Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Philosophers in Depth ((PID))

  • 769 Accesses

Abstract

This introductory chapter firstly explains a threefold purpose of this volume: to elucidate Arendt’s flagship idea of political freedom in relation to its closely connected ideas, including liberation and revolution; to consider her theory of freedom and its continuing relevance (or lack thereof) in light of some of the most notable political experiences over the past decade; and to analyze her theory of freedom comparatively by way of examining a variety of relevant writings in political thought, including the mainstream post-Rawlsian branch of political theory. I then give a summary of each of the chapters in the volume, followed by reflections on the intellectual challenges that Arendt scholars should confront today.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Arendt, “Hannah Arendt on Hannah Arendt,” in her Thinking Without a Bannister: Essays in Understanding 19531975, ed. Jerome Kohn (New York: Schocken Books, 2018), 449.

  2. 2.

    UNHCR, The UN Refugee Agency, “Global Trends: Forced Displacement in 2017,” 25 June 2018, http://www.unhcr.org/figures-at-a-glance.html.

  3. 3.

    Olivia Goldhill, “Hannah Arendt Was the Philosopher to Reference in 2017,” Quartzy, 23 December 2017, https://quartzy.qz.com/1162378/hannah-arendt-the-thinker-on-totalitarianism-is-popular-in-the-trump-era/; and Dominic Green, “Meet Michiko Kakutani, the Conservative,” Spectator USA, 16 July 2018, https://spectator-usa.com/2018/07/meet-michiko-kakutani-the-conservative/.

  4. 4.

    For a compelling challenge to this story, see Catherine H. Zuckert, ed., Political Philosophy in the Twentieth Century: Authors and Arguments (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011).

  5. 5.

    See, e.g., the Symposium on the John Rawls papers with contributions by Mark Bevir, David A. Reidy, P. MacKenzie Bok, Daniele Botti, and Andrius Gališanka, in the Journal of the History of Ideas 78, no. 2 (2017): 255–308; as well as Mark Bevir and Andrius Gališanka, “John Rawls in Historical Context,” History of Political Thought 33, no. 4 (2012): 701–25; P. MacKenzie Bok, “To the Mountaintop Again: The Early Rawls and Post-protestant Ethics in Postwar America,” Modern Intellectual History 14, no. 1 (2015): 1–33; and David Reidy, “Rawls’s Religion and Justice as Fairness,” History of Political Thought 31, no. 2 (2010): 309–44.

  6. 6.

    The literature is growing fast. See, e.g., Bernard Williams, In the Beginning Was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument, ed. Geoffrey Hawthorn (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005); Raymond Geuss, Philosophy and Real Politics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008); David Leopold and Marc Stears, eds., Political Theory: Methods and Approaches (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008); Jeremy Waldron, “Political Political Theory: An Inaugural Lecture,” The Journal of Political Philosophy 21, no. 1 (2013): 1–23; Ronald Beiner, Political Philosophy: What It Is and Why It Matters (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014); Enzo Rossi and Matt Sleat, “Realism in Normative Political Theory,” Philosophy Compass 9, no. 10 (2014): 689–701; David Miller, “In What Sense Must Political Philosophy Be Political?” Social Philosophy and Policy 33, no. 1–2 (2016): 155–74; and Jonathan Floyd, Is Political Philosophy Impossible? Thoughts and Behaviour in Normative Political Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2017).

  7. 7.

    It is indicative that a recent 500-page anthology of philosophical writings on freedom, edited by three leading analytic philosophers, fails to include an excerpt from Arendt’s work, while including a number of less significant pieces by their analytic colleagues. See Ian Carter, Matthew H. Kramer, and Hillel Steiner, eds., Freedom: A Philosophical Anthology (Oxford: Blackwell, 2007).

  8. 8.

    Kye Barker, “Book Review: Hannah Arendt and Political Theory: Challenging Tradition by Steve Buckler,” LSE Review of Books, 29 March 2013, http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/52797/1/Book_Review_Hannah_Arendt_and_Political_Theory.pdf.

  9. 9.

    On the latter see, especially, José Luis Martí and Philip Pettit, A Political Philosophy in Public Life: Civic Republicanism in Zapatero’s Spain (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000).

  10. 10.

    It is worth noting here that Canovan’s seminal book, which characterized Arendt’s political thought as a “new republicanism,” appeared in 1992. This book is ignored in Pettit’s Republicanism, published in 1997. See Margaret Canovan, Hannah Arendt: A Reinterpretation of Her Political Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), esp. 201–52; and Philip Pettit, Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997).

  11. 11.

    Hannah Arendt, “Reflections on Little Rock,” Dissent 6, no. 1 (1959): 45–56.

  12. 12.

    Smithand Zhang’s essay may thus be compared to Sabl’s “creative reconstruction” of Rawls’s theory of disobedience in his “Looking Forward to Justice: Rawlsian Civil Disobedience and Its Non-Rawlsian Lessons,” The Journal of Political Philosophy 9, no. 3 (2001): 307–30.

  13. 13.

    Hannah Arendt, “On Violence,” in her Crises of the Republic (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1972), 177.

  14. 14.

    Samantha Balaton-Chrimes, “The Might of Power Facing up to the Violence of Strength: An Arendtian View of Politics and Revolution,” Open Democracy, 2 February 2011, https://www.opendemocracy.net/samantha-balaton-chrimes/might-of-power-facing-up-to-violence-of-strength-arendtian-view-of-politics.

  15. 15.

    Hannah Arendt and Hans Jürgen Benedict, “Revolution, Violence, and Power: A Correspondence,” Constellations 16, no. 2 (2009): 305.

  16. 16.

    Arendt, “Thoughts on Politics and Revolution,” in her Crises of the Republic, 230.

  17. 17.

    Jeremy Waldron, “Arendt’s Constitutional Politics,” in The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt, ed. Dana Villa (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 203.

  18. 18.

    This is the phrase Seyla Benhabib used to characterize her interpretive strategy in her “Feminist Theory and Hannah Arendt’s Concept of Public Space,” History of the Human Sciences 6, no. 2 (1993): 100. She uses the same approach in Seyla Benhabib, The Reluctant Modernism of Hannah Arendt (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2003).

  19. 19.

    Larry May, “Hannah Arendt: A Remembrance,” Arendt Studies 1 (2017): 22.

Bibliography

  • Arendt, Hannah. “Reflections on Little Rock.” Dissent 6, no. 1 (1959): 45–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. Crises of the Republic. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. Thinking Without a Bannister: Essays in Understanding 1953–1975. Edited by Jerome Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 2018.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah, and Hans Jürgen Benedict. “Revolution, Violence, and Power: A Correspondence.” Constellations 16, no. 2 (2009): 302–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balaton-Chrimes, Samantha. “The Might of Power Facing up to the Violence of Strength: An Arendtian View of Politics and Revolution.” Open Democracy, 2 February 2011. https://www.opendemocracy.net/samantha-balaton-chrimes/might-of-power-facing-up-to-violence-of-strength-arendtian-view-of-politics.

  • Barker, Kye. “Book Review: Hannah Arendt and Political Theory: Challenging Tradition by Steve Buckler.” LSE Review of Books, 29 March 2013. http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/52797/1/Book_Review_Hannah_Arendt_and_Political_Theory.pdf.

  • Beiner, Ronald. Political Philosophy: What It Is and Why It Matters. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, Seyla. “Feminist Theory and Hannah Arendt’s Concept of Public Space.” History of the Human Sciences 6, no. 2 (1993): 97–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. The Reluctant Modernism of Hannah Arendt. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2003.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bevir, Mark. “John Rawls in Light of the Archive: Introduction to the Symposium on the Rawls Papers.” Journal of the History of Ideas 78, no. 2 (2017): 255–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bevir, Mark, and Andrius Gališanka. “John Rawls in Historical Context.” History of Political Thought 33, no. 4 (2012): 701–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bok, P. MacKenzie. “To the Mountaintop Again: The Early Rawls and Post-protestant Ethics in Postwar America.” Modern Intellectual History 14, no. 1 (2015): 1–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. “‘The Latest Invasion from Britain’: Young Rawls and His Community of American Ethical Theorists.” Journal of the History of Ideas 78, no. 2 (2017): 275–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Botti, Daniele. “Rawls on Dewey Before the Dewey Lectures.” Journal of the History of Ideas 78, no. 2 (2017): 287–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Canovan, Margaret. Hannah Arendt: A Reinterpretation of Her Political Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, Ian, Matthew H. Kramer, and Hillel Steiner, eds. Freedom: A Philosophical Anthology. Oxford: Blackwell, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Floyd, Jonathan. Is Political Philosophy Impossible? Thoughts and Behaviour in Normative Political Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2017.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gališanka, Andrius. “Just Society as a Fair Game: John Rawls and Game Theory in the 1950s.” Journal of the History of Ideas 78, no. 2 (2017): 299–308.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geuss, Raymond. Philosophy and Real Politics. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldhill, Olivia. “Hannah Arendt Was the Philosopher to Reference in 2017.” Quartzy, 23 December 2017. https://quartzy.qz.com/1162378/hannah-arendt-the-thinker-on-totalitarianism-is-popular-in-the-trump-era/.

  • Green, Dominic. “Meet Michiko Kakutani, the Conservative.” Spectator USA, 16 July 2018. https://spectator-usa.com/2018/07/meet-michiko-kakutani-the-conservative/.

  • Leopold, David, and Marc Stears, eds. Political Theory: Methods and Approaches. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martí, José Luis, and Philip Pettit. A Political Philosophy in Public Life: Civic Republicanism in Zapatero’s Spain. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, Larry. “Hannah Arendt: A Remembrance.” Arendt Studies 1 (2017): 13–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, David. “In What Sense Must Political Philosophy Be Political?” Social Philosophy and Policy 33, no. 1–2 (2016): 155–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reidy, David A. “Rawls’s Religion and Justice as Fairness.” History of Political Thought 31, no. 2 (2010): 309–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. “Rawls on Philosophy and Democracy: Lessons from the Archived Papers.” Journal of the History of Ideas 78, no. 2 (2017): 265–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rossi, Enzo, and Matt Sleat. “Realism in Normative Political Theory.” Philosophy Compass 9, no. 10 (2014): 689–701.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sabl, Andrew. “Looking Forward to Justice: Rawlsian Civil Disobedience and Its Non-Rawlsian Lessons.” The Journal of Political Philosophy 9, no. 3 (2001): 307–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • UNHCR, The UN Refugee Agency. “Global Trends: Forced Displacement in 2017.” 25 June 2018. http://www.unhcr.org/figures-at-a-glance.html.

  • Waldron, Jeremy. “Arendt’s Constitutional Politics.” In The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt, edited by Dana Villa, 201–19. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. “Political Political Theory: An Inaugural Lecture.” The Journal of Political Philosophy 21, no. 1 (2013): 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. In the Beginning Was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument. Edited by Geoffrey Hawthorn. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zuckert, Catherine H., ed. Political Philosophy in the Twentieth Century: Authors and Arguments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kei Hiruta .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Hiruta, K. (2019). Introduction. In: Hiruta, K. (eds) Arendt on Freedom, Liberation, and Revolution. Philosophers in Depth. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-11695-8_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics