Skip to main content

Individual Sacrifices and the Flourishing of Ecosystems

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 245 Accesses

Abstract

Even without direct negative impacts, wild nature, with death, diseases, predation etc., can seem discomforting to humans. Why should humans, therefore, care for nature if it is full of seemingly evil elements? This has been identified as a potential problem for developing the motivation to protect the natural environment, and one proposition to overcome this threat has been an ethical theory developed by, i.a., Holmes Rolston, who proposes to look at ecological transactions from a systemic perspective at which all such exchanges acquire a productive, rather than destructive, function. However, such approach, though seemingly efficacious in removing human anxieties, effaces a whole domain of experience connected to the individual perspective on the world. An alternative is proposed, which offers a more tragic and ambivalent perspective of nature and of the place of an individual in it. While in such a perspective it is difficult to build an ethics of respect for nature based on values, it is showed that both meaning and aesthetic appreciation are much more tolerant of ambivalence and the tragic. In fact, in the latter frameworks, such qualities can lead to a development of a more nuanced and profound forms of appreciation of nature.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For an in-depth discussion of the controversy and interesting philosophical ideas on the issue see Klaver et al. (2002).

  2. 2.

    But see e.g. Keulartz (2003) and Holland (2011) who both point out the strong Christian motives underneath Rolston’s ideas. This should not be surprising, given that Rolston is an ordained minister of the Presbyterian Church. Still, many of his ideas, even those relating to theodicy, can be intelligible in a secular worldview and no strong commitment to Christian beliefs seems necessary to embrace his philosophy.

  3. 3.

    For an extensive study of this subject that includes not just a summary of all the existing attempts to address the problem of evil in environmentalism, but also an insightful discussion of the relationship between theological and ecological theodicies, see Kowalsky (2006).

  4. 4.

    Kowalsky (2006) notes that Rolston hardly ever speaks about ‘evil’ in nature, and instead uses the term ‘disvalues’, at least in the works that are directed towards the environmental community.

  5. 5.

    Another interesting direction to pursue would be to seek inspiration in communitarian political theory. In communitarian writings of MacIntyre (e.g. 1981), Sandel (1982), Taylor (e.g. 1989), Etzioni (2014a; 2014b; 2014c), and others we can find not just a focus on the importance of community, the common good, and the role that community plays in individual development, but also close attention to the appropriate kinds of relations existing between individuals and the community to which they belong. I will return to this point briefly in the next chapter. However, in this book I will not give a thorough analysis, since this would require first a general reflection on the applicability of these ideas to environmental issues raised by concern with animals and environments. Such preliminary work would take us too far from the topic at hand, though it remains an interesting and potentially promising direction to pursue.

References

  • Abbey, Edward. 1971. Desert Solitaire. A Season in the Wilderness. New York: Ballantine Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brady, Emily. The Sublime in Modern Philosophy: Aesthetics, Ethics, and Nature. Cambridge University Press, 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callicott, J. Baird. 1980. Animal liberation: a triangular affair. Environmental Ethics 2: 311–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callicott, J. Baird, Jonathan Parker, Jordan Batson, Nathan Bell, Keith Brown and Samantha Moss. 2011. The other in a sand county Almanac: Aldo Leopold’s animals and his wild-animal ethic. Environmental Ethics 33 (2): 115–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Etzioni, Amitai. 2014a. Common good. The Encyclopedia of Political Thought 603–610. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118474396.wbept0178.

  • Etzioni, Amitai. 2014b. Communitarianism. The Encyclopedia of Political Thought 620–625. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118474396.wbept0184.

  • Etzioni, Amitai. 2014c. Community. The Encyclopedia of Political Thought 625–640. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118474396.wbept0185.

  • Gould, Stephen Jay. 1982. Nonmoral nature. Natural History 91 (2): 19–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hettinger, Ned. 2010. Animal beauty, ethics, and environmental preservation. Environmental Ethics 32 (2): 115–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holland, Alan. 2009. Darwin and the meaning in life. Environmental Values 18 (4): 503–516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holland, Alan. 2011. Why it is important to take account of history. Ethics, Policy & Environment 14 (3): 377–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holland, Alan. 2012. The value space of meaningful relations. In Human-Environment Relations: Transformative Values in Theory and Practice, ed. Brady, Emily and Pauline Phemister, 3–15. Springer Science & Business Media.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan, William R.I.I.I. 2003. The Sunflower Forest: Ecological Restoration and the New Communion with Nature. Berkeley: University of California.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keulartz, Jozef. 2003. Rolston. A Contemporary Physico-Theologian. In Is Nature Ever Evil?, ed. Drees and Willem B, 90–93. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, Thomas, and Vera Vicenzotti. 2014. A historical and systematic survey of European perceptions of wilderness. Environmental Values 23 (4): 443–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klaver, Irene, Jozef Keulartz, and Henk Van Den Belt. 2002. Born to be wild. Environmental Ethics 24 (1): 3–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kowalsky, Nathan. 2006. Beyond Natural Evil. Ph.D. Dissertation, Katholieke Universiteit Leuven

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Blanc, Jill. 2001. A mystical response to disvalue in nature. Philosophy Today 45 (3): 254–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leopold, Aldo. 1970. A Sand County Almanac. New York: Ballantine.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, Jack. 1986. Fierce Green Fire: Remembering Aldo Leopold. EPA Journal 12: 26–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1981. After Virtue. A Study in Moral Theory. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ouderkirk, Wayne. 1999. Can nature be evil?: Rolston, disvalue, and theodicy. Environmental Ethics 21 (2): 135–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plumwood, Val. 2012. Eye of the Crocodile. Canberra: Australian National University E Press. https://doi.org/10.22459/EC.11.2012.

  • Rolston, Holmes I.I.I. 1979. Can and ought we to follow nature? Environmental Ethics 1 (1): 7–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolston, Holmes I.I.I. 1983. Values gone wild. Inquiry 26 (2): 191–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolston, Holmes III. 1991. Environmental ethics : Values in and duties to the natural world. In Ecology, Economics, Ethics: The Broken Circle, ed. Bormann, F. Herbert and Stephen R. Kellert, 73–96. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rolston, Holmes I.I.I. 1992a. Disvalues in nature. The Monist 75 (2): 250–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolston, Holmes I.I.I. 1992b. Ethical responsibilities toward wildlife. Journal of the American Veterinary Medical Association 200: 615–622.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rolston, Holmes I.I.I. 2015. Rediscovering and rethinking Leopold’s green fire. Environmental Ethics 37 (1): 45–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, Michael J. 1982. Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scoville, J. Michael. 2013. Historical environmental values. Environmental Ethics 35 (1): 7–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, Peter. 1975. Animal Liberation. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1989. Sources of the Self. The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tillich, Paul. 1952. The Courage to Be. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, Lynn Jr. 1967. The historical roots of our ecologic crisis. Science 155: 1203–1207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worster, Donald. 1977. Nature’s Economy. The Roots of Ecology. San Francisco: Sierra Club Books.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mateusz Tokarski .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Tokarski, M. (2019). Individual Sacrifices and the Flourishing of Ecosystems. In: Hermeneutics of Human-Animal Relations in the Wake of Rewilding. The International Library of Environmental, Agricultural and Food Ethics, vol 30. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-18971-6_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics