Skip to main content

Interim Period: Carnap Versus Popper

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 401))

  • 373 Accesses

Abstract

The “Vienna Circle” worded young Wittgenstein’s philosophy as the identification of language with the language of science. He had claimed to have solved the problem of induction. They had to respond to Popper’s new solution to it. They took his solution to be in the framework of Wittgenstein’s identification of language with the language of science, although Popper rejected it, as he followed the traditional view of the negation of a scientific theory as unscientific: this is a denial that science is closed under negation (as a language should be). Carnap and Hempel managed to ignore this fact. They then found it easy to prove Popper’s theory of science is inconsistent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    When Wittgenstein demanded of Popper to present a philosophical problem, he mentioned this problem; Wittgenstein dismissed it. Late in life Ayer 1982 , 18 disagreed: “For my own part, I think that if one were looking for a single phrase to capture the stage to which philosophy has progressed, ‘the study of evidence’ would be a better choice than ‘the study of language’.” Notice that Ayer did not say what philosophers should study; he only noted that philosophy has progressed in a direction that Wittgenstein said has its road forever closed. Why then did the problem of induction trouble so many of Wittgenstein self-proclaimed followers? I do not know. Young Wittgenstein did and Mature Wittgenstein did not discuss the problem of induction; he responded to Popper saying that the problem was not philosophical. As he said this in an awkward situation, it need not count.

  2. 2.

    Hintikka 1991 , 180, viewed Philosophical Investigation as an unreliable pastiche that reflects only the views of its editors. They were the literary executors of Wittgenstein. Hintikka called them derisively “Wittgenstein’s literary heirs”, among whom was his Doktorvater von Wright, whom he appreciated and who denied the view that Hintikka ascribed to him (Wright 1969 , 488).

  3. 3.

    Monk 1990 is the most popular life of Wittgenstein. It is defensive. This defensiveness is an insult to Wittgenstein’s memory.

  4. 4.

    In response to Popper’s solution to the problem of induction that rests on his view that there is no inductive method, a few Wittgenstein fans suggested – in the spirit of mature Wittgenstein – that only a general method does not exist; many detailed (local) ones do exist. This of course, is a true observation. As it is no solution to the problem of induction, it is a red herring.

  5. 5.

    This is my understanding. The only direct evidence on it that I have found goes against it. Hintikka 2006, 37, reports that Wittgenstein said to him, “… let me tell you – if I had come to a university when I was a young man and professors had been such fools as to not understand my ideas – I would not have been unhappy at all. That would have been a marvelous opportunity!” Hintikka added this: “I am not sure that Wittgenstein’s counterfactual was true, but it does illustrate the facet of his personality that has not received its due.”

  6. 6.

    This holds particularly for Ray Monk’s popular lives of Wittgenstein and of Russell.

  7. 7.

    The disagreement between Russell and Wittgenstein as to the possibility of the meta-language is irrelevant here: Russell ascribed to Wittgenstein the mystical view of the totality as ineffable, dismissing him as irrationalist. Incidentally, Wittgenstein’s refusal to recognize the meta-language is the view of the vernacular as an ideal-surrogate. Thus, Wittgenstein’s view is in conflict with the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis (Harvey 1963 , esp. 175). The literature is full of attempts to square them, which is easy, of course: already Maimonides used profusely the technique diffusing metaphysical assertions by considering them metaphorical.

  8. 8.

    Hintikka too praised Wittgenstein for his truth tables (Hintikka 2006, 35 ff.). Otherwise, Hintikka found Wittgenstein’s first book no more than gross errors and vague suggestions. Nevertheless, he considered him a “major thinker” in “the entire field of human thought” (Hintikka 1996, 7).

  9. 9.

    Landini 2007 describes this wavering in fascinating detail, but without saying that this is what he does.

  10. 10.

    It was a common practice in mid-century Oxford to finish an observation saying, Wittgenstein would not have approved of what I have just said and to take back the observation. This conduct won much appreciation as austere though it was no show of courage.

  11. 11.

    The idea that before criticizing an idea one should develop it and strengthen it and put it succinctly follow the traditions of Plato and of Galileo . It makes reading them and Russell enjoyable.

  12. 12.

    “When he finally came, instead of answering their questions about his book, he sat facing away from them reading Tagore, the Indian poet-novelist, for over an hour and then got up and silently left the room. Afterward Carnap remarked to Schlick , ‘I guess he is not one of us’.” Schlick’s response is not on record. His politicking still has adverse effect on the philosophical tradition; only the Heidegger scandal tops it. McGuinness 2002 , 189 reports Herbert Feigl’s explanation for Wittgenstein’s conduct; “he did not want to see their expressions as he read”. French 1993 presents it as an illustration of his view of life forms, no less.

  13. 13.

    Politically, Wittgenstein was a conservative (Hayes 2003 , 2; Vinten 2015 suggests philosophers should ignore this). The Romantic view of religion appealed to him as Engelmann’s memoir on him indicates; I suppose this is why he found Tolstoy appealing.

  14. 14.

    Griffiths 1991 ; Ayer 1936 , Ch. 4. Ayer recognizes the empirical part of ethics and then he decides that this is all that there is to ethics. Here he definitely disagreed with Wittgenstein. His subjectivist theory oddly conflicts with any case of akrasia (moral weakness): victims of kleptomania disapprove of the thefts that they fail to resist. More generally, emotivism fails to notice moral qualms and moral growth. More generally, the reduction of value to taste ignores comparative valuation.

  15. 15.

    TLP, §6.432. Already Maimonides deemed harmful superstitions all beliefs in divine interventions in the world – except for the miracles reported in Holy Writ.

  16. 16.

    Hempel , the last of the “Vienna Circle”, renounced verification (Linsky 1952 , 163–88), yet he approved of the dismissal of theology as meaningless. This renders the demand for verification a mere excuses, and (as Popper [1935] 1957 , §6 has observed early in the day) the epithet “meaningless” is a mere swearword.

  17. 17.

    This view of Einstein is problematic, yet it is the starting point of all serious philosophy of science. Hence, most active philosophers of science today do not count (Agassi 1995a) . Incidentally, Einstein endorsed Popper’s solution to the problem of induction; Russell did not.

  18. 18.

    TLP, §6.341. The best presentation of this view – conventionalism – still is that of Poincaré .

  19. 19.

    Regrettably, commentators on Wittgenstein ignore an original and interesting idea. Admitting the conventional character of the fit of facts and theory, Wittgenstein observed that this refutes the conventionalist view of theories as utterly uninformative. This is important.

  20. 20.

    Possibly references to the likes of Pears are unwise. In this chapter – on the reception of Wittgenstein – his case is an instance of the pervasive hero-worship. Biletzki 2003 , 194 agrees; Hacker 2001 , 1 does not.

  21. 21.

    Goethe used a better metaphor: “Hypotheses are only the pieces of scaffolding erected round a building during the course of construction, and taken away as soon as the edifice is completed.” Now the removal of the scaffolding is the proof of the hypothesis – that happens to be a false hope. The removal of the ladder is different. The difference between the meta-language and the object language includes the difference between mention and use, and Wittgenstein’s throwing away the ladder is then the loss of ability to mention words that he used! The limitation that TLP imposes is much wider than it looks: how can one write a history, say, of the rise of writing?

  22. 22.

    The medieval nominalism-realism dispute ended when Frege destroyed its basis, the reference theory of meaning. The sought-for alternative was – still is – realism with no Platonic Heaven and no Aristotelian definitions. This presentation is not quite adequate; I do not know how to improve it.

  23. 23.

    This is not the only way to avoid the paradoxes: there is the Zermelo-Fraenkel abstract set theory (ZF) and the von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory (NBG) and there is Quine’s modification of Russell’s theory. Russell was not pleased with any available solution, as he found all of them too artificial. Although he considered sets fictitious, he still wanted them intuitive, namely, quasi-natural.

  24. 24.

    For the argument for the impossibility of metaphysics to hold universally, it has to employ a general characterization of metaphysics and rules that hold in all languages. Wittgenstein’s hostility to “craving for generality” blocks this option. The ideal language obeys only general rules (Frege).

  25. 25.

    Black 1934 . Speaking of the standard wording of the verification principle, Linsky 1952, 6 says, “the vagueness and lack of precision in this formulation are obvious.” Since the “Vienna Circle” praised that principle for its securing clarity and precision, this observation condemns the “Vienna Circle” as not serious.

  26. 26.

    Not quite. Rorty does not ascribe to Popper a criterion of meaning but he still distorts Popper grossly as he describes (200, 135) Popper’s criterion of demarcation as “tracing the border between good science and bad metaphysics”. In his most ardent aloofness from metaphysics, Popper never said it was bad tout court.

  27. 27.

    This step is timely but insufficient: it invites assessment of contributions in oversight of biography. Alas, concerning Wittgenstein such assessments often rest on the ascription to him of old ideas, often Galileo’s picture of the way theory influences perception (Niiniluoto 1999, 115 ).

References

  • Agassi, J. (1995a). Contemporary philosophy of science as thinly masked antidemocratic apologetics. In Gavroglu, et al., pp. 153–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alam, R. (1990). Bertrand Russell’s logical atomism. New Delhi: Mittal.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A. J. (1936). Language, truth, and logic. Burwood: Royal Blind Society of New South Wales.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A. J. (1982). Philosophy in the twentieth century. London: Phoenix.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A. J. (1991). A. J. Ayer: Memorial essays (A. Phillips Griffiths, Ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biletzki, A. (2003). (Over) interpreting Wittgenstein. Dordrecht/Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Black, M. (1934). The principle of verifiability. Analysis, 2, 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Church, A. (1943). Reviews. Willard V. Quine. Notes on Existence and Necessity. The Journal of Philosophy, 40, 113–127 and the Journal of Symbolic Logic, 8, 45–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flew, A., & MacIntyre, A. C. (1955). New essays in philosophical theology. London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, P. A. (1993). Why did Wittgenstein read Tagore to the Vienna circle? ProtoSociology, 5, xxx.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacker, P. M. S. (2001). Wittgenstein: Connections and controversies. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, H. (1963). A reply to Dr Carney’s challenge. Philosophy, 38, 170–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayes, C. J. (2003). The grammar of politics: Wittgenstein and political philosophy. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1991). An impatient man and His papers. Synthese, 87, 183–201 (A shorter version appeared in The Times Literary Supplement 1990, p. 1030.).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1996). Ludwig Wittgenstein: Half-truths and one-and-a-half-truths. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (2006). Intellectual autobiography. In Auxier & Hahn, 2006, pp. 1–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landini, G. (2007). Wittgenstein’s apprenticeship with Russell. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Linsky, L. (Ed.). (1952). Semantics and the philosophy of language: A collection of readings. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGuinness, B. (2002). Approaches to Wittgenstein.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1999). Critical scientific realism. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. ([1935] 1959). The logic of scientific discovery. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1971). Autobiographical. In O. P. Wood, & G. Pitcher (Eds.), Ryle (Modern Studies in Philosophy). London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vinten, R. (2015). Was Wittgenstein a conservative philosopher? Revista Estudos Hum(e)anos. http://revista.estudoshumeanos.com/was-wittgenstein-a-conservative-philosopher-por-robert-vinten/

  • von Wright, G. H. (1969). Special supplement: The Wittgenstein papers. Philosophical Review, 78, 483–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1929). Some remarks on logical form. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary, 9, 162–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe Trans.). (Here labelled PI).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L ([1967] 2007). Lectures and conversations on aesthetics, psychology and religious beliefs. Compiled from notes taken down at the time by three of the students: Rush Rhees, Yorick Smythies, & James Taylor; edited by Cyril Barrett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1974). Letters to Russell, Keynes, and Moore. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Agassi, J. (2018). Interim Period: Carnap Versus Popper. In: Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. Synthese Library, vol 401. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00117-9_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics