Skip to main content

The Eighteenth and Early Nineteenth Centuries: The Age of Continuity

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Continuous, the Discrete and the Infinitesimal in Philosophy and Mathematics

Part of the book series: The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science ((WONS,volume 82))

  • 487 Accesses

Abstract

The leading practitioner of the calculus, indeed the leading mathematician of the eighteenth century, was Leonhard Euler (1707–83). While Euler’s genius has been described as being of “equal strength in both of the main currents of mathematics, the continuous and the discrete”, philosophically he was a thoroughgoing synechist. Rejecting Leibnizian monadism, he favoured the Cartesian doctrine that the universe is filled with a continuous ethereal fluid and upheld the wave theory of light over the corpuscular theory propounded by Newton.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Bell (1965), Vol I, p. 152

  2. 2.

    Euler (1843), Vol 1, pp. 83–84.

  3. 3.

    Ibid., pp. 254–5.

  4. 4.

    Euler (1843), Vol. II, p. 39.

  5. 5.

    Ibid., p. 39–40.

  6. 6.

    Ibid., p. 41.

  7. 7.

    Ibid., pp. 50–51.

  8. 8.

    But here Euler seems to have missed the point that, if from the assumption that bodies are extended it follows logically that they are unextended, then it can be concluded that bodies are unextended. This is an instance of the logical tautology (p¬ p) → ¬ p.

  9. 9.

    Quoted from Euler’s Institutiones of 1755 in Kline (1972), p 429.

  10. 10.

    This is a reigning principle of smooth infinitesimal analysis, see Chap. 10 below. See also Lawvere (2011).

  11. 11.

    Weyl (1950), p. 92.

  12. 12.

    Euler , Principia motus fluidorum and Principes généraux du mouvement des fluides, 1755. Summarized in Dugas (1988), pp. 301–304.

  13. 13.

    Kline (1972), p. 340.

  14. 14.

    Art. Function, Encyclopedia Britannica, Eleventh Edition, 1910–11.

  15. 15.

    Ibid.

  16. 16.

    Boyer(1959), p. 243.

  17. 17.

    Ibid., p. 247.

  18. 18.

    Quoted in Boyer (1959), pp. 248.

  19. 19.

    Quoted ibid., pp. 247–8.

  20. 20.

    Ibid.,p. 250.

  21. 21.

    Maclaurin , Treatise of Fluxions , Preface, in Ewald (1999) From Kant to Hilbert, p. 93.

  22. 22.

    Ibid, pp. 107–8

  23. 23.

    Ibid., p. 108.

  24. 24.

    Ibid.

  25. 25.

    Boyer (1959), p. 251.

  26. 26.

    First introduced in 1715 by the English mathematician Brook Taylor (1685–1731).

  27. 27.

    Hence the term derivative. The notation f ‘(x) was also introduced by Lagrange.

  28. 28.

    Carnot (1832), p. 14.

  29. 29.

    Ibid., p. 33

  30. 30.

    Ibid., p. 34.

  31. 31.

    See below.

  32. 32.

    Carnot (1832), pp. 101–2.

  33. 33.

    Jesseph (1993), p. 37.

  34. 34.

    Ibid., p. 57. The doctrine of perceptible minima is, of course, subject to the same objections that had been raised against previous attempts at analyzing extension in terms of atoms.

  35. 35.

    Berkeley (1960), §124.

  36. 36.

    According to Jesseph (1993, p. 67), Berkeley was largely unaware of the tradition of “mathematical atomism ” in ancient and medieval philosophy.

  37. 37.

    Berkeley (1960), §130. It is of interest here to note that the final sentence of this quotation is an explicit rejection of the concept of nilpotent infinitesimal which had been defended by Nieuwentijdt against Leibniz . 250 years later, that concept was to be revived in smooth infinitesimal analysis. See Chap. 10 below.

  38. 38.

    Ibid., §132.

  39. 39.

    Berkeley , De Motu, §61. In Ewald (1999).

  40. 40.

    Likely the astronomer Edmund Halley (1656–1742).

  41. 41.

    By “difference” Berkeley means “differential”.

  42. 42.

    Berkeley , Analyst, §7. In Ewald (1999).

  43. 43.

    Ibid., §35.

  44. 44.

    Ibid., §§5, 6.

  45. 45.

    Ibid., §22.

  46. 46.

    Cajori (1919), p. 89.

  47. 47.

    Furley (1967), Ch. 10.

  48. 48.

    Ibid., p. 137.

  49. 49.

    Hume (1962), II, 1.

  50. 50.

    Ibid. But presumably the idea of a grain of sand is separable into the ideas “grain” and “sand”.

  51. 51.

    Ibid.

  52. 52.

    Ibid.

  53. 53.

    Ibid.

  54. 54.

    Ibid., II, 2.

  55. 55.

    Ibid., II, 3.

  56. 56.

    Ibid., II, 4.

  57. 57.

    Furley (1967) p. 142.

  58. 58.

    Körner (1955), p. 94.

  59. 59.

    Kant (1964), p. 204.

  60. 60.

    Ibid., p. 203.

  61. 61.

    Ibid., p. 203.

  62. 62.

    Ibid., p. 208.

  63. 63.

    Ibid., p. 270.

  64. 64.

    Kant (1970), p. 53. Cf. Critique of Pure Reason, Observation on the Second Antinomy:

    Though it may be true that when a whole, made up of substances, is thought by the pure understanding alone, we must, prior to all composition, of it, have the simple…

  65. 65.

    Ibid., p. 53.

  66. 66.

    Kant’s thus echoes Leibniz – with the exception that Leibniz’s monads were not physical.

  67. 67.

    Physical Monadology , Proposition II, in Kant (1992).

  68. 68.

    Physical Monadology , Scholium to Prop. IV.

  69. 69.

    Ibid., Scholium to Prop. V.

  70. 70.

    I am grateful to my colleague Lorne Falkenstein for pointing this out to me.

  71. 71.

    Kant (1970), p. 55.

  72. 72.

    Ibid., p.54.

  73. 73.

    Kant (1977), p. 83.

  74. 74.

    Ibid.

  75. 75.

    As already observed, Kant would probably maintain the truth of the Thesis in that event.

  76. 76.

    Kant (1964), p. 448.

  77. 77.

    Ibid., p. 459.

  78. 78.

    Hegel (1961), p. 204.

  79. 79.

    Ibid., p. 200.

  80. 80.

    Ibid.

  81. 81.

    Ibid.

  82. 82.

    Ibid., pp. 202–3.

  83. 83.

    Ibid., p. 204.

  84. 84.

    Ibid., p. 211.

  85. 85.

    Ibid., p. 213.

  86. 86.

    Ibid., p. 214.

  87. 87.

    Ibid., p. 214.

  88. 88.

    Russell (1964), p. 346.

  89. 89.

    Quoted in Dauben (1979), p. 170.

  90. 90.

    Quoted ibid., p. 221.

  91. 91.

    By Quantum Hegel means determinate Quantity , that is, Quantity of a definite size.

  92. 92.

    Hegel (1961), p. 269.

  93. 93.

    Ibid., pp. 269–70.

  94. 94.

    Ibid., p. 271.

  95. 95.

    Ibid., p. 274.

  96. 96.

    Ibid.

  97. 97.

    Ibid., p. 275–6.

  98. 98.

    Ibid., p. 280.

  99. 99.

    Ibid., p. 280–1. Hegel regards as highly dubious the procedure of omitting terms in a sum because of their “relative smallness”.

  100. 100.

    Ibid., p. 281–2.

  101. 101.

    Ibid., p. 287.

  102. 102.

    Ibid.

  103. 103.

    Ibid.

  104. 104.

    I.e., the differential triangle .

  105. 105.

    Ibid., p. 287–8.

  106. 106.

    Hegel distinguishes between extensive and intensive magnitude . When a magnitude is regarded as a multiplicity, it is extensive; regarded as a unity, it is intensive .

  107. 107.

    Ibid., p. 288.

  108. 108.

    Hegel ’s disciple Karl Marx was also preoccupied by the infinitesimal calculus. See Marx (1983).

Bibliography

  • Bell, E.T. 1965. Men of Mathematics. Vol. 2. Harmondsworth/Middlesex: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley, G. 1960. Principles of Human Knowledge. New York: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, C. 1959. The History of the Calculus and Its Conceptual Development. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cajori, F. 1919. A Short History of the concepts of Limits and Fluxions. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnot, L. 1832. Reflexions sur la Métaphysique du Calcul Infinitesimal. Trans. Browell. Parker, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dauben, J. 1979. Georg Cantor: His Mathematics and Philosophy of the Infinite. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dugas, R. 1988. A History of Mechanics. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Euler, L. 1843. Letters of Euler on Different Subjects in Natural Philosophy : Addressed to a German Princess; with Notes, and a Life of Euler / by David Brewster; Containing a Glossary of Gcientific Term[s] with Additional Notes, by John Griscom. New York: Harper and Brothers. Reprint by Forgotten Books, 2012.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ewald, W. 1999. From Kant to Hilbert, A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics. Vol. I and II. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Furley, D. 1967. Two Studies in the Greek Atomists. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. 1961. Science of Logic. Trans. Johnston & Struthers. Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 1962. A Treatise of Human Nature, Book I. London: Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jesseph, D. 1993. Berkeley’s Philosophy of Mathematics. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. 1964. Critique of Pure Reason. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1970. Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science. Trans. Ellington. Bobbs-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1977. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. Trans. Carus, revsd. Ellington. Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1992. In Theoretical Philosophy 1755–1770, ed. Watford and Meerbote. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kline, M. 1972. Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times. Vol. 3 volumes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Körner, S. 1955. Kant. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawvere, F.W. 2011. Euler’s continuum functorially vindicated. In Vintage Enthusiasms: Essays in Honour of John L. Bell, ed. D. Devidi, P. Clark, and M. Hallett. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, K. 1983. Mathematical Manuscripts. Clapham/London: New Park Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. 1964. The Principles of Mathematics. London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. 1950. Space-Time-Matter. Trans. Brose, H. Dover. (English translation of Raum, Zeit, Materie, Springer, 1918.)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Bell, J.L. (2019). The Eighteenth and Early Nineteenth Centuries: The Age of Continuity. In: The Continuous, the Discrete and the Infinitesimal in Philosophy and Mathematics. The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, vol 82. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-18707-1_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics