtt {u}\in \texttt {R}(\texttt {w})\), and \(\mathtt {v}\in \texttt {S}(w, \llbracket p \rrbracket )\).

  9. 9.

    From Blackburn et al. (2001,Ā Definition 3.2) A formula \(\varphi \) defines a class of frames K if for all frames \(\mathtt {F}\), \(\mathtt {F}\in \texttt {K}\) iff \(\varphi \) is valid in \(\mathtt {F}\).

  10. 10.

    The proofs of definability are straightforward and left to the reader.

  11. 11.

    A condition that implies but is not equivalent to POS is the converse of NEC: \((\texttt {R}(\texttt {w})\cap \texttt {X}) \subseteq \texttt {S}(\texttt {w}, \texttt {X})\). If we assumed this stronger condition in combination with NEC, we would reduce conditionals to strict implication, which would be a bad idea (cf., David 1973, Sect. 1.2).

  12. 12.

    ā€˜So that is our basic procedure for handling the antecedent of a counterfactual implicated in a case of extra-mathematical explanation: hold as much fixed as you can within mathematics compatible with the twiddle, without inducing a contradictionā€™, Baron et al. (2017), p.11.

  13. 13.

    VC is Lewisā€™s favourite counterfactual logic. I choose it here without a strong philosophical commitment. Assume the limit assumption for simplicity. The choice is entirely modular and you can pick your favourite conditional logic if you donā€™t like VC; no problem.

  14. 14.

    The axiom pos is canonical for POS in a standard Henkin completeness proof adapted from Chellas (1975). Check or proceed without concern.

  15. 15.

    \(\texttt {w}\in \llbracket \Box \lnot \varphi \rrbracket ^{+} \Rightarrow \texttt {R}(\texttt {w}) \subseteq \llbracket \lnot \varphi \rrbracket ^{+} \Rightarrow \texttt {R}(\texttt {w}) \subseteq \llbracket \varphi \rrbracket ^{-}\Rightarrow \texttt {w}\in \llbracket \Diamond \varphi \rrbracket ^{-} \Rightarrow \texttt {w}\in \llbracket \lnot \Diamond \varphi \rrbracket ^{+}\).

  16. 16.

    Since the problem is about the duality of modalities, it arises just the same in a formulation with three truth values.

  17. 17.

    As I want to keep the focus on modalities and conditionals, I wonā€™t go into motivating the propositional logic here, and refer you to (Weber etĀ al. 2016) instead.

  18. 18.

    I add the constant \(\bot \) to be able to identify triviality. Unlike in twentieth-century logic, it cannot be defined by a contradictory formula.

  19. 19.

    With apologies to Kabay (2008).

  20. 20.

    Assume that \(\texttt {w}\in \llbracket \Diamond \bot \rrbracket \), then \(\texttt {R}(\texttt {w}) \cap \llbracket \bot \rrbracket \ne \emptyset \), so there exists a world \(\mathtt {x}\) such that \(\mathtt {x}\in \texttt {R}(\texttt {w}) \wedge \mathtt {x}\in \llbracket \bot \rrbracket \). But \(\mathtt {x}\in \llbracket \bot \rrbracket \) implies that \(\mathtt {x}\in \Box \varphi \) for every \(\varphi \), so \(\texttt {R}(\mathtt {x}) \subseteq \llbracket \varphi \rrbracket \) for every \(\varphi \). Furthermore, \(\mathtt {x}\in \texttt {R}(\texttt {w})\) implies by 5 that \(\texttt {w}\in \texttt {R}(\mathtt {x})\). So there is a world \(\mathtt {x}\) such that \(\texttt {w}\in \texttt {R}(\mathtt {x}) \wedge \texttt {R}(\mathtt {x})\subseteq \llbracket \varphi \rrbracket \) for every \(\varphi \), so \(\texttt {w}\in \llbracket \varphi \rrbracket \) for every \(\varphi \). Therefore \(\texttt {w}\in \llbracket \bot \rrbracket \).

References

  • Baker, A. (2005). Are there genuine mathematical explanations of physical phenomena? Mind, 114(454), 223ā€“238.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  • Baron, S., Colyvan, M., & Ripley, D. (2017). How mathematics can make a difference. Philosophers Imprint, 17(3). University of Michigan Press.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  • Berto, F., French, R., Priest, G., & Ripley, D. (2017, August). Williamson on counterpossibles. Journal of Philosophical Logic.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  • Blackburn, P., de Rijke, M., & Venema, Y. (2001). Modal logic. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  • Chellas, B. F. (1980). Modal logic: An introduction. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  • Chellas, B. F. (1975). Basic conditional logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 4(2), 133ā€“153.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  • Cobreros, P., EgrĆ©, P., Ripley, D., & van Rooij, R. (2015, August). Pragmatic interpretations of vague expressions: Strongest meaning and nonmonotonic consequence. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 44(4), 375ā€“393.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  • Divers, J. (1999). A genuine realist theory of advanced modalizing. Mind, 108(430), 217ā€“240.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  • Divers, J. (2014). The modal status of the Lewisian analysis of modality. Mind, 123(491), 861ā€“872.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  • Forrest, P., & Armstrong, M. D. (1984, June). An argument against David Lewisā€™ theory of possible worlds. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 62(2), 164ā€“168.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  • Girard, P., & Weber, Z. (2015) Bad worlds. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  • Humberstone, L. (2011, January). Variation on a trivialist argument of Paul Kabay. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 20(1), 115ā€“132.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  • Jago, M. (2016, July). Advanced modalizing problems. Mind, 125(499), 627ā€“642.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  • Kabay, P.Ā D. (2008). A defense of trivialism.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  • Kant, I. (2004). Prolegomena to any future metaphysics that will be able to come forward as science: With selections from the critique of pure reason. Cambridge texts in the history of philosophy (rev. ed.). Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  • Kripke, S. A. (1959). A completeness theorem in modal logic. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 24(1), 1ā€“14.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  • Kripke, S.Ā A. (1980). Naming and necessity. Library of philosophy and logic (revised and enlarged ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1973). Counterfactuals. Library of philosophy and logic. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  • Martin, B. (2014, September). Dialetheism and the impossibility of the world. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 1ā€“15.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  • Nolan, D. (1996). Recombination unbound. Philosophical Studies, 84(2ā€“3), 239ā€“262.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  • Nolan, D. (1997). Impossible worlds: A modest approach. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 38(4), 535ā€“572.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  • Priest, G. (2002). Beyond the limits of thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  • Priest, G. (2006). In contradiction. Oxford Scholarship Online, Oxford University Press.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  • Priest, G. (2008). An introduction to non-classical logic: From if to is. Cambridge introductions to philosophy (2nd ed.). Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  • Priest, G. (2010, January). Inclosures, vagueness, and self-reference. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 51(1), 69ā€“84.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  • Priest, G. (2016). Thinking the impossible. Philosophical Studies, 173(10), 2649ā€“2662.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  • Pruss, A. R. (2001). The cardinality objection to David Lewisā€™s modal realism. Philosophical Studies, 104(2), 169ā€“178.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  • Ripley, D. (2011). Contradictions at the borders. In R. Nouwen, R. van Rooij, U. Sauerland, & H.-C. Schmitz (Eds.), Vagueness in communication (pp. 169ā€“188). Springer.

    Google ScholarĀ 

  • Stalnaker, R.Ā C. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In W.Ā L. Harper, R. Stalnaker, & G. Pearce (Eds.), IFS, numberĀ 15 in The University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science (pp. 41ā€“55). The Netherlands: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-9117-0_2.

    ChapterĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  • Weber, Z. (2010, October). A paraconsistent model of vagueness. Mind, 119(476), 1025ā€“1045.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  • Weber, Z., Badia, G., & Girard, P. (2016). What is an inconsistent truth table? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 94(3), 533ā€“548.

    ArticleĀ  Google ScholarĀ 

  • Williamson, T. (2010, March). Modal logic within counterfactual logic. In B. Hale & A. Hoffmann (Eds.), Modality: metaphysics, logic, and epistemology. Oxford University Press.

    Google ScholarĀ 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Graham, youā€™ve been a source of inspiration for several scholars that have known or read you, and you are a model of perseverance against adversity. Above all, you are a good friend, and Iā€™m very pleased to be able to contribute this paper in your honour. I would like to thank Zach Weber, Fred Kroon, Joy Britten and Michael Hillas for valuable comments on a previous draft of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Patrick Girard .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

Ā© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Girard, P. (2019). Dialetheic Conditional Modal Logic. In: Başkent, C., Ferguson, T. (eds) Graham Priest on Dialetheism and Paraconsistency. Outstanding Contributions to Logic, vol 18. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-25365-3_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics