Skip to main content

Pediatric Neuro-enhancement, Best Interest, and Autonomy: A Case of Normative Reversal

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Advances in Neuroethics ((AIN))

Abstract

The debate on “cognitive enhancement” has moved from discussions about enhancement in adults to enhancement in children and adolescents. Similar to positions expressed in the adult context, some have argued that pediatric cognitive enhancement is acceptable and even laudable. However, the implications differ between the adult and the pediatric contexts. For example, in the debate over cognitive enhancement in adults, i.e., those who have legal majority, respect for autonomy demands that personal preferences not be overridden in absence of strong arguments because competent adults are in the best position to recognize and protect their own interests. However, the concepts of best interest and autonomy provide a different picture in the case of pediatric enhancement. In the context of decision-making involving minors, it is assumed that the parents are in the best position to promote and protect the interests of their children and this is chiefly why they are granted the authority to make decisions on their behalf. However, we argue in favor of guarding the physical integrity of children from intrusive medical interventions without medical need and with clear and detrimental effects (e.g., suppressing growth). We also support leaving open other legitimate life trajectory and career choices, as this is in the best interest of the child, even if they are less in line with the expectations of parents or success in educational settings. In addition, parental decision-making in favor of cognitive enhancement suffers from a lack of information about cognitive enhancers (e.g., safety and efficacy) and potential biases. Thus, bearing in mind these issues and the development of volitional capacities of children, we argue that pediatric enhancement is not a morally acceptable practice and “inevitability” can be curbed with clear and fair rules that establish duties of state representatives, physicians, and public institutions. We conclude by canvassing evidence-based policy options that could protect the open future of minors and define the parameters of parental decision-making analogous to the cases of nicotine and alcohol.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This could be read as a broadly Millian argument for autonomy. An even stronger one could be made with a Kantian notion of autonomy which assumes that considerations of autonomy trump considerations of beneficence because autonomy itself would be considered intrinsically valuable as an end in itself. We believe that our argument holds whichever version of autonomy one prefers, and thank an anonymous reviewer for the constructive comments which prompted us to make this point more explicit.

  2. 2.

    It should be noted here that a similar argument has been made for the use of tDCS on minors by Maslen and colleagues (2014). For this reason, our argument will briefly mention noninvasive brain stimulation techniques and focus mostly on psychopharmacological interventions.

  3. 3.

    Sports doping could also be seen as a sufficiently like case. We thank an anonymous reviewer for this example.

  4. 4.

    Perhaps the best example of such a “pro-enhancement” position is the view of Jessica Fanigan. She argues that “it […] is morally praiseworthy for parents and physicians to choose to make existing children’s lives as good as they can be. This is not to say that parents and pediatricians are morally required to provide neuro-enhancements when they suspect that the drugs would be beneficial, but that it is beneficent to give children greater opportunities and to correct for existing disadvantages. Parents and pediatricians have rights to refuse to act beneficiently just as parents have rights to choose sub-optimal educational plans…” (Flanigan 2013: 333. Emphasis added).

  5. 5.

    The higher the rating the more harmful the substance. Caffeine was not rated nor ranked as a potentially harmful substance at that time.

  6. 6.

    It might be objected here that this argument has implications beyond the issue of enhancement, say in cases of risky contact sports, such as American Football. However, there is a considerable difference in ethical status of direct neurointerventions and enjoying physical activities. Even though, for lack of space, we cannot pursue this further, suffice it to say that children are initiators of physical activities, whereas outside interference is necessary for providing psychoactive substances or brain stimulation.

  7. 7.

    For a longer argument focusing specifically on tDCS in pediatric context, see Maslen et al. (2014).

  8. 8.

    If the the conditions of distribution for cognitive enhancement are developed in such a way that it will benefit the least advantaged, this conclusion might be changed. However, it remains to be seen if any realistic type of policy proposal successfully tackles these and other ethical objections to cognitive enhancement. We thank an anonymous reviewer for suggesting this point.

References

  • Austin MW (2016) Rights and obligations of parents. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ISSN 2161-0002. http://www.iep.utm.edu/parentri. Accessed 26 Aug 2016

  • Banjo OC, Nadler R, Reiner PB (2010) Physician attitudes towards pharmacological cognitive enhancement: safety concerns are paramount. PLoS One 5(12):e14322

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Bell SK, Lucke JC, Hall WD (2012) Lessons for enhancement from the history of cocaine and amphetamine use. AJOB Neurosci 3(2):24–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berman SM, Kuczenski R, McCracken JT, London ED (2009) Potential adverse effects of amphetamine treatment on brain and behavior: a review. Mol Psychiatry 14(2):123–142

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow BC (2006) UXL encyclopedia of drugs and addictive substances. UXL/Thompson Gale, Detroit

    Google Scholar 

  • Bikson M, Bestman S, Edwards S (2013) Neuroscience: transcranial devices are not playthings. Nature 501:167

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Bostrom N, Ord T (2006) The reversal test: eliminating status quo bias in applied ethics. Ethics 116(4):656–679

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Buchannan A (2011) Cognitive enhancement and education. Theory Res Educ 9(2):145–162

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad P, Bergey MR (2014) The impending globalization of ADHD: notes on the expansion and growth of a medicalised disorder. Soc Sci Med 122:31–43

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Deaton A, Arora R (2009) Life at the top: the benefits of height. Econ Hum Biol 7(2):133–136

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Dressler M, Repantis D (2015) Cognitive enhancement in humans. In: Knafo S, Venero C (eds) Cognitive enhancement. Elsevier, Academic, Amsterdam, pp 273–306

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dubljević V (2012a) Principles of justice as the basis for public policy on pycho-pharmacological cognitive enhancement. Law Innov Technol 4(1):67–83

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubljević V (2012b) Toward a legitimate public policy on cognition-enhancement drugs. AJOB Neurosci 3(3):29–33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubljević V (2013a) Cognitive enhancement, rational choice and justification. Neuroethics 6(1):179–187

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubljević V (2013b) Prohibition or coffee-shops: regulation of amphetamine and methylphenidate for enhancement use by healthy adults. Am J Bioeth 13(7):23–33

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Dubljević V (2013c) Autonomy in neuroethics: political and not metaphysical. AJOB Neurosci 4(4):44–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubljević V (2015) Neurostimulation devices for cognitive enhancement: toward a comprehensive regulatory framework. Neuroethics 8(2):115–126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubljević V, Saigle V, Racine E (2014) The rising tide of tDCS in the media and academic literature. Neuron 82(4):731–736

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Durrant JE (1996) The Swedish ban on corporal punishment: its history and effects. Family violence against children: a challenge for society. Prevention and intervention in childhood and adolescence. Walter De Gruyter, Berlin, New York, pp 19–25

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitz NS, Reiner PB (2013) The challenge of crafting policy for do-it-yourself brain stimulation. J Med Ethics. Epub ahead of print June 3, 2013. https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2013-101458

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Flanigan J (2013) Adderall for all: a defense of pediatric neuroenhancement. HEC Forum 25:325–344

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaucher N, Payot A, Racine E (2013) Cognitive enhancement in children and adolescents: is it in their best interests? Acta Paediatr 102:1118–1124

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Graf WD, Nagel SK, Epstein LG, Miller G, Nass R, Larriviere D (2013) Pediatric neuroenhancement: ethical, legal, social, and neurodevelopmental implications. Neurology 80(13):1251–1260

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas J (2001) Die Zukunft der menschlichen Natur [Future of Human Nature]. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main

    Google Scholar 

  • Iuculcano T, Cohen Kadosh R (2013) The mental cost of cognitive enhancement. J Neurosci 33(10):4482–4486

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krutzinna J (2016) Can a welfarist approach be used to justify a moral duty to cognitively enhance children? Bioethics 30(7):528–535

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie K (2008) Alcohol and drug use among teenagers. Can Med Assoc J 178(2):149

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lieb K (2010) Hirndoping: Warum wir nicht alles schlucken sollten. Artemis & Winkler, Mannheim

    Google Scholar 

  • Maslen H, Earp BD, Cohen Kadosh R, Savulescu J (2014) Brain stimulation for treatment and enhancement in children: an ethical analysis. Front Hum Neurosci 8:953. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00953

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Morin K, Rakatansky H, Riddick FA, Morse LJ, O’Bannon JM, Goldrich MS et al (2002) Managing conflicts of interest in the conduct of clinical trials. J Am Med Assoc 287(1):78–84

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nutt D, King L, Saulsbury AW, Blakemore C (2007) Development of a rational scale to assess the harm of drugs of potential misuse. Lancet 369(9566):1047–1053

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Peck P (2004) Cosmetic surgery in adolescents a booming, yet controversial medical niche. Medscape Medical News, Oct 13, 2004. http://www.medscape.com/viewarticle/491266

  • Racine E (2010) Pragmatic neuroethics: improving treatment and understanding of the mind-brain. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ruxton CHS (2014) The suitability of caffeinated drinks for children: a systematic review of randomised controlled trials, observational studies and expert panel guidelines. J Hum Nutr Diet 27:342–357

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sahakian B, Morein-Zamir S (2007) Professor’s little helper. Nature 450:1157–1159

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sandel MJ (2007) The case against perfection: ethics in the age of genetic engineering. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu J (2006) Justice, fairness and enhancement. Ann N Y Acad Sci 1093:321–338

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu J, Foddy B, Clayton M (2004) Why we should allow performance enhancing drugs in sport. Br J Sports Med 38(6):666–670

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Singh I, Kelleher KJ (2010) Neuroenhancement in young people: proposal for research, policy, and clinical management. AJOB Neurosci 1(1):3–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steenbergen L, Sellaro R, Hommel B, Lindenberger U, Khun S, Colzato LS (2016) Unfocus on foc.us: commercial tDCS headset impairs working memory. Exp Brain Res 234:637–643

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Support for this work comes from the Banting Postdoctoral Fellowships Programme (Dubljević) and the Fonds de recherche du Québec—Santé for career awards (Racine). We extend our thanks to members of the Neuroethics Research Unit for feedback on previous versions of this manuscript. Special thanks to Matthew Sample for detailed constructive feedback on a previous version of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Veljko Dubljević .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Dubljević, V., Racine, E. (2019). Pediatric Neuro-enhancement, Best Interest, and Autonomy: A Case of Normative Reversal. In: Nagel, S. (eds) Shaping Children. Advances in Neuroethics. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-10677-5_13

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-10677-5_13

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-10676-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-10677-5

  • eBook Packages: MedicineMedicine (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics