Skip to main content

Legislation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 397 Accesses

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 128))

Abstract

The chapter purports to cast some light on the basic ideas of the realistic theory of legislation. It will be, accordingly, a place for rehearsing many of the theoretical theses advanced, and argued for, in the preceding chapters.

Here, then, in the very cradle of legislative empire grew up another power, in words the instrument of the former, in reality continually its censor and not infrequently its successful rival

—J. Bentham (1977)

The conscientious, intelligent judge will consider government a sort of orchestra, in which, in symphonies authorized by the people, the courts and the legislature each play their parts

—J. Frank (1949a)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See, e.g, Bentham (1789); Filangieri (1780–1785). On juridical Enlightenment, see e.g. Tarello (1976), Comanducci (1978), pp. 7–24; Postema (1986), parts II and III; Lieberman (1989), chs. 2, 13.

  2. 2.

    Waldron (1999b), at 1, 2, we read: “legislation and legislatures have a bad name in legal and political philosophy, a name sufficiently disreputable to cast doubt on their credentials as respectable sources of law […] I want us to see the process of legislation – at its best – as something like the following: the representatives of the community come together to settle solemnly and explicitly on common schemes and measures that can stand in the name of them all, and they do so in a way that openly acknowledges and respects […] the inevitable differences of opinion and principle among them”; Waldron (1999a), part I.

  3. 3.

    See, e.g.: Wintgens (2002), including essays by L. Wintgens, L. D. Eriksson, K. Pietilä, S. Eng, C. Dahlman, H. Tolonen, K. Tuori, A. Verhoeven, W. Voermans, and H. Winter; Wintgens (2006), pp. 1–25; Wintgens (2012), p. 7: “Current legal theory is premised on the central role of the judge in contemporary legal systems. Although this evolution has contributed much to a vibrant understanding of law, it has also left the role of the legislator largely ignored and under-theorised. Legal theory routinely takes the law as ‘just there’, and limits its theoretical undertakings to law as a ‘given’. Law, it claims, is the result of political decision-making. But once law comes into force, it can be somehow miraculously separated from politics. And the realm of politics is impure – unlike law’s ‘neutral’ and ‘objective’ methods of reasoning and decision-making”. It goes without saying that legisprudence à la Wintgens is a normative enterprise: starting from the Kantian premise of individuals’ moral autonomy and freedom, it purports to establish the right principles of legislation and, on the basis thereof, the duties legislatures ought to fulfil to be legitimate.

  4. 4.

    Cohen (1949–1950), pp. 886–897. According to the Black’s Law Dictionary, 7th ed., “Legisprudence” is “The systematic analysis of statutes within the framework of jurisprudential philosophies about the role and nature of law”.

  5. 5.

    Waldron and Wintgens seem to be aware of legal realism, so far as statutory interpretation is concerned. See e.g. Waldron (1999b), p. 10; Wintgens (2006), p. 21 ss. However, as we will see later on (Sect. 11.4 below), Waldron apparently resists to a full endorsing of realism.

  6. 6.

    See Waldron (1999b), ch. 2.

  7. 7.

    See, e.g., Holmes (1897), p. 457 ff.; Frank (1930), Llewellyn (1930, 1931), Kelsen (1945), p. 123 ff.; Ross (1946, 1958), Tarello (1962), Castignone (1974), Olivecrona (1971), Twining (1985), Leiter (2007), Part I; Millard (2008), pp. 177–189; Guastini (2011b), pp. 138–161; Llewellyn (2011). On philosophical legal realism, see also Chap. 1, Sect. 1.1, above.

  8. 8.

    In its more encompassing meaning, “legislation” refers to the whole domain of the so-called written law (ius scriptum), i.e., the law provided with an authoritative, fixed, formulation, as opposed to unwritten law (ius non scriptum), like background implicit principles and the rationes decidendi making up the reservoir of judicial precedents (on which, see Chap. 9, Sect. 9.3, above). Here, I will leave this larger meaning aside, focussing instead on the stricter meaning considered in the text.

  9. 9.

    For the present reconstruction of the realistic theory of legislation I considered the following works: Bentham (2010), p. 161ff., 169ff., 174ff., 227 ff.; Bentham (1977), p. 89 ff., 137 ff.; Austin (1885), p. 525 ff., 620 ff., 989 ff., 1028 ff.; Gray (1909), p. 145 ff.; Frank (1930), p. 186 ff., 310–311; Radin (1930), p. 863 ff.; Cohen (1933), p. 230 ff.; Kelsen (1941), p. 271 ff.; Kelsen (1945), p. 134 ff.; Frank (1949b), pp. 290–291, 292 ff.; Ross (1958), chs. III and IV; Kelsen (1960), chs. V and VIII; Llewellyn (1960), p. 521 ff.; Tarello (1980), chs. II and VIII; Troper (2003), pp. 98–112; Dworkin (1986), ch. 1–3, 9; Eskridge and Frickey (1998), p. 240 ff., 569 ff.; Chiassoni (1999a), p. 21 ff.; Chiassoni (2011), ch. 2; Dworkin (2011), Part II; Llewellyn (2011), p. 119 ff.; Guastini (2011a), Parts I and V. See also Chaps. 3, 4, and 5 above.

  10. 10.

    Autocratic legislators in fact can make known their mind about the “proper” meaning of their statutes by means, say, of declarations accompanying the enacted text, or released through other channels of institutional communication.

  11. 11.

    See Chap. 5, Sects. 5.2 and 5.4 above.

  12. 12.

    Waldron (1999b), p. 27.

  13. 13.

    On the Gricean picture of ordinary conversation see Chap. 3, Sect. 3.5 above.

  14. 14.

    See the complementary remarks below. See also Chap. 5, Sects. 5.2 and 5.4 above.

  15. 15.

    See Chap. 5, Sect. 5.2, and Chap. 10, Sect. 10.2.2, above.

  16. 16.

    By the way, the thesis is in turn a specification of the more sweeping thesis about the general indeterminacy, in Kelsenian terms, of any ‘superior norm’ whatsoever. See, e.g., Kelsen (1960), ch. VIII.

  17. 17.

    On legal indeterminacy, see also Chap. 10, Sect. 10.2 above.

  18. 18.

    See Chap. 5, Sect. 5.2, above.

References

  • Austin J (1885) Lectures on jurisprudence or the philosophy of positive law, 5th edn. Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham J (1789) Introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. In: Burns JH, Hart HLA (eds) University of London/The Athlone Press, London, 1970

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham J (1977) A comment on the commentaries. In: Burns JH, Hart HLA (eds) A comment on the commentaries and a fragment on government. University of London/The Athlone Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham J (2010) In: Schofield P (ed) Of the limits of the Penal Branch of jurisprudence. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Castignone S (1974) La macchina del diritto. Il realismo giuridico in Svezia. Comunità, Milano

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiassoni P (1999a) L’ineluttabile scetticismo della “scuola genovese”. In: Comanducci P, Guastini R (eds) Analisi e diritto 1998. Ricerche di giurisprudenza analitica. Giappichelli, Torino, pp 21–76

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiassoni P (2011) Técnicas de interpretación jurídica. Breviario para juristas. Marcial Pons, Madrid-Barcelona-Buenos Aires

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen FS (1933 [1959]) Ethical systems and legal ideals. An essay on the foundations of legal criticism. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen J (1949–1950) Towards realism in legisprudence. Yale Law J 59:886–897

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Comanducci P (1978) L’illuminismo giuridico. Il Mulino, Bologna

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1986) Law’s empire. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (2011) Justice for Hedgehogs. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Eskridge W, Frickey P (1998) Cases and materials on legislation. Statutes and the creation of public policy. West, St. Paul

    Google Scholar 

  • Filangieri G (1780–1785) La scienza della legislazione. Grimaldi, Napoli, p 2003

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank J (1930) Law and the modern mind. Stevens & Sons, VI Printing, London, p 1949

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank J (1949a) Courts on trial. Myth and reality in American justice. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank J (1949b [1930]) Notes on fictions. In: Frank J (ed) Law and the modern mind, Sixth Printing. Stevens, London, pp 312–322

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray JC (1909) The nature and sources of law. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Guastini R (2011a) Interpretare e argomentare. Giuffrè, Milano

    Google Scholar 

  • Guastini R (2011b) Rule-Scepticism restated. In: Green L, Leiter B (eds) Oxford studies in philosophy of law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 138–161

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Holmes OW Jr (1897) The path of the law. Harv Law Rev 10:457–478

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (1941 [1957a]) The pure theory of law and analytical jurisprudence. In: Kelsen H (ed) What is justice? Justice, law, and politics in the mirror of science. University of California Press, Berkeley, pp 266–286

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (1945) General theory of law and state. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (1960) Reine Rechtslehre, 2nd edn. Deuticke Wien [eng. tr. The pure theory of law. The University of California Press, Berkeley, and Los Angeles, 1967]

    Google Scholar 

  • Leiter B (2007) Naturalizing jurisprudence. Essays on American legal realism and naturalism in legal philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman D (1989) The province of legislation determined. Legal theory in eighteenth-century Britain. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Llewellyn KN (1930) A realistic jurisprudence – the next step. Columbia Law Rev 30:431–467

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Llewellyn KN (1931) Some realism about realism – responding to Dean Pound. Harv Law Rev 44:1222–1264

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Llewellyn KN (1960) The common law tradition. Deciding appeals. Little, Brown & C, Boston-Toronto

    Google Scholar 

  • Llewellyn KN (2011) The theory of rules. Edited and with an introduction by F. Schauer. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Millard E (2008) Positivisme logique et réalisme juridique. Analisi e Diritto:177–189

    Google Scholar 

  • Olivecrona K (1971) Law as fact, 2nd edn. Stevens & Sons, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Postema GJ (1986) Bentham and the common law tradition. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Radin R (1930) Statutory interpretation. Harv Law Rev 43:863–885

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross A (1946) Towards a realistic jurisprudence. A criticism of the dualism in law. Munksgaard, Copenhagen

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross A (1958) On law and justice. Stevens & Sons, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarello G (1962) Il realismo giuridico Americano. Giuffrè, Milano

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarello G (1976) Storia della cultura giuridica moderna. I. Assolutismo e codificazione del diritto. Il Mulino, Bologna

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarello G (1980) L’interpretazione della legge. Giuffrè, Milano

    Google Scholar 

  • Troper M (2003) La philosophie du droit. Presses Universitaires de France, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Twining W (1985) Karl Llewellyn and the Realist Movement. Reprinted with Postscript. Weidenfeld and Nicolson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron J (1999a) Law and disagreement. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron J (1999b) The dignity of legislation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Chiassoni, P. (2019). Legislation. In: Interpretation without Truth. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 128. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-15590-2_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-15590-2_11

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-15588-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-15590-2

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics