Skip to main content

Sentences as Systems: The Principle of Compositionality and Its Limits

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Systemic Turn in Human and Natural Sciences

Part of the book series: Contemporary Systems Thinking ((CST))

Abstract

In this chapter, it is argued on two different grounds that sentences in natural languages can be seen as systems. First, beyond their linear order, sentences exhibit a syntactic hierarchical structure. Therefore, they are structured entities. Although this structure is usually interpreted as independent of meaning, many semanticists believe that syntactic structure indicates the order in which the meanings of the parts are combined. Second, although the principle of compositionality—which states that the meaning of a sentence is a function of the meanings of the parts of that sentence—is valid in general for natural languages, this principle has been shown to have many exceptions, where interpretation does not proceed bottom-up but top-down, from the meaning of the whole to the meaning of the parts. For this reason, a radical version of the principle of compositionality is untenable; if the whole depends on its parts and the parts on the whole, then the sentence is a system that cannot be dissected into separate parts without losing something essential.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For written texts, “follow” is intended in a spatial sense; for oral texts, it is intended in a temporal sense.

  2. 2.

    This statement simplifies a more complex definition. A regular grammar is a quadruple G = <T, N, E, R>, where T is a set of terminal symbols, N is a set of non-terminal symbols, E is the start symbol, and R is a set of transforming rules A → β, where A is a non-terminal symbol and β is either a terminal symbol or a symbol formed by a terminal symbol and a non-terminal symbol. Given the start symbol, the grammar can generate all the strings of symbols allowed by the rules. Transformation rules can be applied only if the string contains a non-terminal symbol; otherwise, the string is terminal. In natural languages, the start symbol is S (sentence); the non-terminal symbols are constituents larger than words, and the terminal symbols are words. We have already seen an example of a transformation rule (S → NP + VP).

  3. 3.

    More precisely, a context-sensitive grammar is a quadruple G = <T, N, E, R>, where T is a set of terminal symbols, N is a set of non-terminal symbols, E is the start symbol, and R is a set of transforming rules αAβ → αγβ, where A is a non-terminal symbol, and α, β, and γ are either terminal symbols or strings of terminal and non-terminal symbols. α and β may be empty; these provide the “context” for A.

  4. 4.

    This is not the usual interpretation of these sentences, which usually is related to the different logical forms underlying the sentence rather than to semantic indeterminacy. In Frigerio (2010), I demonstrated that this solution has many drawbacks and that an interpretation in terms of semantic indeterminacy is preferable.

  5. 5.

    Grice (1989) emphasizes that participants presuppose that their interlocutors say true and pertinent things.

References

  • Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic structures. The Hague-Paris: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigerio, A. (2010). L’unità dell’enunciato. Indeterminatezza semantica e determinazioni pragmatiche. Milano: Mimesis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. (1989). Studies in the ways of words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B., ter Meulen, A., & Wall, R. (1990). Mathematical methods in linguistics. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Predelli, S. (2005). Painted leaves, context, and semantic analysis. Linguistics and Philosophy, 28, 351–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2004). Literal meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1980). The background of meaning. In J. Searle, F. Kiefer, & M. Bierwisch (Eds.), Speech acts theory and pragmatics (pp. 221–232). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Aldo Frigerio .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Frigerio, A. (2019). Sentences as Systems: The Principle of Compositionality and Its Limits. In: Urbani Ulivi, L. (eds) The Systemic Turn in Human and Natural Sciences. Contemporary Systems Thinking. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00725-6_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics