Skip to main content

Information at the Threshold of Interpretation: Science as Human Construction of Sense

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover A Critical Reflection on Automated Science

Part of the book series: Human Perspectives in Health Sciences and Technology ((HPHST,volume 1))

Abstract

This text will first discuss the great and productive “linguistic turn” that originated in Logic, at the end of the nineteenth century. After Turing’s work on the Logical Computing Machine (1936–1950) and Shannon’s theory (1948), Brillouin attributed information content to Maxwell’s demon’s action (1956), with a scientific invention and, in my opinion, a touch of humor, thus granting to inert matter an intelligent activity capable of inverting entropy. Moreover, since the 1950s, many identified the digital elaboration of data with human intelligence and some projected the processing of information onto inert matter. In the same years, DNA was identified as the complete information carrier of phylogenesis and ontogenesis. In these approaches, an ambiguity has been arbitrarily played out, and a threshold has been sometimes crossed, sometimes not; first, in Logic and Computing, between “formal principles of proof” or of computation and their “semantics” (their mathematical meaning); then in Biology, between elaboration of information and biological dynamics in their context. Today, well beyond classical Artificial Intelligence on discrete data types, Brillouin’s invention and Deep Learning on continuous mathematical structures are the new loci of confusion between knowledge construction and transmission or processing of information. Yet, the construction of human knowledge is even more radically by-passed and science dehumanized when information is directly embedded in a world that is viewed as a massive information processor. The remarkable scientific and economic productivity of our new observable, information, must instead be seen in the context of our human, ecosystemic and historical activities, in order to subordinate it to interpretation and meaningful action that enrich and do not strip the sense from our forms of knowledge and life. To this purpose, we must strictly distinguish between information, as formal elaboration and transmission of signs, and information as production of “meaning” in our active friction on reality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    We use “sign”, in reference to a priori meaningless strokes, letters, 0 s and 1 s …, thus we use the expression “sign pushing” instead of “symbol pushing” widely used in Computer Science. “Symbol” retains the Greek etymology of “sym-ballein” or “to bring together” or to unify different acts of experience or synthesize meaning.

  2. 2.

    Note that computability and its machines were invented in order to prove the limits of the formal-linguistic approach. As hinted above, in order to prove undecidability and incomputability, Gödel, Church and Turing (1936) had first to give precise definitions of “computable function” and “formal derivation”, thus of formal computing/arithmetic machines, the mathematical foundation of modern digital computers – see (Longo 2010) for the relevance of these and other negative results.

  3. 3.

    H. Weyl, Hilbert’s “best student”, recalls his supervisor’s philosophy by quoting: “a typically Hilbertian manner: “It must be possible to replace in all geometric statements the words point, line, plane by table, chair, mug.” In [Hilbert’s] deductive system of geometry the evidence, even the truth of axioms, is irrelevant …” (Weyl 1953).

  4. 4.

    Even Wiles’ 1993 proof of this easy to state arithmetic property, Fermat’s last theorem, required the invention of new deep mathematical ideas, a complex blend of advanced algebraic geometry, the “vision” of a path that linked homology to the analysis of elliptic curves, leading to the totally unrelated new ideas and techniques of the “modularity lifting theorem” (Cornell et al. 2013). Checking formally the proof, a posteriori – once it has been given, may be very useful, but it is a different matter, (Hesselink 2008).

  5. 5.

    In short, following a proof allegedly given by Gauss at the age of 7, place

    1

    2

    n

    on a row

    n

    (n-1)

    1

    on the next row (an audacious mirror symmetry of the usual order of number writing), then obtain:

    (n + 1) … (n + 1) by adding the columns. Thus, the sum of the first n integers is (n + 1)n/2, which is easy now to check by induction; yet, we had first to produce the formula, by this or other similar constructions. The rule-based formalist approach confuses proving, in mathematics, which includes inventions like here, with a posteriori proof checking, a remarkable technique in Computer Science, that we will mention below.

  6. 6.

    In (Longo and Montévil 2014), we added to irreversibility of time and to entropy production the coexistence of a “symmetry breaking” and of a random event: these four phenomena seem to be correlated in all existing physical theories. In our work, this correlation extends to proper biological dynamics, such as embryogenesis and evolution, where increasing organization as well (anti-entropy production) produces entropy.

  7. 7.

    The information content is the logarithm of the probability, as a frequency, of the chosen card. This example opens the way to conflating Boltzmann’s logarithmic formula for entropy to Brillouin’s quantification of information, modulo a negative sign and a differing constant, as pointed out above, also by its dimensionality – a further major difference.

  8. 8.

    See “We Have Learned Nothing from the Genome” (Venter 2010), written by the leader of the team that first decoded a human DNA, and (Longo 2018a) for some references to the amazing promises made in early 2000s as for cancer’s genetic diagnosis, prognosis and therapy, see also (Weinberg 2014), (Gatenby 2017).

  9. 9.

    In a rare attempt to clarify the different role of Turing-Kolmogorov vs Shannon-Brillouin approaches in biology, (Maynard-Smith 1999) confuses, in the explanatory examples, the dual correlation that entropy and complexity have in the two theories, see (Longo et al. 2012), (Perret and Longo 2016) for details.

  10. 10.

    Even more radically “proteins never do fold into a particular shape, but rather remain unstructured or ‘disordered’ […]. In mammals, about 75% of signaling proteins and half of all proteins are thought to contain long, disordered regions, while about 25% of all proteins are predicted to be ‘fully disordered’ […]. Many of these intrinsically unstructured proteins are involved in regulatory processes, and are often at the center of large protein interaction networks” (Gsponer and Madan Babu 2009). See also the increasingly acknowledged important role of long non-coding RNAs (Hadjiargyrou and Delihas 2013). Dogmas on the exact mechanisms inspired by the need to transmit and elaborate alpha-numeric information are collapsing one after the other (Mouilleron et al. 2016).

  11. 11.

    Overlapping genes are parts of a given DNA or RNA region that can be translated in at least two different reading frames, yielding very different proteins. In fact, a shift in the reading frame of a nucleotide sequence, by one-two bases, totally changes the resulting protein. Discovered in the late ‘70s in a small viral genome (Barrell et al. 1976), there are coming to the limelight only recently since many studies have shown they are not restricted to viruses (Chirico et al. 2010), but they are present as well in cellular organisms, man included (reviewed in Pavesi et al. 2018). M. Granero and A. Porati, among the pioneers in this field, nicely described the phenomenon in Italian: by a one letter shift CARABINE MICIDIALI becomes ARABI NEMICI DI ALI, and GAS INODORO becomes ASINO D’ORO (A. Vianelli, personal communication). This sort of shifts in ‘reading’ is not recommended in linguistic analysis nor in programming, where it is avoided by the use of parenthesis, typically – like in lambda-calculus, a consistently evoked reference for the genetic program, see (Danchin 2003, 2009). Actually, even in genomes (at least bacterial ones) there might be more STOP off-frame codons than expected to avoid unneeded reading frame shifts (Seligmann and Pollock 2004; Abraham and Hurst 2018). What is a gene, then?

  12. 12.

    As observed (and promoted) by H. Weyl (1949), physics moved “from causal lawfulness to the structural organization of time and space (structural lawfulness), nay, from causal lawfulness to intelligibility by mathematical (geometric) structures”, see also (Bailly and Longo 2006).

  13. 13.

    This is in blatant contrast with biological organisms, which “go wrong” very often or most of the time – but, in absence of a pre-given phase space for biological dynamics, it is hard to pre-define “wrong/right”: very rarely, but crucially, hopeful monsters may be “right” in evolution, and contribute to speciation, as we may observe a posteriori (Longo 2017). The point is that ecosystemic compatibility and viability is not optimality, in particular because the ecosystem is not pre-defined, but co-constructed with/by the organism.

  14. 14.

    “… due to the inherent limitations of scientific instruments, all an observer can know of a process in nature is a discrete time, discrete-space series of measurements. Fortunately, this is precisely the kind of thing — strings of discrete symbols, a “formal” language—that computation theory analyzes for structure.” (Crutchfield 1994).

  15. 15.

    “subjective-absolute and objective-relative seems to me to contain one of the most fundamental epistemological insights that can be extracted from natural sciences” (Weyl 1949).

  16. 16.

    Note that also declarative or functional languages are “imperative”: they apply reduction rules to get to “normal forms” or implement the equality (and this on the grounds of fundamental theorems, such as Normalization (Girard et al. 1989) and Church-Rosser (Barendregt 1984)).

  17. 17.

    Unfortunately, this attitude is shaping minds. A student in mathematics, in my top institution in higher education (ENS, Paris), asked me not long ago: “how can the Universe compute at each instant where it will go in the next instant?”. I answered: “there are plenty of very small Turing Machines, hidden everywhere, that do the computations!”. And I wrote a letter to Alan Turing (Longo 2018c) – he explicitly and radically departed from these views (the brain … the Universe, are surely not discrete state machines, i.e. Turing Machines, says he – see references in my letter).

  18. 18.

    Quantum Computing formally introduces a major feature of Quantum Mechanics, entanglement (Zorzi 2016). By this, it forces a connection between hardware and software, a major computing and engineering challenge, beyond Turing’s fruitful split, hardware vs software, perhaps along the way of a major revolution in computing.

  19. 19.

    Many projected into nature Kolomogorof’s effective notion of “incompressibility” for finite strings, as the dual component of predictive determination, i.e. as randomness. A finite sequence or string of letters/numbers w, say, is incompressible if no program to generate it is shorter than w (Calude 2002). Today, this is a crucial notion since our machines need to compress strings. However, it does not describe physical randomness, as thought by many, yet another abuse of a (remarkable) computational invention. Only asymptotically, infinite random sequences, as defined by Martin-Löf, relate to classical and quantum randomness (Calude and Longo 2016). This is to be expected: limit constructions already unified, by Boltzmann work, random particle trajectories and thermodynamic entropy (Chibbaro et al. 2015). In the finite, all sufficiently long strings are compressible, by Van der Waarden theorem (Calude and Longo 2017). Thus, in terms of incompressibility, there would be no long random sequences …. And a string to be generated, in the future (next year lottery drawings), is blatantly not random if one can compute, now, just one element of it, independently of its ‘a posteriori’ compressibility or not. Once more, there is no way to analyze such a meaningful notion for physics, randomness for finitely many events, in abstract computational terms: one has first to specify the intended theory, as an interpretation and organization of (a fragment of) nature, and then define randomness relatively to it (Calude and Longo 2016).

  20. 20.

    A red herring, the so-called extended Church Thesis, often blurred computational novelties: any physical finite structure computes at most Turing computable functions. Now, mathematical neural nets are not meant to compute number-theoretic functions. Of course, in this and other cases, if one forces a physical dynamic to take a digital input and then produce at most one digital output and formalizes the dynamics “à la Hilbert”, one can prove that that formal system computes no more than a Turing Machine. This says nothing about the proper expressivity and possible functions of a continuous dynamics of networks (see below), whose job is not to compute functions on integers (see below for more). A similar trivializing game has been played also with Quantum Computing and Concurrent Networks (Aceto et al. 2003).

  21. 21.

    See (Supiot 2017) for the difference between democratic government and governance, and (Longo 2018b) for the entanglement of science and democracy.

  22. 22.

    “Optimal pricing of goods in an economy appears to arise from agents obeying the local rules of commerce” (Fama 1991), quoted in (Crutchfield 1994), where it is stressed: “global information processing plays a key role”.

  23. 23.

    Statistical analysis of “abstract” data govern finance and, thus, economy, (Bouleau 2017). These analyses are independent from the underlying assets, that is from any reference to “tables, chairs, mugs”, as Hilbert would put it (footnote 3).

  24. 24.

    “The machine may be out of order and present the operating characteristics similar to a mad behavior of a living being. But it cannot revolt. The revolt indeed implies a profound transformation of the finalized behavior, and not a malfunction of the conduct.”

  25. 25.

    Papers (co-)authored by Giuseppe Longo are downloadable here: http://www.di.ens.fr/users/longo/download.html

References

Papers (co-)authored by Giuseppe Longo are downloadable here: http://www.di.ens.fr/users/longo/download.html

  • Abraham, L., and L.D. Hurst. 2018. Refining the Ambush Hypothesis: Evidence that GC- and AT-Rich Bacteria Employ Different Frameshift Defense Categories. Genome Biology and Evolution 14: 1153–1173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aceto, L., G. Longo, and B. Victor, eds. 2003. The Difference Between Concurrent and Sequential Computations, Special issue. Mathematical Structures in Computer Science 13: 4–5. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adjiri, A. 2017. DNA Mutations May Not Be the Cause of Cancer. Oncol Therapy 5 (1): 85–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asperti, A., and G. Longo. 1991. Categories, Types and Structures. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baccelli, F., H.M. Mir-Omid, and A. Khezeli. 2016. Dynamics on Unimodular Random Graphs. In arXiv:1608.05940v1 [math.PR].

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailly, F., and G. Longo. 2006. (Trans. 2011) Mathematics and the Natural Sciences: The Physical Singularity of Life. London: Imperial College Press, (original French version, Hermann, 2006).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Biological Organization and Anti-Entropy. Journal of Biological Systems 17 (01): 63–96. https://doi.org/10.1142/S0218339009002715.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, S. 2014. Recognizing Paradigm Instability in Theories of Carcinogenesis. British Journal of Medicine and Medical Research 4 (5): 1149–1163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. A Cancer Theory Kerfuffle Can Lead to New Lines of Research. Journal of the National Cancer Institute 107: dju405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barbaresco, F., and A. Mohammad-Djafari, eds. 2015. Information, Entropy and Their Geometric Structures. Basel/Beijing: MDPI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barendregt, H. 1984. The Lambda-Calculus: Its Syntax, Its Semantics. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrell, B.G., G.M. Air, and C.A. Hutchison 3rd. 1976. Overlapping Genes in Bacteriophage φX174. Nature 264: 34–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berthoz, A. 1997. Le Sens du Mouvement. Paris: Odile Jacob (English version, 2000).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bezem, M., J.W. Klop, and R. Roelde Vrijer. 2013. Term Rewriting Systems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biasoni, S. 2020. De la précarité épistémique des systèmes complexes en transition critique étendue. Vers une épistémologie ouverte des processus de marchés. Thèse de Doctorat, sous la direction de J. Lassègue et G. Longo, Ens, Paris (publication attendue: 2020).

    Google Scholar 

  • Boser, B., E. Sackinger, J. Bromley, Y. LeCun, and L. Jackel. 1991. An Analog Neural Network Processor with Programmable Topology. IEEE Journal of Solid-State Circuits 26 (12): 2017–2025.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouleau, N. 2017. Wall street ne connait pas la tribu borélienne. Paris: Spartacus IDH.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bravi, B., and G. Longo. 2015. The Unconventionality of Nature: Biology, from Noise to Functional Randomness. In Unconventional Computation and Natural Computation, LNCS 9252, ed. Calude and Dinneen, 3–34. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brillouin, L. 1956. Science and Information Theory. New York: Academic.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brock, A., and S. Huang. 2017. Precision Oncology: Between Vaguely Right and Precisely Wrong. Cancer Research. https://doi.org/10.1158/0008-5472.CAN-17-0448. Published December.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bühlmann, V., L. Hovestadt, and V. Moosavi. 2015. Coding as Literacy. Basel: Birkhäuser.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Calude, C. 2002. Information and Randomness. 2nd ed. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Calude, C., and G. Longo. 2016. Classical, Quantum and Biological Randomness as Relative Unpredictability. Special issue of Natural Computing 15 (2): 263–278, Springer, June.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. The Deluge of Spurious Correlations in Big Data. Foundations of Science 22 (3): 595–612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cant, N.B., and C.G. Benson. 2003. Parallel Auditory Pathways: Projection Patterns of the Different Neuronal Populations in the Dorsal and Ventral Cochlear Nuclei. Brain Research Bulletin 60 (5–6): 457–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castiglione, P., M. Falcioni, A. Lesne, and A. Vulpiani. 2008. Chaos and Coarse-Graining in Statistical Mechanics. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chaitin, G. 2012. Proving Darwin: Making Biology Mathematical. Pantheon: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chatelet, G. 1993. Les enjeux du mobile. Paris: Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chibbaro, S., L. Rondoni, and A. Vulpiani. 2015. Reductionism, Emergence and Levels of Reality: The Importance of Being Borderline. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chirico, N., A. Vianelli, and R. Belshaw. 2010. Why Genes Overlap in Viruses. Proceedings of the Biological Sciences 277 (1701): 3809–3817. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2010.1052. Epub 2010 Jul 7. PubMed PMID: 20610432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collet, P., F. Krüger, and O. Maitre. 2013. Automatic Parallelization of EC on GPGPUs and Clusters of GPGPU Machines with EASEA and EASEA-CLOUD. In Massively Parallel Evolutionary Computation on GPGPUs, Natural Computing Series Book Series, 35–59. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cornell, Gary., Joseph H. Silverman, and Glenn. Stevens. 2013. Modular Forms and Fermat’s Last Theorem (illustrated ed.). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cortini, R., M. Barbi, B. Caré, C. Lavelle, A. Lesne, J. Mozziconacci, and J.M. Victor. 2016. The Physics of Epigenetics. Reviews of Modern Physics 88: 025002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cousot, P. 2016. Abstract Interpretation. In SAVE 2016, Changsha, China, 10–11 December.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F.H.C. 1958. On Protein Synthesis. In Symposia of the Society for Experimental Biology, Number XII: The Biological Replication of Macromolecules, ed. F.K. Sanders, 138–163. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crutchfield, J. 1994. The Calculi of Emergence: Computation Dynamics, and Induction. Special issue of Physica D, Proceedings of the Oji International Seminar “From Complex Dynamics to Artificial Reality”.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danchin, A. 2003. The Delphic Boat. What Genomes Tell Us. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Bacteria as computers making computers. FEMS Microbiology Reviews 33 (1). https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/full/10.1111/j.1574-6976.2008.00137.x.

  • Dawkins, R. 1976. The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T.W., A. Srivastava, and J.A. Bacigalupi. 2014. The Transition from Constraint to Regulation at the Origin of Life. Frontiers in Bioscience – Landmark 19: 945–957.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devaney, R.L. 1989. An Introduction to Chaotic Dynamical Systems. Reading: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, J. 1987. Neural Darwinism: The Theory of Neuronal Group Selection. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elowitz, M.B., A.J. Levine, E. Siggia, and P.S. Swain. 2002. Stochastic Gene Expression in a Single Cell. Science 297: 1183–1186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fama, E. 1991. Efficient Capital Markets II. The Journal of Finance 46: 1575–1617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox Keller, E. 2000. The Century of the Gene. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fromion, V., E. Leoncini, and P. Robert. 2013. Stochastic Gene Expression in Cells: A Point Process Approach. SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics 73 (1): 195–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garapon, A., and J. Lassègue. 2018. Justice digitale. Paris: PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gatenby, R.A. 2017. Is the Genetic Paradigm of Cancer Complete? Radiology 284: 1–3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, W. 1992. A vision of the Grail. In The Code of Codes: Scientific and Social Issues in the Human Genome Project, ed. Daniel J. Kevles and E. Leroy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Girard, J.Y., Y. Lafont, and R. Taylor. 1989. Proofs and Types. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goubault, E., ed. 2000. Geometry in Concurrency, Special issue, Mathematical Structures in Computer Science, Cambridge University Press., vol.10, n. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J. 1996. Full House. New York: Three Rivers Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gouyon, P.H., J.P. Henry, and J. Arnoud. 2002. Gene Avatars, The Neo-Darwinian Theory of Evolution. New York: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gsponer, J., and M. Madan Babu. 2009. The Rules of Disorder or Why Disorder Rules. Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology 99: 94–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hadjiargyrou, M., and N. Delihas. 2013. The Intertwining of Transposable Elements and Non-coding RNAs. International Journal of Molecular Sciences 14 (7): 13307–13328. https://doi.org/10.3390/ijms140713307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hebb, D. 1949. The Organization of Behavior. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesselink, Wim H. 2008. Computer Verification of Wiles’ Proof of Fermat’s Last Theorem. www.cs.rug.nl. Retrieved 2017-06-29.

  • Hilbert, D. 1898. The Foundations of Geometry. Trans. 1901. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1926. Über das Unendliche. Mathematische Annalen 95 (1): 161–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Islami, A., and G. Longo. 2017. Marriages of Mathematics and Physics: A Challenge for Biology. In The Necessary Western Conjunction to the Eastern Philosophy of Exploring the Nature of Mind and Life, ed. K. Matsuno et al. Special Issue, Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology 131: 179–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Israeli, N., and N. Goldenfeld. 2004. Computational Irreducibility and the Predictability of Complex Physical Systems. Physical Review Letters 92 (7): 074105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, F. 1970. La logique du vivant. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1974. Le modèle linguistique en biologie, Critique, XXX, 322.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, F., and J. Monod. 1961. Genetic Regulatory Mechanisms in the Synthesis of Proteins. Journal of Molecular Biology 3: 318–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kato, S., S.M. Lippman, K.T. Flaberty, and R. Kurrock. 2016. The Conundrum of Genetic “Drivers” in Benign Conditions. JNCI Journal of the National Cancer Institute 108 (8).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koppl, R., S. Kauffman, G. Longo, and T. Felin. 2015. Economy for a Creative World. Journal of Institutional Economics 11 (01): 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosman-Schwarback, Y. 2010. The Noether Theorems: Invariance and Conservation Laws in the Twentieth Century. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kowalchuk, G.A., M. Bruinsma, and J. van Veen. 2003. Assessing Responses of Soil Microorganisms to GM Plants. Trends in Ecology and Evolution 18: 403–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kreisel, G. 1982. Four Letters to G. L. http://www.di.ens.fr/users/longo/files/FourLettersKreisel.pdf.

  • Kupiec, J.J. 1983. A Probabilistic Theory for Cell Differentiation, Embryonic Mortality and DNA C-Value Paradox. Speculations in Science and Technology 6: 471–478.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., and D. Ross. 2008. Every Thing Must Go, Metaphysics Naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landauer, R. 1991. Information is Physical. Physics Today 44: 23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laskar, J. 1994. Large Scale Chaos in the Solar System. Astronomy and Astrophysics 287: L9–L12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leff, Harvey S., and Andrew F. Rex, eds. 1990. Maxwell’s Demon: Entropy, Information, Computing. Bristol: Adam-Hilger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lesne, A. 2007. The Discrete vs Continuous Controversy in Physics. Mathematical Structures in Computer Science 17 (2): 185–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Shannon Entropy: A Rigorous Notion at the Crossroads Between Probability, Information Theory, Dynamical Systems and Statistical Physics. Mathematical Structures in Computer Science 24 (3). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longo, G. 2004. Some Topologies for Computations. In Géométrie au XX siècle, 1930–2000. Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Incompletezza. In La Matematica, vol. 4, 219–262, Einaudi. Revised and translated: 2018. Interfaces of Incompleteness. In Systemics of Incompleteness and Quasi-Systems, ed. G. Minati, M. Abram, and E. Pessa. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011a. Reflections on Concrete Incompleteness. Philosophia Mathematica 19 (3): 255–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011b. Theorems as Constructive Visions. In ICMI 19 conference on Proof and Proving, Taipei, Taiwan, May 10–15, 2009, ed. Hanna, de Villiers. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015a. The Consequences of Philosophy. Glass-Bead, Web Journal. http://www.glass-bead.org/article/the-consequences-of-philosophy/?lang=enview.

  • ———. 2015b. Conceptual Analyses from a Grothendieckian Perspective: Reflections on Synthetic Philosophy of Contemporary Mathematics by Fernando Zalamea. In Speculations Web Journal. https://www.urbanomic.com/speculations_lo/.

  • ———. 2017. How Future Depends on Past Histories and Rare Events in Systems of Life. Foundations of Science: 1–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2018a. Information and causality: Mathematical reflections on Cancer biology. Organisms. Journal of Biological Sciences 2 (1): 83–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2018b. Complexity, Information and Diversity, in Science and in Democracy. To appear (see https://www.di.ens.fr/users/longo/download.html for a prelimnary version).

  • ———. 2018c. Letter to Alan Turing. In Theory, Culture and Society, Special Issue on Transversal Posthumanities, ed. Füller, Braidotti.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longo, G., and M. Montévil. 2014. Perspectives on Organisms: Biological Time, Symmetries and Singularities. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Longo, G., Catuscia Palamidessi, and Thierry Paul. 2010. Some Bridging Results and Challenges in Classical, Quantum and Computational Randomness. In Randomness Through Computation, ed. H. Zenil, 73–92. World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longo, G., P.A. Miquel, C. Sonnenschein, and A. Soto. 2012. Is Information a Proper Observable for Biological Organization? Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology 109 (3): 108–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lutz, E., and S. Ciliberto. 2015. Information: From Maxwell’s Demon to Landauer’s Eraser. Physics Today 69 (30).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lwoff, A. 1969. L’ordre biologique. Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mac Lane, S. 1970. Categories for the Working Mathematician. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mallat, S. 2016. Understanding Deep Convolutional Networks. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A 37: 20150203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mallat, S., and W.L. Hwang. 1992. Singularity detection and processing with wavelets. In IEEE Transactions on Information Theory, vol. 32, no. 2, March.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marinov, G.K., B.A. Williams, K. McCue, G.P. Schroth, J. Gertz, R.M. Myers, and B.J. Wold. 2014. From Single-Cell to Cell-Pool Transcriptomes: Stochasticity in Gene Expression and RNA Splicing. Genome Research 24: 496–510.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard-Smith, J. 1999. The Idea of Information in Biology. The Quarter Review of Biology 74: 495–400.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCulloch, W., and W. Pitts. 1943. A Logical Calculus of Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity. Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics 5 (4): 115–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. 1945. Phénomenologie de la perception. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R.C. 1990. Continuous-Time Finance. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monod, J. 1970. Le Hasard et la Nécessité. Paris: PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montévil, M., and M. Mossio. 2015. Closure of Constraints in Biological Organisation. Journal of Theoretical Biology 372: 179–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montévil, M., M. Mossio, A. Pocheville, and G. Longo. 2016. Theoretical Principles for Biology: Variation. Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology 122 (1): 36–50. Soto, Longo & Noble eds.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mouilleron, H., V. Delcourt, and X. Roucou. 2016. Death of a Dogma: Eukaryotic mRNAs Can Code for More Than One Protein. Nucleic Acids Research 44 (1): 14–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A., and H.A. Simon. 1976. Computer Science as Empirical Inquiry: Symbols and Search. Communications of the ACM 19 (3): 113–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. 2018. Alien Reasoning: Is a Major Change in Scientific Research Underway? Topoi. https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s11245-018-9557-1.

  • Onuchic, J., Z. Luthey-Schulten, and P. Wolynes. 1997. Theory of Protein Folding: The Energy Landscape Perspective. Annual Review of Physical Chemistry 48: 545–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paldi, A. 2003. Stochastic Gene Expression During Cell Differentiation: Order from Disorder? Cellular and Molecular Life Sciences 60: 1775–1779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pauling, L. 1987. Schrödinger Contribution to Chemistry and Biology. In Schrödinger: Centenary Celebration of a Polymath, ed. Kilmister. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pavesi, A., A. Vianelli, N. Chirico, Y. Bao, R. Belshaw, O. Blinkova, A. Firth, and D. Karlin. 2018. Overlapping Genes and the Protein they Encode Differ Significantly in Their Sequence Composition from Non-overlapping Genes. PLOS ONE 13 (10): e0202513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perret, N., and G. Longo. 2016. Reductionist Perspectives and the Notion of Information. Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology 122 (1): 11–15. Soto, Longo and Noble eds.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petitot, J. 2017. Elements of Neurogeometry. Functional Architectures of Vision, Lecture Notes in Morphogenesis. Cham: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pilyugin, S. 1999. Shadowing in Dynamical Systems. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramellini, P. 2002. L’informazione in biologia, 39-48. In La Nuova Scienza, La società dell’informazione, ed. U. Colombo and G. Lanzavecchia, vol. 3. Milano: Libri Scheiwiller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riemann, B. 1854. On the Hypothesis Which Lie at the Basis of Geometry (Engl. by W. Clifford, Nature, 1973).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rogers, H. 1967. Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability. New York: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenblatt, F. 1958. The Perceptron: A Probabilistic Model for Information Storage and Organization in the Brain. Psychological Review. 65 (6): 386–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rovelli, C. 2004. Quantum Gravity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rugh, W.J. 1981. Nonlinear System Theory: The Volterra/Wiener Approach. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saigusa, T., A. Tero, T. Nakagaki, and Y. Kuramoto. 2008. Amoebae Anticipate Periodic Events. Phyiscal Review Letters. 100: 018101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarti, A., G. Citti, and D. Piotrowski. 2018. Differential Heterogenesis and the Emergence of Semiotic Function. Semiotica, in press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger, E. 1944. What is Life? The Physical Aspect of the Living Cell. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott, D. 1982. Domains for Denotational Semantics. In Proceedings ICALP 82, LNCS 140. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searls, D.B. 1992. The Linguistics of DNA. American Scientist 80: 579–591.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seligmann, H., and D.D. Pollock. 2004. The Ambush Hypothesis: Hidden Stop Codons Prevent Off-Frame Gene Reading. DNA and Cell Biology 23: 701–705.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shannon, C. 1948. A Mathematical Theory of Communication. Bell Systems Technical Journal 27: 279–423, 623–656.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sifakis, J. 2011. Modeling Real-Time Systems-Challenges and Work Directions. In EMSOFT01, Tahoe City, October 2001. Lecture Notes in Computer Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simondon, G. 1989. L’individuation psychique et collective. Paris: Aubier, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sonnenschein, C., and A.M. Soto. 1999. The Society of Cells: Cancer and Control of Cell Proliferation. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. The Death of the Cancer Cell. Cancer Research 71: 4334–4337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. The Aging of the 2000 and 2011 Hallmarks of Cancer Reviews: A Critique. Journal of Biosciences 38: 651–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sontag, D. 1990. Mathematical Control Theory. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Soto, A.M., and C. Sonnenschein. 2010. Environmental Causes of Cancer: Endocrine Disruptors as Carcinogens. Nature Reviews Endocrinology 6 (7): 363–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Why Is It That Despite Signed Capitulations, the War on Cancer is Still on? Organisms. Journal of Biological Sciences 1: 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soto, A.M., G. Longo, and D. Noble, eds. 2016. From the Century of the Genome to the Century of the Organism: New Theoretical Approaches. Special issue. Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology 122 (1): 1–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Supiot, A. 2017. Governance by Numbers. New York: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. 1936. On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society. (Series 2) 42: 230–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1950. Computing Machinery and Intelligence. Mind 50: 433–460; also in Boden 1990, Collected Works (Volume 1).

    Google Scholar 

  • Venter, C. 2010. We Have Learned Nothing from the Genome. Der Spiegel, July 29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Versteg, R. 2014. Cancer: Tumours Outside the Mutation Box. Nature 506: 438–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Violi, P. 2016. How our Bodies Become Us: Embodiment, Semiosis and Intersubjectivity. Journal of Cognitive Semiotics IV (1): 57–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Uexküll, J. 1934. A Theory of Meaning, reprinted in Semiotica (1982) 42–1, 25–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walras, L. 1874. Théorie mathématique de la richesse sociale. Paris: Corbaz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, R. 2014. Coming Full Circle – Form Endless Complexity to Simplicity and Back Again. Cell 157: 267–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. 1949. Philosophy of Mathematics and of Natural Sciences, 1927, English Trans. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1953. Axiomatic Versus Constructive Procedures in Mathematics (a cura di T. Tonietti) The Mathematical Intelligence, vol. 7, no. 4. New York: Springer, (reprinted) 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiener, N. 1948. Cybernetics or Control and Communication in the Animal and the Machine. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1954. The Human Use of Human Beings: Cybernetics and Society. London: Da Capo Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfram, S. 2002. A New Kind of Science. Champaign: Wolfram Media Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. The Importance of Universal Computation. In A. Turing, His Work and Impact, ed. Cooper. Waltham: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zalamea, F. 2012. Synthetic Philosophy of Contemporary Mathematics. Cambridge: Urbanomic/Sequence Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zeilinger, A. 2004. Why the Quantum? ‘It’ from ‘Bit’? A Participatory Universe? Three Far-Reaching Challenges from John Archibald Wheeler and Their Relation to Experiment. In Science and Ultimate Reality: Quantum Theory, Cosmology and Computation, ed. J. Barrow, P. Davies, and C. Harper, 201–220. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zorzi, M. 2016. Quantum Lambda Calculi: A Foundational Perspective. Mathematical Structures in Computer Science 26 (7): 1107–1119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Inigo Wilkins made a critical and competent reading of a preliminary version of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Giuseppe Longo .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Longo, G. (2020). Information at the Threshold of Interpretation: Science as Human Construction of Sense. In: Bertolaso, M., Sterpetti, F. (eds) A Critical Reflection on Automated Science. Human Perspectives in Health Sciences and Technology, vol 1. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-25001-0_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics