Skip to main content

The Living Body as a Model of Systemic Organization in Ancient Thinking

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Systemic Turn in Human and Natural Sciences

Part of the book series: Contemporary Systems Thinking ((CST))

  • 434 Accesses

Abstract

Analyzing Homer and Aristotle, the Author faces the ancient Greek origin of the organicist model (introduced since 1920 in system theory) presenting its features. In Homer there is still no term to indicate the living body as a whole, but is present the idea of a principle capable of giving “shape” (eidos) to body elements and to counteract the natural tendency to disintegration: the soul (psyché). Only with Aristotle the living body begins to be understood as “organism,” thanks to a hylomorphic and non-dualistic vision of the relationship of the soul with matter, which explains the living organism. The soul itself, in Aristotle, has the characteristics of a system. From this analysis, the organicist model seems to be enriched by the indispensable notion of “form” which, in turn, calls for the need for an efficient cause outside the system.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Bertalanffy (1969: 208).

  2. 2.

    Morgan (1986): on organizations as “machines” [19–38]; on organizations as organisms [39–76]; on organizations on the model of cerebral functioning [77–109]; the potentialities and limits of mechanistic, organicist, and cerebral models are considered at pp. 33–38, 71–76, and 105–109, respectively. With a historical-descriptive approach, Scott (1992) studies and contrasts the organization of a system according to the “rational” model [29–50] with that of one according to the “natural” model, proper to “dynamic” systems [51–75]. Both of these systems can be “open” or “closed” [76–94] and can combine with each other [95–124]. The interesting conclusion of this study is that it is not possible to define a priori the most effective type of organization [342–362]. The complexity of the various components of an organizational system, along with the variability and the indeterminacy of situations, even when provided with highly detailed information, demonstrates our inability to control the absolute effectiveness of the functioning of individual systems given that, in contingent situations, some degree of unpredictability always remains. Even in the best of cases, therefore, something always seems to escape our rational domain. For these reasons, systems always have histories that are more or less limited in time, or they are subject to transformations that change their identity.

  3. 3.

    Del Giudice (2010: 47–70), Villani (2010: 71–89), Bertolaso (2013, 143–169).

  4. 4.

    I would like to point out some of the studies that have set out such issues, first of all, the body–soul relationship, Rohde (1921); Hirzel (1914); Böhme (1929), Snell (1955: 15–37); Meyer (2008); Jaeger (1953: 88–106 and notes at p. 261–264); Onians (1998); Jahn (1987); Schmitt (1990); Zavalloni (1990).

  5. 5.

    For just a few bibliographical references: Adinolfi (1963: 333–342); Bartolomei (1984); Bellia and Garribba (2011), especially Bellia (2011), Jossa (2011), and Pitta (2011: 75–77).

  6. 6.

    Cf. the contributions of Schütz and Wibbing (2010: 1279–1280) and Wibbing (2010: 1281–1285); Freedman (1992: 767–772: 768); Pitta (2011: 76–77); Schweizer (1981, cols. 609–790), Viagulamuthu (2002), Sichkaryk (2011).

  7. 7.

    For The Iliad and The Odyssey, unless otherwise indicated, my translation is literal, rather than literary.

  8. 8.

    Lehrs (1964: 86–87 and 160) contains the observations by the grammarian Aristarchus on the notion of sôma in the Homeric poems, according to whom “sôma apud Homerum dicitur tantum de cadavere.” Cf. Snell (1955: 19–22), Jaeger (1953: 89).

  9. 9.

    The interpretation of Il. 3.23 can only be dubious.

  10. 10.

    In these verses: Il. 3.23, 7.79, 18.161, 22.342, 23.169; Od. 11.53, 12.67, 24.187. The lexicon of corporeality is studied specifically by Vivante (1955: 43–44).

  11. 11.

    Urso (1997).

  12. 12.

    Il. 4. 460–461. Cf. Urso’s observations (1997: 26), which acknowledge the reference to the frontal bone, but also that “it is not possible from the text to infer whether or not it was known that the cranium is made up of various articulated bones rather than being one single bone.”

  13. 13.

    Observe Urso (1997: 26): “The term glênê (= pupil) will be used posteriorly with the meaning of bone hollow, distinct from kotylê, which indicates a deeper bone cavity. This suggests perhaps that in the Homeric age it was known that the pupil was a cavity (or hole) of the eye, but it certainly indicates that the term is used precisely to indicate that structure and not applied generically.”

  14. 14.

    Il. 14.493–499.

  15. 15.

    Il. 16.345–350.

  16. 16.

    Il. 5.72–75.

  17. 17.

    Urso (1997: 27) notes that the blows delivered to the laterocervical region, in severing the external carotid artery, were nearly always fatal for heroes of The Iliad.

  18. 18.

    Il. 5. 290–293.

  19. 19.

    Il. 17. 617–618, cf. 13.671–672 and 16.606–607.

  20. 20.

    Il. 20.481–483.

  21. 21.

    Il. 20.469–471.

  22. 22.

    Il. 16.203.

  23. 23.

    Il. 20.478–480.

  24. 24.

    Il. 4. 501–502.

  25. 25.

    Il. 20.397–400.

  26. 26.

    Il. 8.518, 13.188 and 805, 15.609 and 648, 16.104, 18.611; Od. 11.319, 18.378, 22.102.

  27. 27.

    Il. 5.146–147.

  28. 28.

    Il. 5.65–67.

  29. 29.

    Il. 5.305–308.

  30. 30.

    Il. 13.442.

  31. 31.

    Il. 1.188–189 and 3.31.

  32. 32.

    Il. 4.531, 5.539, 5.616, 13.372, 13.398 and 506, 16.163 and 465, 17.313 and 519, 21.180.

  33. 33.

    Il. 13.290.

  34. 34.

    Il. 4.526, 21.181.

  35. 35.

    Il. 13.507, 14.517, 17.314–15, 20. 418 and 420.

  36. 36.

    Il. 4.525, 13.568, 20.416, 21.180.

  37. 37.

    Il. 13.568.

  38. 38.

    The sternum: Il. 4.528 and 530, 13.290, 15.542, 16.312 and 400. The chest: Il. 4.108 and 480, 5.19, 41, 57, 317 and 346, 8.121, 303, 313 and 326, 11.108 and 144, 13.186 and 586, 15.420, 523, 577 and 650, 16.597, 17.606. Cf. Od. 9.301, 22.82.

  39. 39.

    Il. 14.466. Cf. Od. 10.560 and 11.65.

  40. 40.

    Il. 13.546.

  41. 41.

    Il. 22.327–329 (this is the episode in which Achilles strikes a deadly blow to Hector, but never pierces the trachea, so that the Trojan hero is able to utter some final words). Urso (1997: 28) observes that “the clarification in the text that Hector could still articulate words after having been struck raises the question of whether the term employed, aspharagos (= trachea), refers to the larynx or to the trachea-larynx complex. The fact that the term larynx (= larynx) is never used in Homer would support this hypothesis.”

  42. 42.

    Il. 4.528.

  43. 43.

    Il. 11.579, 13.412. 17.349.

  44. 44.

    Il. 16.481, cf. 504.

  45. 45.

    Onians (1998: 44–62); Jahn (1987: 9–27).

  46. 46.

    Onians (1998: 93–122); Jahn (1987: 17–19).

  47. 47.

    Il. 10.10.

  48. 48.

    Il. 16.481.

  49. 49.

    Il. 11.579, 13.412, 17.349; Od. 9.301.

  50. 50.

    Il. 3.442, 14.294.

  51. 51.

    Il. 1.103, 4.661–662.

  52. 52.

    Il. 24.40: “Achilles, who does not have sound reason” and Od. 18.215. In Il. 23.103–104, the formula is in reference to the absence of “mind” in the psychai that are in Hades, as in The Iliad 24.201: “Alas, where did your mind go?” Cf. Od. 10.493, concerning the rational mind, which only the soothsayer Tiresias conserved, by gift of Persephone, even in Hades.

  53. 53.

    Od. 11.367.

  54. 54.

    Il. 24.51.

  55. 55.

    Il. 1.608, 18.380 and 482, 20.12; Od. 7.92.

  56. 56.

    Il. 9.646; Od. 18.348.

  57. 57.

    Od. 5.389: the verb is protiossomai.

  58. 58.

    Il. 13.282–83.

  59. 59.

    Il. 1.188–189: the heart is expressed by to êtor and the verb is mermêrizô.

  60. 60.

    Il. 3.31: the heart is expressed by to êtor and the verb is kataplêssô.

  61. 61.

    Od. 4.427, 10.309: the verb is porphyrô.

  62. 62.

    Od. 4.467.

  63. 63.

    Od. 14.517, 15.339, 16.81, 21.198 e 342: the verb is keleuô. In Il. 10.220 and 319, Od. 18.61 the heart (hê kradiê) is in hendiadys with ire (ho thymos) and the verb is otrynô.

  64. 64.

    Od. 20.22–24: literally “remains in obedience,” as contrasted with physical agitation.

  65. 65.

    Od. 15.395: the verb is anôgô.

  66. 66.

    Od. 20.13 and 16: the verb is hylaktô.

  67. 67.

    Od. 23.103 (kradiê stereôterê lithoio).

  68. 68.

    Od. 4.293 (kradiê sidêreê).

  69. 69.

    Il. 2.490.

  70. 70.

    Od. 20.17–18.

  71. 71.

    Il. 22.452–453.

  72. 72.

    Il. 21.114, 21.425; Od. 4.703, 5.297 and 406, 22.68 and 147, 24.345, 24.345.

  73. 73.

    Od. 18.211 and 24.381.

  74. 74.

    Il. 13.61, 23.772.

  75. 75.

    Il. 3.34, 7.215, 8.452, 10.95 and 390, 14.506, 20.44, 22.448, 24.170; Od. 11.527, 18.88 and 341.

  76. 76.

    Il. 4.230, 5.811, 7.6, 13.85, 19.165 and 169, 23.63, 23.627 (for old age); Od. 1.192, 8.233, 12.279.

  77. 77.

    Il. 4.469, 6.27, 7.12 and 16, 11.240 and 260, 15.435 and 581, 16.312, 341, 400, 465, 805, 17.524, 18.31, 21.406, 23.691; Od. 18.238 and 242.

  78. 78.

    Il. 7.11–12.

  79. 79.

    Il. 7.16.

  80. 80.

    Onians (1998: 174–186).

  81. 81.

    Onians (1998: 98–100).

  82. 82.

    Il. 2.171, 8.147, 10.220, 10.244, 10.319, 15.208, 16.52.

  83. 83.

    Il. 10.93–95. Cf. Schmitt’s status quaestionis (1990: 115–116, 271–272 note 352).

  84. 84.

    For these observations, see Hirzel (1914: 6–7), Snell (1955: 15–37), Schweizer (1981, col. 612 note 3), Freedman (1992: 768).

  85. 85.

    Cf. below, note 104.

  86. 86.

    Animals as well possess thymos and give it off at the moment of death: Il. 16.469 (death of a horse), and 23.880 (death of a dove); Od. 10.163 (death of a deer), 19.454 (death of a wild boar).

  87. 87.

    Vivante (1955: 30 note 1 and 40–42).

  88. 88.

    Il. 7.131, 13.671–72, 16.607, 23.191 (reference to the limbs of Hector’s corpse, protected by Apollo with a cloud, so that the sun’s heat would not desiccate the skin covering them), 23.880 (referring to the body of a slain dove); Od. 11.201, 15.354.

  89. 89.

    Il. 13.671–72, 16.607.

  90. 90.

    Il. 11.669 and Od. 11.394, 13.398, 21.283.

  91. 91.

    Il. 16.110, 23.689 and Od. 11.600.

  92. 92.

    Od. 18.77.

  93. 93.

    Snell (1955: 19–20); Vivante (1955: 42).

  94. 94.

    Again as accusative of relation, Il. 1.115, 5.801, 8.305, 13.45, 17.323 and 555, 21.285, 22. 227, 24.376; Od. 2.268, 2.401, 3.468, 4.796, 5.212–213, 7.210, 8.14, 8.116, 8.194, 10.240, 11.469, 13.222, 13.288, 14.177, 16.157, 16.174, 17.307, 17.313, 18.251, 19.124, 19.381, 20.31, 20.194, 22.206, 23.163, 24.17, 24.503, 24.548. In Il. 11.596 and 13.673, 17.366, 18.1 demas pyros “with an aspect like that of fire (demas pyros)” recurs as an adverbial formula.

  95. 95.

    Il. 1.115, 2.58, 3.208, 22.370; Od. 5.212, 6.16 and 152, 7.210, 8.134 and 168.

  96. 96.

    Again as accusative of relation, cf. Il. 2.58, 2.715, 3.39, 3.45, 3.55, 3.124, 3.224, 5.787, 6.252, 8.228, 10.316, 3.365, 13.378, 13.769, 17.142, 17.279, 21.316, 22.370, 24.376; Od. 4.14, 4.264, 5.213, 5.217, 6.16, 6.152, 7.57, 8.116, 8.169, 8.174 e176, 11.337, 11.469, 11.550, 14.177, 18.4, 18.249, 18.251, 19.124, 20.71, 24.17, 24.253, 24.374.

  97. 97.

    Vivante (1955: 30 note 1 and 44–47).

  98. 98.

    Chantraine (2009: 250–251), s.v. demô; Beekes (2010: 314–315), s.v. demô.

  99. 99.

    The root, i.e., *weid, expresses the idea of “to see” present in the Greek verbs idein (“to see”) and oida (“to know”) and in the Sanskrit vedas “knowledge” (Chantraine (2009: 302), s.v. eidos; Beekes (2010: 379–380), s.v. eidomai).

  100. 100.

    I would point out, indicatively, these synthesis studies, mainly devoted to eidos in the early naturalist philosophers, in Plato and in Aristotle: Motte et al. (2003); Fronterotta and Leszl (2005).

  101. 101.

    The nineteenth-century work of Rohde (1921) was fundamental to this topic, which opened a further complex critical debate, resumed and summarized by Otto (1923: 5–15) and by Jaeger (1953: 89–106); Jahn (1987: 124–151) offers a reasoned status quaestionis of the interpretations of the soul/spirit in the nineteenth- and twentieth-century studies with a bibliography to which the reader is referred. Also Böhme (1929); Snell (1955: 15–37); Onians (1998: 93–122); Schmitt (1990).

  102. 102.

    Il. 5.296 = 8.123 and 315.

  103. 103.

    Il. 16.453.

  104. 104.

    Od. 21.153–154, 21.170–171. Cf. Onians (1998: 94): “The thymos is constantly spoken of as feeling and thinking, as active in the lungs (phrenes) or chest (stêthos) of the living person, and as departing at death, but it is not spoken of in connection with the succeeding state.” On thymos as the constituent matter of consciousness in the phrenes, cf. 23–24, 30–31, 40, as “the seat of emotions,” 44–61.

  105. 105.

    Il. 13.671–672, 16.606–607, 856–857 = 20.362–363; Od. 11. 219–22.

  106. 106.

    On the idea of psychê as substitute in Hades of the living body, cf. Meyer (2008: 12–15).

  107. 107.

    Od. 10. 495, 11.207.

  108. 108.

    Od. 11.207 and 222.

  109. 109.

    Odysseus’s friend Elpenor appears to him as an eidôlon in Od. 11.83.

  110. 110.

    Meyer (2008: 12–13).

  111. 111.

    Od. 11.204–208.

  112. 112.

    The behavior of Anticlea, mother of Odysseus, was exemplary when she addresses her son whom she has just met in Hades, as observed by the Peripatetic philosopher Praxiphanes (cf. comment to fr 25 by Praxiphanes in Matelli (2012b: 296–297)).

  113. 113.

    The thymos is active in the lungs and in the chest, as well as in the blood: see Onians (1998: 23–50, 94).

  114. 114.

    Od. 10.536–537 = 11.49–50 and 11.88–89 (Odysseus does not permit anyone to drink the sacrificial blood before interrogating Tiresias), 11.96–99, 146–149 (in Hades, Tiresias drinks the sacrificial blood in order to proclaim the “truth” to Odysseus; the other shades as well can tell the truth only after drinking this blood), 11.142, 153 (Anticlea drinks “smoking black blood,” before speaking to her son), 11.225–234 (other women in Hades).

  115. 115.

    Od. 11.34–36, cf. Jahn (1987: 36).

  116. 116.

    Onians (1998: 93–94).

  117. 117.

    Jahn (1987: 35–37). By identity, I do not mean consciousness, which underlies a different debate, in relation to which, see note 4 above.

  118. 118.

    Mondin (2001: 25).

  119. 119.

    I refer the reader to Matelli (2004: 318–19 note 55), for the observation that the term psychê is used for the first time to indicate the butterfly in the Peripatetic context in the fourth to third centuries BC by Aristotle and Theophrastus, with explicit reference to the metamorphosing insect.

  120. 120.

    I attribute to the term double a value different from Rohde’s animist value (1921), criticized by Jaeger (1953: 92–106), who, however, maintains this meaning. See note 101 above.

  121. 121.

    Jahn (1987: 35–36).

  122. 122.

    In Calzecchi Onesti’s Italian translation of Od. 10.494–495 “a lui solo concesse Persefone d’aver mente saggia da morto, gli altri come ombre vane svolazzano” (“him alone [i.e., Tiresias] did Persephone permit to have a wise mind in death, the others flutter about as vain shades,”) the adjective vain, absent in the Greek text, is added arbitrarily. The verb aissô contains the idea of momentum, cf. Jahn (1987: 36).

  123. 123.

    The reader is referred to the syntheses of studies cited in note 4 above, to which Sichkaryk (2011: 86–99) can be added.

  124. 124.

    Caserta (2007: 66).

  125. 125.

    Caserta (2007, 2012).

  126. 126.

    Vegetti (1983: 459–469).

  127. 127.

    An. 2.1 412a11–13 (henceforth An.).

  128. 128.

    An. A5, 411b7–8: “it seems, rather, that it is the soul that keeps the body united, since, once the soul leaves, the body suddenly dissolves and putrefies.”

  129. 129.

    Busche (2001: 118–119), Centrone (2005): 103–114), Bodson (2003), Bouquiaux (2003), Évrard (2003), Fiasse (2003), Guldentops (2003), Motte (2003), Opsomer (2003a, b, c, d), Seron (2003), Rutten (2003a, b), Stevens (2003a, b), Vancamp (2003), Fronterotta and Leszl (2005: 180–185).

  130. 130.

    Meixner, Newen (2003: 52–56).

  131. 131.

    An. 3.5 430a10–25.

  132. 132.

    For a synthesis, Grasso & Zanatta (2005: 244–263).

  133. 133.

    “Ossia il principio formale, la prima e fondamentale determinazione del vivente, condizione di tutte le sue funzioni vitali, cognitive e operative,” (“That is, the formal principle, the first and fundamental determination of the living, the condition of all its vital, cognitive, and operative functions,”) Movia (2001: 266 note 12); cf. also Busche (2001: 126–131).

  134. 134.

    An. 2.4 (415a14–416b31).

  135. 135.

    An. 2.5 (416b32–418a25).

  136. 136.

    An. 3.4 (429a10–430a9).

  137. 137.

    An. 2.1 (414a29–31).

  138. 138.

    An. 1.5 (411a5–14).

  139. 139.

    Bastian (2010); Busche (2001: 2 n. 9) intends to overcome the negative judgment of Gigon (1986: 158) according to which the idea of system cannot be attributed to Aristotle’s philosophical corpus.

  140. 140.

    An. 2.7 (418a26–424b18).

  141. 141.

    An. 1.4 (408b19–30), 2.1 (413b24–26), 3.5 (430a10–25), cf. Metaph. 12.3 (1070a24–26).

  142. 142.

    An. 3.5 (430a10–25). In view of the exegetical complexities of this section, I refer the reader to the interpretation of Grasso & Zanatta (2005: 244–263).

  143. 143.

    In his On Nature, 24 DK B4, Alcmaeon speaks of the state of physical health (hygieia), sustaining that it consists in an equilibrium (isonomia) of opposing (as in humid/dry, cold/hot, sweet/bitter, etc.) forces (dynameis), while the state of illness (nosos) comes about through the prevalence of just one of these forces over the others, a situation he refers to using the term monarchy: note the lexicon derived from the political sphere being used to qualify the prosperity or pathology of the physical body. Cf. Caserta (2007: 70).

  144. 144.

    Plat. Tim. 15 42e ss.

  145. 145.

    I am following Rackham’s translation of Aristotle’s Politics.

  146. 146.

    Arist. Poet. 4 (1449a9–15). Cf. Plat. Phaedr. 264c.

  147. 147.

    Poet. 7 1450b32–1451b6. Cf. also the analogy of Poet. 23 1459a17–24. Matelli (2012b: 419–450).

  148. 148.

    Rhet. 1.1 1354a11–16.

  149. 149.

    Rhet. 3.14 1415b6–8, 3.19 1496b19–23. Matelli (2012a: 725–754).

  150. 150.

    Adinolfi (1963: 333–342).

  151. 151.

    Roman Antiquities 6.83.2.

  152. 152.

    History of Rome 2.32.7–12.

  153. 153.

    Laws 686b7.

  154. 154.

    Philebus 17d2.

  155. 155.

    Epinomis 991e2.

  156. 156.

    Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics 1168b.32, On the Generation of Animals 740a.20, 752a.7, 758b.3, On the Heavens 391b.9, Poetics 1456a.12.

  157. 157.

    The reader is referred to the contributions in this volume by Urbani Ulivi and Giuliani.

  158. 158.

    See note 139 above.

  159. 159.

    See Appendix IV on “Ancient Jewish conceptions of the mind or ‘soul’, the ‘spirit’, ‘the holy spirit’, the body and the divinity of Christ” in Onians (1998: 480–505); Grasso & Zanatta (2005: 244–263) and Busche (2001: 100–146).

  160. 160.

    I propose a literal translation of this holy text.

Bibliography

  • Adinolfi, M. (1963). Le metafore greco-romane della testa e del corpo e il corpo mistico di Cristo. In Studiorum Paulinorum Congressus internationalis catholicus 1961, simul Secundus Congressus internationalis catholicus de Re Biblica, completo xix saeculo post S. Pauli in Urbem adventum (Vol. II, pp. 333–342). Roma, Pontificio Istituto Biblico (Analecta Biblica 18).

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristoteles. (1932). Aristotle’s Politics, with an English translation by H. Rackham. Cambridge, London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristoteles. (1961). Aristoteles, De Anima, Edited with Introduction and Commentary by W.D. Ross. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartolomei, M. C. (1984). Ellenizzazione del Cristianesimo: linee di critica filosofica e teologica per una interpretazione del problema storico. L’Aquila-Roma: Japadre.

    Google Scholar 

  • Basore, J. W. (1958). Seneca, On Anger. In Seneca Moral Essays, with an English translation. (Vol. I, pp. 106–355). London: William Heinemann Ltd, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bastian, T. (2010). Die Seele als System. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beekes, R. (2010). Etymological dictionary of Greek (Vol. 1–2). Leiden-Boston: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertalanffy, L. (1969). General system theory: Foundations, development, applications. New York: George Braziller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertolaso, M. (2013). Sull’irriducibilità della prospettiva sistemica in biologia. Un’analisi delle convergenze dei modelli interpretativi del cancro. In L. Urbani Ulivi (Ed.), Strutture di mondo. Il pensiero sistemico come specchio di una realtà complessa (Vol. II, pp. 143–169). Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bodson, L. (2003). § 6. Aristote, Génération des animaux, Histoire des animaux, Marche des Animaux, Mauvement des animaux. In A. Motte, C. Rutten, & P. Somville (Eds.), Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote (pp. 391–433).

    Google Scholar 

  • Böhme, J. (1929). Die Seele und das Ich im homerischen Epos. Leipzig-Berlin: Teubner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bouquiaux, L. (2003). § 1. Aristote, Du ciel. In A. Motte, C. Rutten, & P. Somville (Eds.), Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote (pp. 341–359).

    Google Scholar 

  • Busche, H. (2001). Die Seele als System: Aristoteles’ Wissenschaft von der Psyche. Hamburg: Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bellia, G. (2011). L’ellenizzazione del cristianesimo: un percorso storico-teologico. Introduzione, in Bellia, G. and Garibba, D. (Eds.), L'ellenizzazione del cristianesimo dal I al II secolo. Atti del XIII Convegno di Studi Neotestamentari (pp. 5–13). Bologna: EDB.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bellia, G. and Garibba, D. Eds (2011). L'ellenizzazione del cristianesimo dal I al II secolo. Atti del XIII Convegno di Studi Neotestamentari (Ariccia, 10–12 settembre 2009), Bologna: EDB.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calzecchi Onesti, R. (Ed.). (1950). Omero, Iliade. Torino: Giulio Einaudi Editore.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calzecchi Onesti, R. (Ed.). (1963). Omero, Odissea. Torino: Giulio Einaudi Editore.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caserta, C. (2007). Normale e patologico nel corpo e nella polis: “isonomia” e armonia fra VI e V secolo. In G. Daverio Rocchi (Ed.), Tra concordia e pace: parole e valori della Grecia antica, Giornata di studio, Milano, 21 ottobre 2005 (pp. 65–87). Milano: Cisalpino (Quaderni di Acme 92).

    Google Scholar 

  • Caserta, C. (2012). Πόλεων καὶ ἰδιωτῶν κράτιστοι: “corpo politico” e salvezza della città nell’ideologia democratica. In S. Cataldi, E. Bianco, & G. Cuniberti (Eds.), Salvare le “poleis”, costruire la concordia, progettare la pace (pp. 365–383). Alessandria: Edizioni dell’Orso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Centrone, B. (2005). L’eidos come holon in Platone e i suoi riflessi in Aristotele. In Francesco Fronterotta, Walter Leszl (a cura di), Eidos - Idea. Platone, Aristotele e la tradizione platonica (pp. 103–114). Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag (International Plato Studies).

    Google Scholar 

  • Chantraine, P. (2009). Dictionnaire étymologique de la langue grecque. Histoire des mots, nouvelle edition, Bonchamps-lès-Laval, Klincksieck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cicero. (1971). Marcus Tullius Cicero, De officiis, quartum recognovit C. Atzert, Leipzig, B.G. Teubner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohoon, J. W., Crosby, H. L. (1951). Dio Chrysostom, Discourses (Vol. III, pp. 31–36). Cambridge: Harvard University Press, London: William Heinemann Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Del Giudice, E. (2010). Una via quantistica alla teoria dei sistemi. In L. Urbani Ulivi (Ed.), Strutture di mondo. Il pensiero sistemico come specchio di una realtà complessa (Vol. I, pp. 47–70). Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dio Chrysostom. (1893). In J. de Arnim (Ed.), Dionis Prusaensis quem vocant Chrysostomum quae exstant omnia (Vol. I–II). Berlin: Weidmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epictetus. (1916). In Schenkl (Ed.), Epicteti Dissertationes ab Arriano digestae. Leipzig: B. G. Teubner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Évrard, É. (2003). § 5. Aristote, Génération et Corruption. In A. Motte, C. Rutten, & P. Somville (Eds.), Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote (pp. 383–389).

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiasse, G. (2003). § 12. Aristote, Étiques. In A. Motte, C. Rutten, & P. Somville (Eds.), Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote (pp. 507–537).

    Google Scholar 

  • Freedman, D. N. (Ed.) (1992). The Anchor Bible dictionary (Vol. I, pp. 767–772). New York: Doubleday, s.v. “body”.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fronterotta, F., & Leszl, W. G. (Eds.). (2005). Eidos - Idea: Platone, Aristotele e la tradizione platonica. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag (International Plato Studies 21).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigon, O. (1986). Physik und Metaphysik in Aristoteles’ PERI PSYCHES. In Energeia. Études aristotéliciennes offertes a Mgr. Antonio Iannone. Paris: J. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grasso, R., & Zanatta, M. (2005). La forma del corpo vivente. Studio sul De Anima di Aristotele. Milano: Edizioni Unicopli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guldentops, L. (2003). § 11. Aristote, Politiques. In A. Motte, C. Rutten, & P. Somville (Eds.), Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote (pp. 497–505).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirzel, R. (1914). Die Person. Begriff und Name derselben im Altertum (p. 10). Sitzungen der Königlich Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften.

    Google Scholar 

  • Homer. (19172–19192). Homeri Opera, recognoverunt brevique adnotatione critica instruxit Th.W. Allen, III–IV (Odyssea), Oxonii, e Typographeo Clarendoniano.

    Google Scholar 

  • Homer. (19203). Homeri Opera, recognoverunt brevique adnotatione critica instruxerunt D.B. Monro et Th.W. Allen, I–II (Iliades), Oxonii, e Typographeo Clarendoniano.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaeger, W. (1953). Die Theologie der frühen griechischen Denker. Stuttgart: W. Kohlhammer (Ital. trans. La teologia dei primi pensatori greci, Firenze, La Nuova Italia, 1961).

    Google Scholar 

  • Jossa, G. (2011). Giudaismo ellenistico e cristianesimo ellenistico. In Bellia, G. and Garibba, D. (Eds.), L'ellenizzazione del cristianesimo dal I al II secolo. Atti del XIII Convegno di Studi Neotestamentari (pp. 15–26). Bologna: EDB.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jahn, T. (1987). Zum Wortfeld ‘Seele-Geist’ in der Sprache Homers. München: C.H.Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrs, K. (1964). De Aristarchi studiis homericis. Leipzig: Gebruder Bornträger, 18823 = Hildesheim, G. Olms.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matelli, E. (2004). Grammata didaskein a Rodi nel III-II sec. a.C.. In La cultura ellenistica. L’opera letteraria e l’esegesi antica. Atti del Convegno COFIN 2001 (pp. 307–325). Roma, Edizioni Quasar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matelli, E. (2011). In che senso si possa parlare di ‘sistema poetico’ secondo Aristotele. Rivista di Filosofia Neo-scolastica, 103, 419–450.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matelli, E. (2012a). Perché sia necessario parlare di retorica in senso sistemico. Rivista di Filosofia Neo-scolastica, 104, 725–754.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matelli, E (2012b). Prassifane. Testimonianze e frammenti. Filosofia e grammatica in età ellenistica. Milano: Vita e Pensiero (Pubblicazioni del Centro di Ricerche di Metafisica. Temi Metafisici e Problemi del Pensiero Antico).

    Google Scholar 

  • Meixner, U., & Newen, A. (Eds.). (2003). Seele, Denken, Bewusstsein. Zur Gesschichte der Philosophie des Geistes. Berlin-New York: Walter De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, M. F. (2008). Der Wandel des Psyche-Begriffs im frühgriechischen Denken von Homer bis Heraklit. Archiv für Begriffsgeschichte, 50, 9–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minati, G. (2013). Note di sintesi: novità, contributi, prospettive di ricerca dell’approccio sistemico. In L. Urbani Ulivi (Ed.), Strutture di mondo. Il pensiero sistemico come specchio di una realtà complessa (Vol. II, pp. 315–336). Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, G. (1986). Images of organization. Beverly Hills-Newbury Park, Cal.-London-New Dehli: Sage (Ital. trans. Images. Le metafore dell’organizzazione, Milano, Franco Angeli, 1989).

    Google Scholar 

  • Motte, A. (2003). § 13. Aristote, Rhétorique. In A. Motte, C. Rutten, & P. Somville (Eds.), Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote (pp. 539–549).

    Google Scholar 

  • Motte, A., Rutten, C., & Somville, P. (Eds.). (2003). Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote, Actes du colloque interuniversitaire de Liège, 29 et 30 mars 2001, travaux du Centre d’études aristotéliciennes de l’Université de Liège, Louvain-la-Neuve-Paris, Peeters.

    Google Scholar 

  • Movia, G. (Ed.). (2001). Aristotele, L’anima. Testo greco a fronte. Milano: Bompiani.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matelli, E (2012b). Prassifane. Testimonianze e frammenti. Filosofia e grammatica in età ellenistica. Milano: Vita e Pensiero (Pubblicazioni del Centro di Ricerche di Metafisica. Temi Metafisici e Problemi del Pensiero Antico).

    Google Scholar 

  • Mondin, B. (2001). Storia dell'antropologia filosofica. Dalle Origini fino a Vico. (Vol. I). Bologna: Edizioni Studio Domenicano.

    Google Scholar 

  • Onians, R. B. (1998). The Origins of European Thought about the Body, the Mind, the Soul, the World, Time and Fate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (Ital. trans. Le origini del pensiero europeo. Intorno al corpo, la mente, l’anima, il mondo, il tempo e il destino: nuove interpretazioni di materiali greci e romani, di altre testimonianze e di alcune fondamentali concezioni ebraiche e cristiane, Milano, Adelphi, 20112).

    Google Scholar 

  • Opsomer, J. (2003a). § 3. Aristote, Du Ciel. In A. Motte, C. Rutten, & P. Somville (Eds.), Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote (pp. 361–370).

    Google Scholar 

  • Opsomer, J. (2003b). § 4. Aristote, Météorologique. In A. Motte, C. Rutten, & P. Somville (Eds.), Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote (pp. 371–381).

    Google Scholar 

  • Opsomer, J. (2003c). § 8. Aristote, De l’Âme. In A. Motte, C. Rutten, & P. Somville (Eds.), Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote (pp. 441–458).

    Google Scholar 

  • Opsomer, J. (2003d). § 9. Aristote, Parva Naturalia. In A. Motte, C. Rutten, & P. Somville (Eds.), Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote (pp. 459–467).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostwald, M. (1969). Nomos and the beginnings of the Athenian democracy. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Otto, W. (1923). Die Manen oder von den Urformen des Totenglaubens. Eine Untersuchung zur Religion der Griechen, Römer und Semiten und zum Volksglauben überhaupt. Berlin: Verlag von Julius Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pubblicazioni del Centro di Ricerche di Metafisica.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitta, A. (2011). Sistemi argomentativi e topologie ellenistiche nelle lettere paoline. In Bellia, G. and Garibba, D. (Eds.), L'ellenizzazione del cristianesimo dal I al II secolo. Atti del XIII Convegno di Studi Neotestamentari (43-90). Bologna: EDB.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohde, E. (1921). Psyche: Seelencult und Unsterblichkeitsglaube der Griechen. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rutten, C. (2003a). § 15. Aristote, Fragments. In A. Motte, C. Rutten, & P. Somville (Eds.), Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote (pp. 555–574).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rutten, C. (2003b). § 14. Aristote, Poétique. In A. Motte, C. Rutten, & P. Somville (Eds.), Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote (pp. 551–554).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, A. (1990). Selbständigkeit und Abhängigkeit menschlichen Handelns bei Homer: hermeneutische Untersuchungen zur Psychologie Homers. Stuttgart: F. Steiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schütz, H. G., & Wibbing, S. (2010). melos, Glied (s.v.). In Theologisches Begriffslexikon zum neuen Testament (2nd Edition, pp. 1279–1280). Nördlingen: SCM R. Brockhaus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schweizer, E. (1981). “sôma” (s.v.), In F. Montagnini, G. Scarpat, & O. Soffritti (Eds.), Grande Lessico del Nuovo Testamento (Vol. 8, pp. 609–790). Brescia: Paideia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott, W. R. (1992). Organizations, rational, natural and open systems. Upper Saddle River, New Jersey: Prentice Hall Inc., A Pearson Education Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seron, D. (2003). § 1. Aristote, Organon. In A. Motte, C. Rutten, & P. Somville (Eds.), Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote (pp. 333–359).

    Google Scholar 

  • Sichkaryk, I. (2011). Corpo come punto focale nell’insegnamento paolino. Roma: Editrice Pontificia Università Gregoriana (Tesi Gregoriana, Teologia, 185).

    Google Scholar 

  • Snell, B. (1955). Die Entdeckung des Geistes. Studien zur Entstehung des europäischen Denkens bei den Griechen. Hamburg: Classen Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stevens, A. (2003a). § 10. Aristote, Métaphisique. In A. Motte, C. Rutten, & P. Somville (Eds.), Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote (pp. 469–496).

    Google Scholar 

  • Stevens, A. (2003b). § 16. Philosophie théorique: essai de conclusion sinthétique. In A. Motte, C. Rutten, & P. Somville (Eds.), Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote (pp. 577–582).

    Google Scholar 

  • Urso, C. (1997). Riferimenti anatomici nell’Iliade di Omero. Pathologica, 89(1), 26–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vancamp, B. (2003). § 7. Aristote, Partie des Animaux. In A. Motte, C. Rutten, & P. Somville (Eds.), Philosophie de la forme: “eidos”, “idea”, “morphè” dans la philosophie grecque des origines à Aristote (pp. 435–439).

    Google Scholar 

  • Vegetti, M. (1983). Metafora politica e immagine del corpo negli scritti ippocratici, in Formes de pensée dans la Collection hippocratique, In F. Lasserre & P. Mudry (Eds.). Actes du IVe Colloque International Hippocratique Lausanne, 21–26 septembre 1981 (pp. 459–469). Genève: Droz (Publ. Fac. Lettres Univ. de Lausanne XXVI), .

    Google Scholar 

  • Viagulamuthu, X. P. B. (2002). Offering our Bodies as a living Sacrifice to God. A Study in Pauline Spirituality Based on Romans 12.1. Roma: Editrice Pontificia Università Gregoriana (Tesi Gregoriana, Spiritualità, 7).

    Google Scholar 

  • Villani, G. (2010). La chimica: una scienza della complessità sistemica ante litteram. In L. Urbani Ulivi (Ed.), Strutture di mondo. Il pensiero sistemico come specchio di una realtà complessa (Vol. I, pp. 71–89). Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vivante, P. (1955). Sulla designazione del corpo in Omero. Archivio Glottologico Italiano, 40, 39–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wibbing, S. (2010). sôma, Körper, Leib (s.v.). In Theologisches Begriffslexikon zum neuen Testament (2nd Edition, pp. 1281–1285). Wuppertal, Brockhaus, Nördlingen: SCM R. Brockhaus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zavalloni, R. (1990). Linee di sviluppo nella concezione della “corporeità” umana. Antonianum, 65(2–3), 345–382.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elisabetta Matelli .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Matelli, E. (2019). The Living Body as a Model of Systemic Organization in Ancient Thinking. In: Urbani Ulivi, L. (eds) The Systemic Turn in Human and Natural Sciences. Contemporary Systems Thinking. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00725-6_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics