Skip to main content

Abduction: Enhancing Knowledge with an Ignorance-Based Reasoning

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Ignorant Cognition

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 46))

  • 336 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, by highlighting the role of abduction in the scientific methodology, I will proceed to describe the function of ignorance in its structure, deeming it as an invaluable resource for the performance of this kind of ampliative reasoning. Abduction can indeed be described as “the fundamental problem of contemporary epistemology”, as proposed by Hintikka (1998), for some good reasons. The high formal flexibility and cognitive salience of abduction vastly depend on the role that ignorance plays in its formulation: abduction indeed represents an ampliative inference that preserves the agent’s ignorance and also allows the expansion of the agent’s knowledge. Thus, I will distinguish between the preservation of ignorance implied in the selective model of abduction and an enhancement of knowledge through ignorance that is provided by the generation of a new hypothesis in the creative abduction. Furthermore, I will refer to the difference between selective and creative abduction to spell out two kinds of ignored possibilities that are relevant for chance-discovery, highlighting the importance of “understanding the meaning of an impending phenomenon as a chance” as a chance-discovery activity driven by the agent’s ignorance.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Abduction can be said to expand the agent’s knowledge when (1) the knowledge-enhancing effect is at play and so the fruit of abduction is not potential knowledge but just knowledge (think of the Galilean thought experiment concerning falling bodies), and (2) when the guessed hypothesis (so potentially endowed with knowledge content) is accepted because it is evaluated (for example empirically).

  2. 2.

    The multifarious character of cognition is also testified by Peirce’s conviction that iconicity hybridates logicality: the sentential aspects of symbolic disciplines like logic or algebra coexist with model-based features—iconic. Sentential features like symbols and conventional rules are intertwined with the spatial configuration, like in the case of “compound conventional signs” (written natural languages are concerned by iconic aspects too). What is called sentential abduction is in reality far from being strongly separated from model-based aspects: iconicity is always present in human reasoning, even if often hidden and implicit.

  3. 3.

    \(K^*\) is an accessible successor of K to the degree that an agent has the know-how to construct it in a timely way; i.e., in ways that are of service in the attainment of targets linked to K. For example if I want to know how to spell ‘accommodate’, and have forgotten, then my target can’t be hit on the basis of K, what I now know. But I might go to my study and consult the dictionary. This is \(K^*\). It solves a problem originally linked to K.

  4. 4.

    A detailed illustration of the AKM schema is given in Magnani (2009, chapter two, subsection 2.1.3).

  5. 5.

    cf. Woods (2013, chapter ten).

  6. 6.

    I need to remark here that minimality and consistency aren’t requirements of the GW-model but can be legitimately added to its discussion.

  7. 7.

    As I will delineate better in the following section, what I called “ignorance-that” refers to specific ignorances the agent is aware of, against a broader kind of ignorance the agent is not aware of. In spite of the similarities, it does not relate to the difference between knowing-that and knowing-how.

  8. 8.

    The distinction between off-line and on-line thinking is analyzed in detail in Magnani (2009, subsection 3.6.5, pp. 189–193). Some authors have raised doubts about the on-line/off-line distinction on the grounds that no thinking agent is ever wholly on-line or wholly off-line. I think this distinction is at least useful from an epistemological perspective as a way of theoretically illustrating different cognitive levels in human and animal cognition. It must be kept in mind that the theoretical distinctions between types of abduction are meant to frame the main traits of each type, but they are not necessarily mutually exclusive and different analyses may highlight different kinds of abduction at play in a same process. Sentential abduction refers to the possibility of working on sentences, be them expressed in logical or verbal language, and it is hence more closely connected to traditional logical studies. Nevertheless, the iconic dimension is never that far out: whereas the semantic understanding and appraisal of a sentence concern sentential abduction, the visual or auditive recognition of the signs expressing it rather involves a model-based approach to the process. Not to mention the language-forming capabilities afforded by diagrams, dicisigns, and icons. Peirce himself robustly exploited diagrammatic aspects of reasoning in his own research on logic: his invention of existential graphs is very well-known.

  9. 9.

    Cf. the article “The proper treatment of hypotheses: a preliminary chapter, toward an examination of Hume’s argument against miracles, in its logic and in its history” [1901] (in Peirce 1966, p. 692).

  10. 10.

    Although the notion of representation can be philosophically considered as “emptied” to a certain extent, I decided to maintain it for two main reasons: the contingent one, is to adhere to Millikan’s authoritative lexicon as far as animal cognition is concerned; the more essential one is that this reflection belongs to the model-based reasoning framework, by which a model is used in order to achieve a goal. Representations, as models, do represent a target, and even if the same process can be conveyed by concepts such as “structural coupling of inner and outer systems,” I feel that the notion of representation better depicts its instrumental role.

  11. 11.

    “An economy is an ecology for the generation and distribution of wealth. A cognitive economy is an ecology for the generation and distribution of knowledge” (Woods 2013, p. 85).

  12. 12.

    I need to specify here that the idea of dark knowledge (Woods 2013) or knowledge in the cognitive down-below has nothing to do with frequency of occurrence. Dark knowledge events aren’t dark events in the Maeno and Ohsawa sense.

  13. 13.

    The connection between abduction and affordances in chance discovery based curation has been significantly developed by Abe et al. (2006).

  14. 14.

    “A mass of facts is before us. We go through them. We examine them. We find them a confused snarl, an impenetrable jungle. We are unable to hold them in our minds. [...] But suddenly, while we are poring over our digest of the facts and are endeavoring to set them into order, it occurs to us that if we were to assume something to be true that we do not know to be true, these facts would arrange themselves luminously. That is abduction [...]”. Cf. “Pragmatism as the logic of abduction”, in Peirce (1998, pp. 227–241), the quotation is from footnote 12, pp. 531–532.

  15. 15.

    Cf. the aforementioned brief explanation of the epistemological framework comprehending “theoretical” and “manipulative” abduction.

  16. 16.

    The inferential activity carried out by a detective (who is indeed a chance-discoverer) perfectly embodies the type/token difference, as one might have to individuate the culprit within a set number of suspects, or he might have no suspect at all and thus be forced to assemble a group of suspects. In this case, the abductive reasoning is still selective inasmuch as in the first case the detective must select with a series of tokens, i.e. a number of human beings, while in the second he still has to select his suspect within a type which is still composed of human beings. The detective’s abductions would become creative were he has to postulate a radically different cause for the mishap, shifting the type of culprits for instance from human beings to a sudden chance in atmospheric conditions which led to unusual physical consequences. Indeed, the procedures exemplified by Maeno and Ohsawa (2007) are meant to individuate the dark events within a computationally well-defined tokens belonging to a same type, for instance human beings within a command line or consumable items in a marketing investigation.

  17. 17.

    As contended by Magnani (2013), if we say that truth can be reached through a “simple” abduction (both selective or creative) where simple means that it does not involving an evaluation phase, which coincides with the whole inference to the best explanation, fortified by an empirical evaluation, then it seems we confront a manifest incoherence. In this perspective it is contended that even a simple abduction can provide truth, even if it is epistemically “inert” from the empirical perspective. Why? We can solve the incoherence by observing that we should be compelled to consider abduction as ignorance-preserving only if we consider the empirical test the only way of conferring truth to a hypothetical knowledge content. This clause being accepted, in the framework of the formal model of abduction introduced above the ignorance preservation appears natural and unquestionable. However, if we admit that there are ways to accept a hypothetical knowledge content different from the empirical test, simple abduction is not necessarily constitutively ignorance-preserving: in the end we are dealing with a disagreement about the nature of knowledge, as Woods himself contends. Those who consider abduction as an inference to the best explanation—that is as a truth conferring achievement involving empirical evaluation—obviously cannot consider abductive inference as ignorance-preserving. Those who consider abduction as a mere activity of guessing are more inclined to accept its ignorance-preserving character.

  18. 18.

    This process is very similar to the shift between epistemic bubbles exposed by Woods (2005), but a thorough analysis of this correspondence would transcend the scope of this chapter, and could rather become the object of a future study.

  19. 19.

    This kind of abductive generation of a new chance-system reflects in its gestalt-switch-likeness Peirce’s conception of abduction as akin to truth (Peirce 1931–1958, 7.220), a statement embedded with a nearly mystical value that has to be necessarily balanced with Peirce’s pragmatic (non-metaphysical) conception of truth as “the opinion which is fated to be agreed to by all who investigate.”

  20. 20.

    Even if the issue is clearly related to the topic at stake, I am not especially dealing with the pragmatic relationship between ignorance and courses of action where ignorance can be a synonym of uncertainty, as in the case of economics. A specific investigation about that is due soon, setting off from some reflections introduced in this chapter.

References

  • Abe, A., Ozaku, H.I., Kuwahara, N., Kogure, K.: Cooperation between abductive and inductive nursing risk management. In: Tsumoto, S., Clifton, C.W., Zhong, N., Wu, X., Liu, J., Wah, B.W., Cheung, Y.-M. (eds.) Sixth IEEE International Conference on Data Mining Workshops, Los Alamitos, USA, pp. 705–708. IEEE Computer Society (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  • Aliseda, A.: Seeking Explanations: Abduction in Logic, Philosophy of Science and Artificial Intelligence. Stanford University Press, Stanford (1998)

    Google Scholar 

  • Aliseda, A.: Abductive Reasoning. Logical Investigations into Discovery and Explanation. Synthese Library, vol. 330. Springer, Berlin (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  • Amitani, S., Hori, K.: A method and a system for supporting the process of chance discovery. In: Abe, A., Oehlmann, R. (eds.) The First European Workshop on Chance Discovery, Valencia, pp. 62–71 (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, M.: Why thought experiments are not arguments. Philos. Sci. 66(4), 534–541 (1999)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay, D.M., Woods, J.: The Reach of Abduction: Insight and Trial. A Practical Logic of Cognitive Systems, vol. 2. Elsevier, Amsterdam (2005)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P.: Environmental complexity and the evolution of cognition. In: Sternberg, R., Kaufman, K. (eds.) The Evolution of Intelligence, pp. 233–249. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Mawhah (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendricks, F.V., Faye, J.: Abducting explanation. In: Magnani, L., Nersessian, N.J., Thagard, P. (eds.) Model-Based Reasoning in Scientific Discovery, pp. 271–294. Springer, Boston (1999)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J.: What is abduction? The fundamental problem of contemporary epistemology. Trans. Charles S. Peirce Soc. 34(3), 503–533 (1998)

    Google Scholar 

  • Houston, T.: Google’s project glass augmented reality glasses begin testing. The Verge (2012). http://bit.ly/1mKRzC7

  • Jacob, E.B., Shapira, Y., Tauber, A.I.: Seeking the foundation of cognition in bacteria. From Schrödinger’s negative entropy to latent information. Phys. A Stat. Mech. Appl. 359, 495–524 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kakas, A., Kowalski, R.A., Toni, F.: Abductive logic programming. J. Log. Comput. 2(6), 719–770 (1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kowalski, R.A.: Logic for Problem Solving. Elsevier, New York (1979)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuipers, T.A.F.: Abduction aiming at empirical progress of even truth approximation leading to a challenge for computational modelling. Found. Sci. 4(3), 307–323 (1999)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maeno, Y., Ohsawa, Y.: Human-computer interactive annealing for discovering invisible dark events. IEEE Trans. Ind. Electron. 54(2), 1184–1192 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L.: Abduction, Reason, and Science. Processes of Discovery and Explanation. Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers, New York (2001)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L.: Animal abduction. From mindless organisms to artifactual mediators. In: Magnani, L., Li, P. (eds.) Model-Based Reasoning in Science, Technology and Medicine, pp. 3–37. Springer, Berlin (2007a)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L.: Creating chances through cognitive niche construction. The role of affordances. In: Apolloni, B., Howlett, R.J., Lakhmi, J. (eds.) Knowledge-Based Intelligent Information and Engineering Systems, pp. 917–925. Springer, Berlin (2007b)

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L.: Abductive Cognition. The Epistemological and Eco-Cognitive Dimensions of Hypothetical Reasoning. Springer, Berlin (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L.: Is abduction ignorance-preserving? conventions, models, and fictions in science. Log. J. IGPL 21(6), 882–914 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L., Bardone, E.: Sharing representations and creating chances through cognitive niche construction. The role of affordances and abduction. In: Iwata, S., Oshawa, Y., Tsumoto, S., Zhong, N., Shi, Y., Magnani, L. (eds.) Communications and Discoveries from Multidisciplinary Data. Studies in Computational Intelligence, vol. 123, pp. 3–40. Springer, Berlin (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Meheus, J., Verhoeven, L., Van Dyck, M., Provijn, D.: Ampliative adaptive logics and the foundation of logic-based approaches to abduction. In: Magnani, L., Nersessian, N.J., Pizzi, C. (eds.) Logical and Computational Aspects of Model-Based Reasoning, pp. 39–71. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht (2002)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R.: On reading signs: some differences between us and the others. In: Kimbrough Oller, D., Griebel, U. (eds.) Evolution of Communication Systems: A Comparative Approach, pp. 15–29. The MIT Press, Cambridge (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  • Ohsawa, Y., Fukuda, H.: Chance discovery by stimulated groups of people. J. Cont. Crisis Manag. 10(3), 129–138 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ohsawa, Y., McBurney, P. (eds.): Chance Discovery. Advanced Information Processing. Springer, Berlin (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  • Pasteur, L.: Oeuvres complétes rèunies par M. Pasteur Vallery-Radot, Mèlanges scientifiques et littèraires. Masson et Cie Editeurs, Paris (1854/1937)

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C.S.: Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1931–1958). Vols. 1–6, Hartshorne, C., Weiss, P. (eds.); Vols. 7–8, Burks, A.W. (ed.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C.S.: The Charles S. Peirce Papers: Manuscript Collection in the Houghton Library. The University of Massachusetts Press, Worcester (1966). Annotated Catalogue of the Papers of Charles S. Peirce. Numbered according to Richard S. Robin. Available in the Peirce Microfilm edition. Pagination: CSP \(=\) Peirce/ISP \(=\) Institute for Studies in Pragmaticism

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C.S.: The Essential Peirce. Selected Philosophical Writings. Indiana University Press, Bloomington and Indianapolis (1992–1998). Vol. 1, Houser, N., Kloesel, C. (eds.) (1867–1893); Vol. 2, The Peirce Edition Project (ed.) (1893–1913)

    Google Scholar 

  • Shibata, H., Hori, K.: Towards and integrated environment for writing. In: Abe, A., Oehlmann, R. (eds.) The First European Workshop on Chance Discovery, Valencia, pp. 232–241 (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  • Weir, A.A.S., Kacelnik, A.: A new caledonian crow (corvus moneduloides) creatively re-designs tools by bending or unbending aluminium strips. Animal Cogn. 9(4), 317–334 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J.: Epistemic bubbles. In: Artemov, S., Barringer, H., Garcez, A., Lamb, L., Woods, J. (eds.) We Will Show Them: Essay in Honour of Dov Gabbay (Volume II), pp. 731–774. College Pubblications, London (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J.: Ignorance, inference and proof: abductive logic meets the criminal law. In: Tuzet, G., Canale, D. (eds.) The Rules of Inference: Inferentialism in Law and Philosophy, pp. 151–185. Egea Bocconi University (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J.: Errors of Reasoning Naturalizing the Logic of Inference. Studies in Logic and Cognitive Systems, vol. 45. College Publications, London (2013)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Selene Arfini .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Arfini, S. (2019). Abduction: Enhancing Knowledge with an Ignorance-Based Reasoning. In: Ignorant Cognition. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 46. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-14362-6_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics