Skip to main content

Constitutional Design and Politics-as-Exchange: The Optimism of Public Choice

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
James M. Buchanan

Part of the book series: Remaking Economics: Eminent Post-War Economists ((EPWE))

Abstract

Public choice theory, built on the homo economicus model, is regularly attacked as an empirically inadequate and potentially harmful example of economic imperialism. I offer a methodological defense of the homo economicus assumption and argue that public choice theory provides not merely a negative theory of “government failure.” Instead, public choice can be understood as a positive, optimistic enterprise that points to the potential for institutional reforms that are in the common interests of citizens.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 279.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Contrary to common misconceptions, this does not imply a view of “atomistic” individuals, or that “groups” can play no role in social processes. It merely implies that groups must ultimately be reducible to their individual members, and “group action” must be explained in terms of the behavior of individual group members. This was, of course, the fundamental insight of Olson’s critique of interest group pluralism offered in The Logic of Collective Action (1965).

  2. 2.

    One important consequence of this position—and a key contribution of public choice —is that it implies that is inappropriate to impose on the political process a unitary actor assumption that policy is chosen by a “benevolent dictator” who maximizes social welfare. Instead, political decisions must be explained as “the results of individual decisions when the latter are combined through a specific rule for decision-making” (Buchanan and Tullock 1962, p. 35), which may place significant limitations on what is feasible in the political process. See Vanberg and Vanberg (2012, pp. 247–248) for an elaboration.

  3. 3.

    It is worth noting in this context that there are some disagreements even within the public choice tradition on the importance of material self-interest as a motivation for voters. Most prominently, the theory of “expressive voting” argues that voting behavior is not primarily driven by material self-interest (precisely because voters recognize that they are highly unlikely to be pivotal), but instead motivated by desires to express support for particular values (see Brennan and Lomasky 1993).

  4. 4.

    As Brennan and Buchanan (1988, p. 184) note explicitly, “…there is no invisible hand operative in majoritarian political institutions analogous to that operative in the market setting…” In a bizarre twist, Pettit (2008, pp. 50–51) proceeds to criticize what he has described as the “market model” on the basis of arguments that identify precisely the kinds of issues raised by public choice analysis of majoritarian politics, including the fact that voters are rarely pivotal and must confront bundles of choices, and cannot choose “at the margin.”

  5. 5.

    Note that in the idealized market setting, this conclusion can be reached on purely procedural grounds, without any detailed information about the parties’ preferences, etc. Of course, there are potential complications here, e.g., the question of what makes exchange voluntary (see Munger 2011).

  6. 6.

    As Buchanan puts it (1999 [1990], p. 386): “As it operates and as we observe it to operate, ordinary politics may remain conflictual…while participation in the inclusive political game that defines the rules for ordinary politics may embody positively valued prospects for all members of the polity.”

  7. 7.

    One of the key analytic points made by Buchanan and Tullock is that this “calculus of consent” regarding the constitutional rules that an individual would want to consent to will typically imply that individuals prefer constitutional rules that do not require unanimous consent for day-to-day decisions. See Vanberg (2018) for a detailed discussion.

  8. 8.

    Critically, for Buchanan , this is a humble role. Expert judgments cannot be substituted for the judgements of citizens as sovereigns as expressed in their decisions to consent to a particular institutional arrangement. Expert judgments can only be offered as advice. See Buchanan (1999 [1991], p. 288): “If individuals are considered the ultimate sovereigns, it follows directly that they are the addresses of all proposals and arguments concerning constitutional-institutional issues. Arguments that involve reliance on experts in certain areas of choice must be addressed to individuals, as sovereigns, and it is individuals’ choice in deferring to expert-agents that legitimizes the potential role of the latter, not some external assessment of epistemic competence as such.”

  9. 9.

    Brennan and Buchanan (1981, p. 159): “…whatever model of man is to be used in evaluating alternative social orders – alternative rules of the economic/political/social game – it must be applied uniformly over all the possibilities to be compared…If we are to employ one set of behavioral postulates for one institution, and another set for another institution, no legitimate comparison of the two institutions can be made.”

  10. 10.

    As Brennan and Buchanan put the point, the “claim is that homo economicus rightly belongs in the analytical derivation of normative propositions about appropriate institutional design” (1981, p. 159).

  11. 11.

    This is, of course, exactly the kind of “calculus of consent” that the representative individual conducts when considering the trade-off between “external costs” (the costs imposed by collective decision the individual opposes) and “decision-making costs” (the costs of reaching a decision in light of divergent preferences, as well as the costs of decisions the individual favors that are blocked by others) in the model presented by Buchanan and Tullock in Chapter 6 of The Calculus of Consent.

  12. 12.

    Brennan and Buchanan (1981, p. 160): “The question we are interested in posing about any particular social order is whether the rules by which individual actions are coordinated are such as to transform actions undertaken by participants in their own private interests into outcomes that are in the interests of others. We know that this curious alchemy is in fact worked by the market – that the invisible hand operates, under certain more or less well-defined conditions, to convert private interest into public interest. The prime task of comparative institutional analysis is to enquire whether other institutions do the same…”

  13. 13.

    See also John Stuart Mill in his Considerations on Representative Government (1991, p. 374): “…since the very principle of constitutional government requires it to be assumed, that political power will be abused to promote the particular purposes of the holder; not because it always is so, but because such is the natural tendency of things, to guard against which is the especial use of free institutions.”

  14. 14.

    Note the close affinity between this methodological point, and Karl Popper’s defense of the “rationality principle” as part of what he calls “situational logic.” For Popper, the rationality principle serves as the animating force for models in the social sciences by ensuring that we assume that individuals act “appropriately” within the context of a model. As he put it (1985 [1967], p. 359): “If you look upon the rationality principle from the point of view which I have here adopted, then you will find that it has little or nothing to do with the empirical or psychological assertion that man always, or in the main, or in most cases, acts rationally. Rather, it turns out to be an aspect of, or a consequence of, the methodological postulate that we should pack or cram our whole theoretical effort, our whole explanatory theory, into an analysis of the situation: into the model.”

References

  • Brennan, G., & Buchanan, J. M. (1981). The Normative Purpose of Economic ‘Science:’ Rediscovery of an Eighteenth Century Method. International Review of Law and Economics, 1, 155–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Buchanan, J. M. (1988). Is Public Choice Immoral? The Case for the ‘Nobel’ Lie. Virginia Law Review, 74, 179–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Lomasky, L. (1993). Democracy and Decision: The Pure Theory of Electoral Preference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1999 [1979]). Politics Without Romance: A Sketch of Positive Public Choice Theory and Its Normative Implications. In The Logical Foundations of Constitutional Liberty. The Collected Works of James Buchanan (Vol. 1, pp. 45–59). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1999 [1986]). The Constitution of Economic Policy. In The Logical Foundations of Constitutional Liberty. The Collected Works of James Buchanan (Vol. 1, pp. 455–470). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1999 [1990]). The Domain of Constitutional Economics. In The Logical Foundations of Constitutional Liberty. The Collected Works of James Buchanan (Vol. 1, pp. 377–395). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1999 [1991]). The Foundations of Normative Individualism. In The Logical Foundations of Constitutional Liberty. The Collected Works of James Buchanan (Vol. 1, pp. 281–291). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (2001 [1988]). Economists and Gains from Trade. In Ideas, Persons, and Events. The Collected Works of James Buchanan (Vol. 19, pp. 135–152). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (2003). Public Choice: The Origins and Development of a Research Program. Typescript. Fairfax: Center for Public Choice, George Mason University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Congleton, R. (1998). Politics by Principle, Not Interest: Towards Nondiscriminatory Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (1962). The Calculus of Consent. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cox, G. (1999). The Empirical Content of Rational Choice Theory: A Reply to Green and Shapiro. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 11, 147–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feld, L., & Burret, H. (2018). (Un)intended Effects of Fiscal Rules. European Journal of Political Economy, 52, 166–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fiorina, M. (1995). Empirical Contributions of Rational Choice. Critical Review, 9, 85–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R., Gilovich, T., & Regan, D. (1993). Does Studying Economics Inhibit Cooperation? Journal of Economic Perspectives, 7, 159–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, D., & Shapiro, I. (1994). Pathologies of Rational Choice. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1985). Of the Independency of Parliament. In D. Hume (Ed.), Essays Moral, Political, and Literary. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelman, S. (1987). ‘Public Choice’ and Public Spirit. Public Interest, 87, 80–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levmore, S. (2002). From Cynicism to Positive Theory in Public Choice. Cornell Law Review, 87, 375–383.

    Google Scholar 

  • Madison, J. (1961 [1787]). Federalist 51. In C. Rossiter (Ed.), The Federalist Papers (pp. 320–325). New York: Mentor.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, L., & Vanberg, G. (2013). Multiparty Government, Fiscal Institutions, and Public Spending. Journal of Politics, 75, 953–967.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1991). Considerations on Representative Government. In J. S. Mill (Ed.), On Liberty and Other Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munger, M. (2011). Euvoluntary or Not, Exchange Is Just. Social Philosophy and Policy, 28, 192–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, M. (1965). The Logic of Collective Action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (2008). Three Conceptions of Democratic Control. Constellations, 15, 46–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1985 [1967]). The Rationality Principle. In D. Miller (Ed.), Popper Selections. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, J. (1987). Egoistic Rationality and Public Choice: A Critical Review of Theory and Evidence. Economic Record, 63, 10–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scaff, I., & Ingram, H. (1987). Politics, Policy, and Public Choice: A Critique and a Proposal. Polity, 19, 613–636.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullock. G. (2005 [1967]). Political Ignorance. In The Economics of Politics. Vol. 4 of The Selected Works of Gordon Tullock (pp. 225–240). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. (2005 [1970]). A Simple Algebraic Log-Rolling Model. In The Economics of Politics. Vol. 4 of The Selected Works of Gordon Tullock (pp. 319–330). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. (2005 [1994]). Democracy as It Really Is. In The Economics of Politics. Vol. 4 of The Selected Works of Gordon Tullock (pp. 395–400). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, G. (2018). Constitutional Political Economy, Democratic Theory, and Institutional Design. Public Choice, 177(3–4), 199–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V., & Kerber, W. (1994). Institutional Competition Among Jurisdictions: An Evolutionary Approach. Constitutional Political Economy, 5, 193–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, G., & Vanberg, V. (2012). Towards a (Re-)integration of the Social Sciences: The Calculus of Consent at 50. Public Choice, 152, 245–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, G., & Vanberg, V. (2017). Contractarian Perspectives in Law and Economics. In F. Parisi (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Law and Economics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Georg Vanberg .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Vanberg, G. (2018). Constitutional Design and Politics-as-Exchange: The Optimism of Public Choice. In: Wagner, R. (eds) James M. Buchanan. Remaking Economics: Eminent Post-War Economists. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-03080-3_28

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-03080-3_28

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-03079-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-03080-3

  • eBook Packages: Economics and FinanceEconomics and Finance (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics