Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 401))

  • 368 Accesses

Abstract

Extensionalism makes it possible to study logic independently of any theory of meaning. Frege’s logic was not fully extensional, however: he developed a theory of meaning in order to have classes uniquely determined. That theory is also flexible enough to allow statements of identity to be at times analytic, at times not. He rejected the traditional empiricist epistemology as an obstacle since it is psychologistic – even though he could not replace it. (A few years after Frege died Popper proposed the first non-psychologistic theory of science.)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    How developed is a field when it ceases to be a part of philosophy? This problem of demarcation differs from the one that Popper studied, though the two obviously overlap. Raising different problems of demarcation should appeal to analytic philosophers and perhaps it will when they will become serious again.

  2. 2.

    Wittgenstein rejected the Cartesian solutions the problem of induction and only hinted at an adequate solution to it. (Will 1974 elaborated on this passage.) Wittgenstein suggested that the framework for research is given and its very use solves the problem. It does not: researchers choose systems tentatively; if they improve them, they have to revise their questions and this they usually do.

  3. 3.

    Modern logic has no sign of affirmation akin to the sign of negation. Wittgenstein suggested that each sentence should have yes/no rubrics – to tick off at most one of them.

  4. 4.

    An example is Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, Preface to the first edition: “In this sphere of thought, opinion is perfectly inadmissible, and … everything which bears the least semblance of a hypothesis must be excluded, as of no value in such discussions. For it is a necessary condition of every cognition that is to be established upon a priori grounds that it shall be held to be absolutely necessary …”

  5. 5.

    Ramsey’s review of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus declares this obscure. Russell clarified it; the more formal/exact a text is, the more important is the preliminary introduction to it. This is the ladder to throw away. Russell considered this invitation to dogmatism: as preliminaries are pre-critical, Wittgenstein considered them immune to criticism. Oddly, Russell criticized Wittgenstein for his habit of applying forceful criticism in preliminary stages of research. This may be explicable by the ascription (McCutcheon 2001, Ch. 1) to Wittgenstein stress on preliminaries as the fervent pursuit of perspicuity (of achieving clarity through preliminary stages). As the concern of McCutcheon was with religion, she examined Wittgenstein’s early attention to the central role he ascribed to preliminaries both in formal mathematics and in studies of miracles. This is a coincidence at best, to impress only the superstitious.

  6. 6.

    It often is a tautology, observes Bar-Am 2008 , 47 et passim; not if it means mediaeval London is modern London: this is intuitively true but not tautologically so. This is hardly ordinary language, though. “I am the Lord your Lord” (Exodus 20:2) is more like it.

  7. 7.

    Tarski [1936] 1941 , §19 shows that identity sign is synthetic: (x) (y) (x = y) is true of an empty universe and of one that contains only one object but not otherwise. This does not hold for the identity sign in the sentence “Tullius = Cicero ”, of course.

  8. 8.

    In Leibniz idea of his ideal language essences reign supreme, so the name “Caesar ” includes all the characteristics of Caesar, so that understanding it amounts to knowing all about him. The literature on Wittgenstein ignores this, which is strange; so does the literature on Russell, which is not strange.

  9. 9.

    The logical connection is obvious between diverse theses on the limits of natural languages considered formal: The Tarski-Quine no analytic-synthetic dichotomy, the Duhem-Quine limited inter-translatability thesis and the Bar-Hillel-Catford no-full-machine-translatability thesis. Perhaps it is only the Duhem-Quine no-complete-refutability-in-isolation thesis that is slightly less direct and less obvious. All these impossibilities are due to viewing the informal formally; informally, all of these theses are obvious. We obviously agree to tolerate some (hopefully small) imperfections. See Agassi 2014 Ch. 6 .

  10. 10.

    The model standard introductory logic course seems to me to be the deceptively introductory high-powered text of Hilbert and Ackermann, 1928 .

  11. 11.

    See Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Art. Lakatos .

  12. 12.

    Despite all this, Wittgenstein declared he owed more to Frege than to Russell.

References

  • Agassi, J. (2014). Popper and his popular critics: Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend, Imre Lakatos. Cham/New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Am, N. (2008). Extensionalism: The revolution in logic.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, D. (1979). frege’s theory of judgement. Oxford/New York: Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, M. (1971). A companion to Wittgenstein’s tractatus. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broekman, J. M. (2016). Meaning, narrativity, and the real. Cham: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1973). Frege: Philosophy of language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D., & Ackermann, W. (1928). Grundzüge der theoretischen Logik.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1976). A puzzle about belief. In Margalit 1976, pp. 239–283.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linsky, L. (1967). Referring. New York: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCutcheon, F. (2001). Religion within the limits of language alone: Wittgenstein on philosophy and religion. Florence: Taylor and Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, A. ([1902] 1983). On assumptions. Berkeley: University of California Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1912). Problems of philosophy. New York: H. Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1940). An inquiry into meaning & truth. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. ([1936] 1941). Introduction to logic and to the methodology of deductive sciences. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, J. (1957a). Between analytic and empirical. Philosophy, 32, 112–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wettersten, J. R. (1995). Preliminary report on efforts of Psychologism to gain influence in proper epistemological, methodological and psychological societies. In Jarvie & Laor, 1995, pp. 129–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wettersten, J. R. (2005). Whewell’s critics: Have they prevented him from doing good? Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Will, F. L. (1974). Induction and justification: Investigation of Cartesian procedures in the philosophy of knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (1980). Wittgenstein on the foundations of mathematics. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Agassi, J. (2018). Frege. In: Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. Synthese Library, vol 401. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00117-9_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics